Skip to main content
Log in

A Pilot Study of a Cultural-Historical Approach to Teaching Geometry

  • Published:
Science & Education Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There appears to be a widespread assumption that deductive geometry is inappropriate for most learners and that they are incapable of engaging with the abstract and rule-governed intellectual processes that became the world’s first fully developed and comprehensive formalised system of thought. This article discusses a curriculum initiative that aims to ‘bring to life’ the major transformative (primary) events in the history of Greek geometry, aims to encourage a meta-discourse that can develop a reflective consciousness and aims to provide an opportunity for the induction into the formalities of proof and to engage with the abstract. The results of a pilot study to see whether 14–15 year old ‘mixed ability’ and 15–16 year old ‘gifted and talented’ students can be meaningfully engaged with two such transformative events are discussed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The Elements have been criticised for its lack of rigour (e.g. Russell 1971; Wilder 1981) and may not compare with the rigours of the axiomatics of today (volumes 1–6 of the Elements relies on the diagram for proof which compares rather unfavourable with a formalism that does not rely on diagrams), but pedagogically it serves as an exercise in deductive reasoning. The historical reason for teaching the Elements was that it taught people how to reason. It is interesting to note that Hartshorne (2000) teaches Greek deductive geometry to his mathematics undergraduates before teaching the axiomatics of university mathematics.

  2. Much of this is still speculation as we can only go by Eudemus’ and Proclus’s account of the origins of Greek mathematics. Indeed, Netz (1999) goes so far as to state that there is no hard evidence that Greek mathematics as we know it pre-dates Socrates. Given the destruction of the library at Alexandra and the possible destruction of 99% of all Greek literature, this issue may never be resolved. However, the burning question that remains to be answered is how the Greeks transformed an empirical craft into a science of reason? The period of that transformation is certainly pre-Socratic and at least we have Proclus and Eudemus to go by. Although historically spurious, they can serve to justify the speculation in an educational context.

  3. The following is speculation, but there is reason to suppose Solon, the elected head of state of Athens, actually met and conversed with Thales. If so, then the rule of law as governed by principle (as opposed to the dictate of kings) to which the law applies equally to all subjects, has been influenced by the principles of geometry. That Solon may have met Thales and in Egypt should be mentioned in the classroom in order to show the impact of geometry to other domains such as law (however, whether Thales was actually alone in creating abstract geometry is an historical point best left for the university rather than a point of heritage for the secondary classroom).

  4. Despite the ancient Greek historians attributing proof to Thales, it is unlikely that he developed formal proof and perhaps went no further than cutting out templates to demonstrate opposite angles are equal. Experience from school visits have shown that novice 12 year-old-students may well generate the same kind of demonstration, which means they are on the right path to understanding how the method of proof developed. The essential point is if we took them back to that historical moment and immerse them in the relevant problem space then we can guide the transformation of their understanding as that primary event unfolds.

  5. Such a blanket claim presupposes a contextual domain, in this case plane geometry, but the point here is that, for Plato, a ‘necessary truth’ is fundamentally different to opinion or the dictate of authority.

References

  • Carson R, Rowlands S (2007a) Strategies for affecting the necessary course of cognitive growth as an integral part of curricular and instructional planning. Interchange 38(2):137–165

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carson R, Rowlands S (2007b) Teaching the conceptual revolutions in geometry. Sci Edu 16(9–10):921–954

    Google Scholar 

  • Cuomo S (2001) Ancient mathematics. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis JP, Hersh R (1981) The mathematical experience. Penguin, Harmondsworth

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Doren C (1991) A history of knowledge: the pivotal events, people, and achievements of world history. Ballantine, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Egan K (1997) The educated mind: how cultural tools shape our understanding. The University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Fauvel J, van Maanen J (2000) History in mathematics education, the ICMI study. Kluwer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Grattan-Guinness I (2004) The Mathematics of the past: distinguishing its history from our heritage. Hist Math 31(2):163–185

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gulikers I, Blom K (2001) A historical angle: a survey of recent literature on the use and value of history in geometrical education. Educ Stud Math 47:223–258

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartshorne R (2000) Teaching geometry according to Euclid. Notices AMS 47(4)

  • Hershkowitz R, Schwarz BB, Dreyfus T (2001) Abstraction in context: epistemic actions. J Res Math Educ 32(20):195–222

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jones K, Fujita T (2003) The place of experimental tasks in geometry teaching: learning from the textbook designs of the early 20th century. In: Pope S, McNamara O (eds) Research in mathematics education, papers of the british society for research into learning mathematics, vol 5. BSRLM, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Kline M (1982) Mathematics in Western Culture. Penguin, Harmondsworth

  • Küchemann D, Hoyles C (2006) Secondary school pupils’ approaches to proof-related tasks in geometry. In: British society for research into learning mathematics day conference, University of Warwick, 25th February 2006 BSRLM informal proceedings, vol 26(1), pp 53–58

  • Mathematics Association (1923) The teaching of geometry in schools. G. Bell & Sons, London

  • Mathematics Association (1939) A second report on the teaching of geometry in schools. G. Bell & Sons, London

  • Netz R (1999) The shaping of deduction in greek mathematics: a study in cognitive history. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget J (1977/1952) Logic and psychology. In: Gruber HE, Vonèche JJ (eds) The essential Piaget. Basic Books, New York

  • Radford L (2008) Culture and cognition: towards an anthropology of mathematical thinking. In: English L (ed) Handbook of international research in mathematics education, 2nd edn. Routledge, Taylor and Francis, New York, pp 439–464

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands S, Davies A (2006) Mathematics masterclass: is mathematics invented or discovered? Mathematics in Schools. Math Assoc 35(2):2–6

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell B (1971) ‘The teaching of Euclid’ reprinted from Mathematical Gazette 2(33) 1902. Math Gaz 55(392):143–145

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith Report (2004) Making mathematics count: the report of Professor Adrian Smith’s inquiry into post-14 mathematics education. Printed by the stationary office

  • Tall D, Vinner S (1981) Concept image and concept definition in mathematics with particular reference to limits and continuity. Educ Stud Math 12:151–169

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilder RL (1981) Mathematics as a cultural system. Pergamon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stuart Rowlands.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Rowlands, S. A Pilot Study of a Cultural-Historical Approach to Teaching Geometry. Sci & Educ 19, 55–73 (2010). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-008-9181-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11191-008-9181-3

Keywords

Navigation