Skip to main content
Log in

My Self-as-Philosopher and My Self-as-Scientist Meet to do Research in the Classroom: Some Davidsonian Notes on the Philosophy of Educational Research

  • Published:
Studies in Philosophy and Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Traditionally, philosophical inquiry into pedagogical issues has occurred far from the classrooms in which pedagogy materialises. However, an organised form of inquiry into issues of a normative nature (about what ought to be done pedagogically) and of an analytic nature (about the meaning of pedagogical concepts), making use of ideas obtained in an empirical way in classroom and classroom-related situations, is both feasible and desirable. About desirability, this form of inquiry depends on the particularities of the local situations, and that helps to take them into account when deciding on how to improve pedagogical practice. That is, it contextualises pedagogical decisions. About feasibility for normative issues, an analysis based on Donald Davidson’s philosophy of language shows that there is nothing that compels empirical observations to be descriptive and to not be normative. And normative occasional beliefs acquired empirically can serve as a general confrontation or testing field for ideas about the justification of pedagogical actions or strategies. About feasibility for analytic issues, as a consequence of giving up the analytic–synthetic distinction it is argued that they can also be explored by means of occasional beliefs acquired empirically, when confronted with the implications of the definition of any pedagogical concept.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In the literature, the expression ‘what works?’ has sometimes been associated with experimental or quasi-experimental types of research (Slavin 2002; Olson 2004). Nevertheless, I think that this expression also describes appropriately what is important for other alternative research approaches whose methods do not resemble those of the natural sciences, and in which teachers’ and administrators’ learning about what works may be a main result sought after—even if that learning is not or cannot be translated into formal theories.

  2. I will not, however, deal with the difficult issue of how causal conclusions can be derived from empirical observations. That is beyond the scope of this paper.

  3. The idea of ‘testing’ should be taken here in a broad sense, and not necessarily as a process leading to a full confirmation (proof) or refutation of some hypothesis.

  4. If the analytic–synthetic distinction could be drawn, then it might be possible to find a (limited) number of analytic sentences that define the meaning of any one sentence or word. To understand any sentence or a word would be to understand the set of sentences that define its meaning.

  5. Given the above discussion about Quine’s rejection of the analytic–synthetic distinction, the expression ‘analytic questions’ may be unfortunate. Nevertheless, I use it here for convenience, but without trying to establish any clearcut distinction with other questions. The borders are fuzzy. Analytic questions would be those that, in Rorty’s terminology, would tend to be answered more by looking them up in a dictionary rather than in an encyclopaedia (Rorty 1991). Quine warns us against taking too seriously this distinction between dictionaries and encyclopaedias.

  6. Interpretation requires that the charity principle be observed. According to it, any interpreter has to grant truth to a great many of any speaker’s beliefs, if she will be able to interpret any sentence that the speaker asserts, true or false. ‘Disagreement and agreement alike are intelligible only against a background of massive agreement’ (Davidson 1973, p. 137). This is not a practical suggestion to make interpretation easier; it is rather an essential principle for meaning and language to make sense at all (Ramberg 1989).

References

  • Bible, New International Version. Retrieved August 2006 from http://www.biblegateway.com/

  • Bridges, D. (2003). Fiction written under oath? Essays in philosophy and educational research. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1967). Truth and meaning. In Inquiries into truth and interpretation (pp. 17–36). Clarendon: Oxford.

  • Davidson, D. (1973). Radical interpretation. In Inquiries into truth and interpretation (pp. 126–139). Clarendon: Oxford.

  • Davidson, D. (1974). On the very idea of a conceptual scheme. In Inquiries into truth and interpretation (pp. 183–198). Clarendon: Oxford.

  • Davidson, D. (1988). The myth of the subjective. In M. Krauzs (Ed.), Relativism: Interpretation and confrontation (pp. 159–172). Notre Dame: Univ of Notre Dame.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1990). The structure and content of truth. Journal of Philosophy, 87(6), 279–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1994). The objectivity of values. In C. Gutiérrez (Ed.), El trabajo filosófico en el continente hoy (pp. 59–69). Bogotá: ABC.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hargreaves, D. (1997). In defence of research for evidence-based teaching. British Educational Research Journal, 23(4), 405–419.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaestle, C. (1993). The awful reputation of educational research. Educational Researcher, 22(1), 23–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, J. (2004). Causal explanation, qualitative research, and scientific inquiry in education. Educational Researcher, 33(2), 3–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, D. (2004). The triumph of hope over experience in the search for ‘what works’: A response to Slavin. Educational Researcher, 33(1), 24–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D. (2005). The contested nature of empirical educational research (and why philosophy of education offers little help). (Paper presented at the 40th annual conference of the philosophy of education society of Great Britain, Oxford. Retrieved October 2006 from http://k1.ioe.ac.uk/pesgb/x/Phillips.pdf).

  • Quine, W. (1953). Two dogmas of empiricism. In From a logical point of view: Nine logico-philosophical essays (pp. 20–46). Cambridge: Harvard University.

  • Quine, W. (1969). Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramberg, B. (1989). Donald Davidson’s philosophy of language: An introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1979). Philosophy and the mirror of nature. Princeton: Princeton University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. (1991). Objectivity, relativism and truth. Cambridge: Cambridge University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Cambridge: Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slavin, R. (2002). Evidence-based educational policies: Transforming educational practice and research. Educational Researcher, 31(7), 15–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, G. (1997). What’s the use of theory? Harvard Educational Review, 67(1), 75–104.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Andrés Mejía D..

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mejía D., A. My Self-as-Philosopher and My Self-as-Scientist Meet to do Research in the Classroom: Some Davidsonian Notes on the Philosophy of Educational Research. Stud Philos Educ 27, 161–171 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-007-9096-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11217-007-9096-5

Keywords

Navigation