Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

An Axiomatic Approach to the Measurement of Comparative Female Disadvantage

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Social Indicators Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Female comparative disadvantage refers to the mismatch of the female with respect to achievements in different dimensions of human well-being in comparison with the corresponding achievements of the male. This paper axiomatically derives a general family of female comparative disadvantage indicators which has very important policy implications. The axioms employed are shown to be ‘independent’. An empirical illustration of the general index is provided using the UNDP data on mean years of schooling, life expectancy at birth and gross national income per capita in 2018. Results show that female comparative disadvantage is not necessarily related to standard measures of human development, such as the HDI, and is present even in countries reaching very high human development. The factor where policy intervention is needed the most is income.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The strong version of the poverty axiom was considered also by Tsui (2002).

  2. Ravallion (2012) made an excellent discussion along this line.

References

  • Alkire, S., & Foster, J. E. (2011). Counting and multidimensional poverty measurement. Journal of Public Economics, 95, 476–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alkire, S., Foster, J., Seth, S., Santos, M. E., Roche, J. M., & Ballon, P. (2015). Multidimensional poverty measurement and analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anand, S. (2018). Recasting human development measures. Discussion Paper, UNDP.

  • Anand, S., & Sen, A. (1995). Gender inequality in human development: Theories and measurement. In UNDP, Background papers: Human Development Report1995, United Nations Development Programme, New York, 1996, pp. 1–19. [Previously published in August 1995 as HDRO Occasional Paper 19 for Human Development Report 1995.]

  • Bourguignon, F., & Chakravarty, S. R. (2003). The measurement of multidimensional poverty. Journal of Economic Inequality, 1, 25–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravarty, S. R. (1983). A new index of poverty. Mathematical Social Sciences, 6, 307–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravarty, S. R. (2003). A generalized human development index. Review of Development Economics, 7, 99–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravarty, S. R. (2011). A reconsideration of the tradeoffs in the new human development index. Journal of Economic Inequality, 9, 471–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravarty, S. R. (2018). Analyzing multidimensional wellbeing: A quantitative approach. Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Decancq, K., & Lugo, M. A. (2012). Inequality of well-being: A multidimensional approach. Economica, 79, 721–746.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dijkstra, A. G., & Hanmer, L. C. (2000). Measuring socio-economic gender inequality: Toward an alternative to the UNDP gender-related development index. Feminist Economics, 6, 41–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Foster, J. E., Greer, J., & Thorbecke, E. (1984). A class of decomposable poverty measures. Econometrica, 42, 761–766.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gajdos, T., & Weymark, J. A. (2005). Multidimensional generalized Gini indices. Economic Theory, 26, 471–496.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, J. L. W. V. (1906). Sur les fonctions convexes et les inégalités entre les valeurs moyennes. Acta Mathematica, 30, 175–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kakwani, N. C. (1980). On a class of poverty measures. Econometrica, 48, 437–444.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klasen, S., & Schüler, D. (2011). Reforming the gender-related index and the gender empowerment measure: Implementing some specific proposals. Feminist Economics, 17, 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolm, S. C. (1977). Multidimensional egalitarianism. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 91, 1–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lasso de la Vega, M. C., & Urrutia, A. M. (2012). A note on multidimensional distribution-sensitive poverty axioms. Research on Economic Inequality, 20, 161–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niculescu, C. P., & Persson, L.-E. (2006). Convex functions on intervals. In Convex functions and their applications: A contemporary approach, CMSBM (pp. 7–64). Springer.

  • Permanyer, I. (2010). The measurement of multidimensional gender inequality: Continuing the debate. Social Indicators Research, 95, 181–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Permanyer, I. (2013). A critical assessment of the UNDP’s gender inequality index. Feminist Economics, 19, 1–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ponthieux, S., & Meurs, D. (2015). Gender inequality. In A. B. Atkinson & F. Bourguignon (Eds.), Handbook of income distribution (Vol. 2, pp. 981–1146). Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ravallion, M. (2012). Troubling tradeoffs in the human development index. Journal of Development Economics, 99, 201–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schüler, D. (2006). The uses and misuses of the gender-related development index and gender empowerment measure: A review of the literature. Journal of Human Development, 7, 161–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (1976). Poverty: An ordinal approach to measurement. Econometrica, 44, 219–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stiglitz, J. E., Sen, A., & Fitoussi, J.-P. (2009). Report by the commission on the measurement of economic performance and social progress. CMEPSP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsui, K.-Y. (1998). Multidimensional inequality and multidimensional generalized entropy measures: An axiomatic derivation. Social Choice and Welfare, 16, 145–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsui, K.-Y. (2002). Multidimensional poverty indices. Social Choice and Welfare, 19, 69–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • UNDP. (2010). Human development report 2010—20th anniversary edition. The real wealth of nations: pathways to human development. United Nations Development Programme.

    Google Scholar 

  • UNDP. (2015). Human development report. United Nations Development Programme.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Milorad Kovacevic for directing us to the UNDP indicator’s webpages. We also thank Liyousew Borga for research assistance. We also thank two anonymous reviewers for many helpful suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Conchita D’Ambrosio.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Theorem 1

In view of the strong focus axiom, for any \(d \in N\), we can restrict attention on the censored profile \(z^{*} = \left( {z_{1}^{ * } ,z_{2}^{ * } ,\ldots z_{d}^{ * } } \right)\). By applying the factor decomposability postulate to the profile \(z^{ * }\), we get \(F\left( z \right) = \sum\nolimits_{i = 1}^{d} {w_{i} } f\left( {z_{i}^{ * } } \right)\), where \(f\left( {z_{i}^{ * } } \right) = F\left( {z_{i}^{ * } } \right)\,,\)\(1 \le i \le d\),\(f:\Re_{ + }^{1} \to \Re_{ + }^{1} .\) Continuity of \(F\) ensures that \(f\) is continuous over its domain. In view of the normalization axiom, \(f\left( 0 \right) = 0\) and \(f\left( 1 \right) = 1\).

The proof of strict convexity of \(f\) over \(\left[ {0,1} \right]\) relies on the following theorem of Jensen (1906): Let \(g:I \to \Re^{1}\) be a continuous function, \(I\) being a non-degenerate interval in the set of real numbers \(\Re^{1}\). Then \(g\) is strictly convex if and only if it is midpoint strictly convex, that is, for arbitrary \(p \ne q \in I\), \(g\left( {\frac{p + q}{2}} \right) < \frac{g\left( p \right) + g\left( q \right)}{2}\). (See Niculescu & Persson, 2006, p.10.)

Now, for \(t \in \left[ {0,1} \right]\), choose \(c > 0\) such that \(u\left( { = t - c} \right),v\left( { = u - c} \right) \in \left[ {0,\;1} \right]\). Aggravation sensitivity implies that

$$f\left( v \right) - f\left( u \right) > f\left( u \right) - f\left( t \right).$$
(12)

Note that \(u = \frac{v + t}{2}\). Hence we can rewrite inequality (12) as

$$f\left( {\frac{t + v}{{2}}} \right) < \frac{f\left( t \right) + f\left( v \right)}{{2}}.$$
(13)

Since \(t,v \in \left[ {{0,}\;{1}} \right]\) are arbitrary (as \(c > 0\) is arbitrary), inequality (13) establishes mid-point strict convexity of \(f\). This combined with continuity of \(f\) over \(\left[ {0,\;1} \right]\) demonstrates that \(f\) fulfills the desired strict convexity property. This establishes the necessity part of the theorem. The sufficiency part is easy to verify. \(\Delta\).

Proof of Proposition 1

Given \(g\left( 0 \right) = 1\) and \(g\left( 1 \right) = 0\), by strict convexity of \(g\),\(g\left( {\left( {1 - \theta } \right)} \right) = g\left( {\theta .0 + \left( {1 - \theta } \right).1} \right) < \theta g\left( 0 \right) + \left( {1 - \theta } \right)g\left( 1 \right) = \theta\), where \(0 < \theta < 1\) is arbitrary. Hence for any \(0 < u < 1\), \(g\left( u \right) < \left( {1 - u} \right)\) which implies that \(g\left( u \right)\) is decreasing at 0. Next, strict convexity of \(g\) also implies that \(g\left( u \right) > 0\) for all \(0 < u < 1\). Otherwise, suppose for some \(0 < t < 1\,,\) \(g\left( t \right) = 0\). Then, given \(g\left( 1 \right) = 0\), by strict convexity of \(g\), \(g\left( {\theta .t + \left( {1 - \theta } \right).1} \right) < \theta g\left( t \right) + \left( {1 - \theta } \right)g\left( 1 \right) = 0\,,\) where \(0 < \theta < 1\). This inequality holds only if \(g\left( {\theta .t + \left( {1 - \theta } \right).1} \right) < 0\), which is a contradiction to the assumption that \(g\) is non-negative valued. Now, if \(g\) is not strictly decreasing, then there exist at least three points \(0 < t_{1} < t_{2} < t_{3} < 1\) such that \(g\left( {t_{1} } \right) > g\left( {t_{2} } \right) > 0\) and \(g\left( {t_{2} } \right) < g\left( {t_{3} } \right) > 0\). By construction and by convexity of \(\left[ {0,1} \right]\), we can get \(0 < \delta < 1\) such that \(t_{3} = \delta .t_{2} + \left( {1 - \delta } \right).1\). Then by strict convexity of \(g\), \(g\left( {t_{2} } \right) < g\left( {t_{3} } \right) =\)\(g\left( {\delta .t_{2} + \left( {1 - \delta } \right).1} \right) < \delta g\left( {t_{2} } \right) + \left( {1 - \delta } \right)g\left( 1 \right) = \delta g\left( {t_{2} } \right)\), a contradiction. Since \(g\left( 1 \right) = 0,\) it then follows that \(g\) is strictly decreasing over \(\left[ {0,1} \right]\). This completes the proof of the proposition.\(\Delta\).

Proof of Theorem 2: Since in (2) the weights \(w_{i} \ge 0\) obeying the restriction \(\sum\nolimits_{i = 1}^{d} {w_{i} } = 1\), can be chosen arbitrarily for identifying a functional form that violates a particular postulate, in each part of the demonstration of the independence theorem, we can choose \(w_{i} = \frac{1}{d}\) for all \(i \in Q\,.\)

(A) Consider the female disadvantage index given by

$$F_{1} \left( {z\,} \right) = \frac{1}{d}\left[ {\sum\limits_{{z_{i} < 1}} {\left( {1 - z_{i} } \right)}^{2} + \sum\limits_{{z_{i} \ge 1}} {\left( {\frac{{z_{i} - 1}}{{z_{i} + 1}}} \right)} } \right],$$
(14)

where \(z \in \Re_{ + }^{d}\) is such that for at least one \(i \in \left\{ {1,2,\ldots,d} \right\}\),\(\,z_{i} > 1\) holds. Given such an FMA ratio profile \(z\) with \(\,z_{i} > 1\) choose \(\,c > 0\) so that \(\left( {\,z_{i} - c} \right) > 1\). Given this \(z\), define \(y \in \Re_{ + }^{d}\) as follows: \(y_{i} = \left( {z_{i} - c} \right) > 1\) and \(y_{k} = z_{k}\) for all \(k \in \left\{ {1,2,\ldots,d} \right\}/\left\{ k \right\}\). It is easy to verify that \(F_{1} \left( {y\,} \right) < F_{1} \left( {z\,} \right)\), which demonstrates violation of the strong focus axiom because of its dependence on FMA ratios that are greater than 1. However, \(F_{1}\) fulfills the aggravation sensitivity, factor decomposability, normalization and continuity axioms.

(B) Because of linearity in \(z_{i}^{ * }\) values, the Dijkstra–Hanmer index \(F_{2} \left( {z\,} \right) = \frac{1}{d}\sum\nolimits_{i = 1}^{d} {\left( {1 - z_{i}^{ * } } \right)} ,\) where \(z \in \Re_{ + }^{d}\), is not aggravation sensitive, although it is strongly focused, factor decomposable, normalized and continuous.

(C) For any \(z \in \Re_{ + }^{d}\), let \(\hat{z}^{*}\) be the censored FMA ratio profile associated with the non-increasingly ordered permutation of \(z\), that is,\(z_{1} \le z_{2} \le \cdots \le z_{d}\) so that \(\left( {1 - \hat{z}_{1}^{ * } } \right) \ge \left( {1 - \hat{z}_{2}^{ * } } \right) \ge \cdots \ge \left( {1 - \hat{z}_{d}^{ * } } \right)\). Then for any \(z \in \Re_{ + }^{d}\), the index \(F_{3} \left( {z\,} \right) = \frac{1}{{d^{2} }}\sum\nolimits_{i = 1}^{d} {\left( {2i - 1} \right)\left( {1 - \hat{z}_{i}^{ * } } \right)}\) that employs Gini-type aggregation is a transgressor of the factor decomposability postulate since it is a rank ordered weighted average of \(\left( {1 - \hat{z}_{i}^{ * } } \right)\) ratio values where the weights themselves are dependent of the entire distribution of ratios. However, \(F_{3}\) is an abider of the all the remaining four axioms considered in the theorem statement.

(D) For any \(z \in \Re_{ + }^{d}\), the sum \(F_{4} \left( {z\,} \right) = \sum\nolimits_{i = 1}^{d} {\left( {1 - z_{i}^{ * } } \right)^{2} }\) of squared deviations of \(z_{i}^{ * }\) from unity is a violator of part (ii) of the normalization postulate. (Note that since the normalization principle consists of two separate parts, violation of one part should serve our purpose.) Evidently, \(F_{4}\) is aggravation sensitive, strongly focused, factor decomposable and continuous.

(E) Consider the following form of the disadvantaged index

$$F_{5} \left( {z\,} \right) = \left\{ {\begin{array}{*{20}l} {\frac{1}{d}\frac{1}{2}\sum\limits_{i = 1}^{n} {\left( {1 - z_{i}^{ * } } \right)^{2} } } \hfill & {if\,\,z \ne 01^{n} } \hfill \\ 1 \hfill & {if\,\,\,z = 01^{n} .} \hfill \\ \end{array} } \right.$$
(15)

where \(z = 01^{n}\) is the n-coordinated vector of zeroes and \(z \ne 01^{n}\) means that at least one coordinate of z is non-zero. Evidently, \(F_{5}\) is discontinuous at \(z = 01^{n}\). However, it is strongly focused, aggravation sensitive, factor decomposable and normalized. This completes the proof of the theorem.\(\Delta\).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Chakravarty, S.R., Chattopadhyay, N. & D’Ambrosio, C. An Axiomatic Approach to the Measurement of Comparative Female Disadvantage. Soc Indic Res 164, 747–772 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11205-022-02970-1

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11205-022-02970-1

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation