Skip to main content
Log in

The impact of statistical learning on violations of the sure-thing principle

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

    We’re sorry, something doesn't seem to be working properly.

    Please try refreshing the page. If that doesn't work, please contact support so we can address the problem.

A Publisher's Erratum to this article was published on 01 April 2015

Abstract

This paper experimentally tests whether violations of Savage’s (1954) sure-thing principle (STP) decrease through statistical learning. Our subjects repeatedly had to bet on the drawings from an urn with an unknown proportion of differently colored balls. The control group was thereby subjected to learning through mere thought only. In addition, the test group received more and more statistical information over the course of the experiment by observing the color of the ball actually drawn after each bet. We expected that statistical learning would decrease the decision makers’ ambiguity, thereby implying a stronger decrease of STP violations in the test than in the control group. However, our data surprisingly shows that learning by mere thought rather than statistical learning leads to a decrease in STP violations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for example, Allais (1979), Wu and Gonzalez (1996), Starmer (2000), Schmidt (2004), and Sugden (2004), and references therein.

  2. Somewhat loosely, we speak of “ambiguity” whenever a decision maker cannot comprehensively resolve all his uncertainty through a unique additive — either subjective or objective — probability measure.

  3. Note that there exist alternative theoretical models of Bayesian learning under ambiguity in which statistical learning does not necessarily reduce the decision maker’s ambiguity (cf., e.g. Epstein and Schneider 2007; Zimper and Ludwig 2009; Zimper 2011, 2013). Roughly speaking, in these models ambiguity is, in contrast to Marinacci’s (2002) formal argument, not restricted to the parameter-values in question but it also concerns the joint objective probabilities of these parameter-values and the data sample, i.e. the updating process.

  4. Note that the existing axiomatizations of ambiguity attitudes within the Anscombe and Aumann (1963) framework (e.g. Schmeidler 1989; Gilboa and Schmeidler 1989; Ghirardato et al. 2004) only allow for violations of the STP but not for violations of the IA whenever an ambiguous decision situation reduces to a risky decision situation.

  5. While we fixed the worst payoff x at zero, the second best payoff y was in the range of R40 to R80, and the best payoff z was in the range of R75 to R150. The Supplementary Appendix lists the questionnnaire containing all 30 questions.

  6. Compared to the OLS regression, the IRLS regression produces ‘robust’ estimates in the sense that it accounts for and reduces the influence of extreme observations (observations with large residuals).

  7. Note that there is no β 1 coefficient for the fixed effects logit since the dummy variable, D, representing whether an individual is in the test or control group, is fixed over rounds and is thus dropped from the regression.

  8. If f only takes on finitely many, say m, values, we have where E 1,...,E m denotes the unique partition of S with u(f(s 1))>...>u(f(s m )) for s i E i (cf. Schmeidler 1986).

  9. ν is globally concave (resp. convex) if, and only if, it satisfies for all events E,E

  10. For a more detailed discussion of the relationship between converging Bayesian learning and Doob’s consistency theorem see, e.g. Diaconis and Freedman (1986), Chapter 1 in Gosh and Ramamoorthi (2003), Lijoi et al. (2004), or Chapter 4 in Zimper (2013). For converging statistical learning in the case of ambiguous priors see Marinacci (2002).

  11. We assume that the standard principle of reduction of compound lotteries applies (cf., e.g. Fishburn 1988).

References

  • Abdellaoui, M., Baillon, A., Placido, L., & Wakker, P.P. (2011). The rich domain of uncertainty: source functions and their experimental implementation. American Economic Review, 101, 695–723.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allais, M. (1979). The foundation of a positive theory of choice involving risk and a criticism of the postulates and axioms of the American school. In M. Allais, & O. Hagen (Eds.), Expected Utility Hypotheses and the Allais Paradox. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

  • Anscombe, F.J., & Aumann, R.J. (1963). A definition of subjective probability. Annals of Mathematical Statistics, 34, 199–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diaconis, P., & Freedman, D. (1986). On the consistency of Bayes estimates. Annals of Statistics, 14, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doob, J.L. (1949). Application of the theory of martingales. In Le Calcul des Probabilites et ses Applications, Colloques Internationaux du Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique 13 (pp. 23–27). Paris: CNRS.

  • Ellsberg, D. (1961). Risk, ambiguity and the Savage axioms. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 75, 643–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, L.G., & Schneider, M. (2007). Learning under ambiguity. Review of Economic Studies, 74, 1275–1303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fishburn, P.C. (1988). Nonlinear preferences and utility theory under risk. Baltimore: The John Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardato, P., & Marinacci, M. (2002). Ambiguity made precise: a comparative foundation. Journal of Economic Theory, 102, 251–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ghirardato, P., Maccheroni, F., & Marinacci, M.M. (2004). Differentiating ambiguity and ambiguity attitude. Journal of Economic Theory, 118, 133–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I. (1987). Expected utility with purely subjective non-additive probabilities. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 16, 65–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilboa, I., & Schmeidler, D. (1989). Maxmin expected utility with non-unique priors. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 18, 141–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gosh, J.K., & Ramamoorthi, R.V. (2003). Bayesian nonparametrics. New York: Springer Verlag Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaffray, J.-Y. (1994). Dynamic decision making with belief functions. In R.R. Yager, M. Fedrizzi, & J. Kacprzyk (Eds.), Advances in the Dempster-Shafer theory of evidence (pp. 331–352). New York: Wiley. Jaffray, J.-Y. (1994). Dynamic decision making with belief functions. In RR Yager, M. Fedrizzi, & J. Kacprzyk (Eds.), Advances in the dempster-shafer theory of evidence (pp. 331–352). New York: Wiley.

  • Lijoi, A., Pruenster, I., & Walker, S.O. (2004). Extending Doob’s consistency theorem to nonparametric densities. Bernoulli, 10, 651–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machina, M.J. (2004). Almost-objective uncertainty. Economic Theory, 24, 1–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marinacci, M. (2002). Learning from ambiguous urns. Statistical Papers, 43, 145–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savage, L.J. (1954). The foundations of statistics. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D. (1986). Integral representation without additivity. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society, 97, 255–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmeidler, D. (1989). Subjective probability and expected utility without additivity. Econometrica, 57, 571–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt, U. (2004). Alternatives to expected utility: some formal theories. In P.J. Hammond, S. Barberá, & C. Seidl (Eds.), Handbook of utility theory, Chapter 15, Vol. II. Boston: Kluwer.

  • Starmer, C. (2000). Developments in non-expected utility theory: the hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk. Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 332–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. (1991). Does the random-lottery incentive system elicit true preferences? An experimental investigation. American Economic Review, 81, 971–978.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2004). Alternatives to expected utility: foundation. In P.J. Hammond, S. Barberá, & C. Seidl (Eds.), Handbook of utility theory, Chapter 14, Vol. II. Boston: Kluwer.

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: cumulative representations of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W.K. (1985). A Bayesian perspective on biases in risk perception. Economics Letters, 17, 59–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, W.K., & O’Connor, C.J. (1984). Adaptive responses to chemical labeling: are workers bayesian decision makers? American Economic Review, 74, 942–956.

    Google Scholar 

  • van de Kuilen, G., & Wakker, P.P. (2006). Learning in the Allais paradox. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 33, 155–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Neuman, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1947). Theory of games and economic behavior, 2nd edn. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P.P. (2001). Testing and characterizing properties of nonadditive measures through violations of the sure-thing principle. Econometrica, 69, 1039–1059.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P.P. (2010). Prospect theory for risk and ambiguity. Cambridge University Press.

  • Wakker, P.P., & Tversky, A. (1993). An axiomatization of cumulative prospect theory. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 7, 147–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, G., & Gonzalez, R. (1996). Curvature of the probability weighting function. Management Science, 42, 1676–1690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, G., & Gonzalez, R. (1999). Nonlinear decison weights in choice under uncertainty. Management Science, 45, 74–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimper, A. (2011). Do Bayesians learn their way out of ambiguity?. Decision Analysis, 8, 269–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimper, A. (2013). The emergence of “Fifty-Fifty” probability judgments through Bayesian updating under ambiguity. Fuzzy Sets and Systems, 223, 72–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zimper, A., & Ludwig, A. (2009). On attitude polarization under Bayesian learning with non-additive beliefs. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 39, 181–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alexander Zimper.

Additional information

We thank Justine Burns, Ulrich Schmidt, Alex Ludwig and ESSA 2013 conference participants for helpful comments and suggestions. We are greatly indebted to Peter Wakker and an anonymous referee for sharpening our theoretical understanding of the experimental findings. Aylit and Nicky gratefully acknowledge financial funding of the experiment by the School of Economics and Business Sciences at Wits. We all gratefully acknowledge financial support from Economic Research Southern Africa (ERSA).

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

(PDF 104 KB)

Appendices

Appendix A: The sure-thing principle

The Savage framework considers a state space S, a set of outcomes X, and a set of acts F which map the state space into the outcome space, i.e. f:SX for fF. Savage (1954) provides a set of axioms over preferences \(\succsim \) on the acts in F which gives rise to his famous subjective EU theory. His key axiom for deriving subjective EU theory is the sure-thing principle (STP) which formally states that for all acts f,g,h,h F and all events ES,

$$ f_{E}h\succsim g_{E}h\text{ implies}\ \ f_{E}h^{\prime }\succsim g_{E}h^{\prime }\text{.} $$
(5)

Here f E h denotes the act that gives the outcomes of act f in event E and the outcomes of act h else, i.e.

$$ f_{E}h\left( s\right) =\left\{ \begin{array}{cc} f\left( s\right) & \text{for }s\in E \\ h\left( s\right) & \text{for }s\in S\backslash E\text{.} \end{array} \right. $$
(6)

To formally describe the choice between the prospects A and B, resp. A and B , within the Savage framework, let us reinterpret these prospects as the following acts

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \mathbf{A} &=&f_{Y\cup B}h\text{, }\mathbf{B}=g_{Y\cup B}h\text{;} \end{array} $$
(7)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \mathbf{A}^{\prime } &=&f_{Y\cup B}h^{\prime }\text{, }\mathbf{B}^{\prime }=g_{Y\cup B}h^{\prime }\end{array} $$
(8)

such that

$$ f\left( s\right) =\left\{ \begin{array}{cc} x & \text{for }s\in Y \\ z & \text{for }s\in B \end{array} \right. $$
(9)

as well as g(s)=y for sYB and h(s)=y , h (s)=x for sR. For example, the revealed choice pair A,B , i.e.

$$ \mathbf{A\succ B}\text{ and }\mathbf{B}^{\prime }\mathbf{\succ A}^{\prime } \text{,} $$
(10)

then corresponds to the following revealed preferences over Savage acts

$$ f_{Y\cup B}h\mathbf{\succ }g_{Y\cup B}h\text{ and }g_{Y\cup B}h^{\prime } \mathbf{\succ }f_{Y\cup B}h^{\prime }\text{,} $$
(11)

which violate the STP. Similarly, it is straightforward to see that B,A also violates the STP whereas the choice pairs A,A and B,B are consistent with the STP.

Appendix B: Prospect theory

Although the STP violating choice pairs (2) cannot be represented by EU theory, they can be represented by prospect theory. Restricted to the domain of gains, prospect theory gives rise to the following utility representation for preferences \(\succsim \) over Savage acts f,gF,

$$ f\succsim g\Leftrightarrow \int\limits_{s\in S}^{C}u\left( f\left( s\right) \right) d\nu \left( s\right) \geq \int\limits_{s\in S}^{C}u\left( g\left( s\right) \right) d\nu \left( s\right) $$
(12)

where ν is a unique non-additive (=not necessarily additive) probability measure satisfying ν()=0, ν(S)=1, and ν(E)≤ν(E ) if EE ; and the integral in (12) is the Choquet integral.Footnote 8

$$ \int\limits_{s\in S}^{C}u\left( f\left( s\right) \right) d\nu \left( s\right) = \sum\limits_{i=1}^{m}u\left( f\left( s_{i}\right) \right) \cdot \left[ \nu \left( E_{1}\cup ...\cup E_{i}\right) -\nu \left( E_{1}\cup ...\cup E_{i-1}\right) \right] $$
(13)

Focus at first on the choice pair A,B . Without loss of generality, set u(z)=1 and u(x)=0 so that we obtain for a prospect theory decision maker that

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \mathbf{A} &\succ &\mathbf{B}\Leftrightarrow \end{array} $$
(14)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \int\limits_{s\in S}^{C}u\left( f_{Y\cup B}h\right) dv\left( s\right) &>&\int\limits_{s\in S}^{C}u\left( g_{Y\cup B}h\right) dv\left( s\right) \Leftrightarrow \end{array} $$
(15)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \nu \left( B\right) +u\left( y\right) \left[ \nu \left( B\cup R\right) -\nu \left( B\right) \right] &>&u\left( y\right)\end{array} $$
(16)

as well as

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \mathbf{B}^{\prime } &\succ &\mathbf{A}^{\prime }\Leftrightarrow \end{array} $$
(17)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \int\limits_{s\in S}^{C}u\left( g_{Y\cup B}h^{\prime }\right) dv\left( s\right) &>&\int\limits_{s\in S}^{C}u\left( f_{Y\cup B}h^{\prime }\right) dv\left( s\right) \Leftrightarrow \end{array} $$
(18)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} u\left( y\right) \left[ \nu \left( B\cup Y\right) \right] &>&\nu \left( B\right) \text{.} \end{array} $$
(19)

Combining inequalities (16) and (19) shows that the utility representation (12) of the revealed choices A,B requires local concavity of ν in the following senseFootnote 9

$$ \nu \left( E\cup E^{\prime }\right) +\nu \left( E\cap E^{\prime }\right) \leq \left( \text{resp. }\geq \right) \nu \left( E\right) +\nu \left( E^{\prime }\right) \text{.} $$
(20)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} u\left( y\right) \left[ \nu \left( B\cup Y\right) \right] &>&u\left( y\right) \left[ 1-\left[ \nu \left( B\cup R\right) -\nu \left( B\right) \right] \right] \Leftrightarrow \end{array} $$
(21)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \nu \left( B\cup Y\right) &>&\nu \left( S\right) -\left[ \nu \left( B\cup R\right) -\nu \left( B\right) \right] \Leftrightarrow \end{array} $$
(22)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \nu \left( B\cup Y\right) \!+\nu \left( B\cup R\right)\! &>&\!\nu \left( \left( B\cup Y\right) \cup \left( B\cup R\right) \right) \!+\nu \left( \left( B\cup Y\right) \cap \left( B\cup R\right) \right) \text{.}\end{array} $$
(23)

An analogous argument shows that the choice pair B,A requires local convexity of ν in the following sense

$$ \nu \left( B\cup Y\right) +\nu \left( B\cup R\right) <\nu \left( \left( B\cup Y\right) \cup \left( B\cup R\right) \right) +\nu \left( \left( B\cup Y\right) \cap \left( B\cup R\right) \right) \text{.} $$
(24)

Concavity, resp. convexity, of the non-additive probability measure ν is typically associated with optimistic, resp. pessimistic, ambiguity attitudes of a prospect theory decision maker (cf. Wakker 2001; Chapter 10.4.3 in Wakker 2010).

Appendix C: Risk and the independence axiom

Consider the limiting case of statistical learning in which the decision maker could observe an infinite number of drawings (with replacement) from the urn, i.e. an infinite amount of data generated by multivariate Bernoulli trials driven by the balls’ true proportions. According to standard models of statistical Bayesian learning, this decision maker will then learn, by Doob’s (1949) consistency theorem, with certainty the true probabilities of the events R, Y, and B.Footnote 10

Denote this objective probability measure as π ; e.g. in our experiment we stipulate that π (R)=π (Y)=0.2, π (B)=0.6 in accordance with the balls’ true proportions. In this risky decision situation with known probabilities, the prospects A, B, A , and B can be reinterpreted as the following lotteries (=objective probability distributions) over the monetary outcomes x,y,z, respectively:

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \mathbf{A} &=&\left( 0.2,0.2,0.6\right) \text{,} \\ \mathbf{B} &=&\left( 0,1,0\right) \text{,} \\ \mathbf{A}^{\prime } &=&\left( 0.4,0,0.6\right) \text{,} \\ \mathbf{B}^{\prime } &=&\left( 0.2,0.8,0\right) \text{.} \end{array} $$

EU theory had been first axiomatized for preferences over lotteries by von Neuman and Morgenstern (1947). Key to their celebrated EU representation theorem is the independence axiom (IA) which implies that, for all lotteries L,L ,L and all λ∈(0,1),

$$ L\succsim L^{\prime }\Leftrightarrow \lambda \cdot L+\left( 1-\lambda \right) L^{\prime \prime }\succsim \lambda \cdot L^{\prime }+\left( 1-\lambda \right) L^{\prime \prime }\text{.} $$
(25)

Focus on the choice pair A,B and observe that it reveals a violation of the IA. To see this denote by δ k , k∈{x,y,z}, the degenerate lottery that gives the monetary amount k with probability one. Let λ=π (R) and (1−λ)⋅μ=π (Y) and observe that (25) implies for the choice pair A,B thatFootnote 11

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \mathbf{A\succ B} &\Leftrightarrow & \end{array} $$
(26)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \lambda \cdot \delta_{y}+\left( 1-\lambda \right) \cdot \left[ \mu \cdot \delta_{x}+\left( 1-\mu \right) \cdot \delta_{z}\right] &>&\lambda \cdot \delta_{y}+\left( 1-\lambda \right) \cdot \delta_{y}\Leftrightarrow \end{array} $$
(27)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \mu \cdot \delta_{x}+\left( 1-\mu \right) \cdot \delta_{z} &>&\delta_{y} \text{.} \end{array} $$
(28)

as well as

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \mathbf{B}^{\prime } &\mathbf{\succ }&\mathbf{A}^{\prime }\Leftrightarrow \end{array} $$
(29)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \lambda \cdot \delta_{x}+\left( 1-\lambda \right) \cdot \delta_{y} &>&\lambda \cdot \delta_{x}+\left( 1-\lambda \right) \cdot \left[ \mu \cdot \delta_{x}+\left( 1-\mu \right) \cdot \delta_{z}\right] \Leftrightarrow \end{array} $$
(30)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \delta_{y} &>&\mu \cdot \delta_{x}+\left( 1-\mu \right) \cdot \delta_{z} \text{.} \end{array} $$
(31)

Since (28) and (31) constitute a contradiction, the revealed preferences A,B violate the IA.

More generally, in a decision situation with known probabilities the choice pairs (1) are consistent with the IA, whereas the choice pairs (2) violate the IA.

Appendix D: Caveat

Whereas the choice pairs (2) unambiguously reveal a violation of the STP for the control group, the situation is slightly different for the test group whose members observe the drawing of one ball after each choice. To see this consider a decision maker of the test group and denote by I n the information he has received by observing n drawings. If this decision maker chooses, e.g. A after n and B after n+1 drawings, these revealed choices could be rationalized as EU consistent choices as follows:

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \mathbf{A}\mathbf{\succ B} &\Leftrightarrow & \end{array} $$
(32)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} u\left( x\right) \cdot \pi \left( Y\mid I_{n}\right) +u\left( z\right) \cdot \pi \left( B\mid I_{n}\right) &>&u\left( y\right) \cdot \left( 1-\pi \left( R\mid I_{n}\right) \right) \end{array} $$
(33)

and

$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} \mathbf{B}^{\prime } &\succ &\mathbf{A}^{\prime }\Leftrightarrow \end{array} $$
(34)
$$\begin{array}{@{}rcl@{}} u\left( y\right) \cdot \left( 1-\pi \left( R\mid I_{n+1}\right) \right) &>&u\left( x\right) \cdot \pi \left( Y\mid I_{n+1}\right) +u\left( z\right) \cdot \pi \left(B\mid I_{n+1}\right) \text{.} \end{array} $$
(35)

Whereas the two inequalities (33) and (35) cannot simultaneously hold if π(⋅∣I n ) and π(⋅∣I n+1) are sufficiently similar probability measures, it is possible that (33) and (35) are satisfied for appropriately chosen values of π(⋅∣I n ) and π(⋅∣I n+1). In that case, the choices A,B would not reveal a violation of the STP but rather the different perception of the urn’s uncertainty by an EU decision maker before versus after he updates his additive belief on the n+1th observation.

We could have easily avoided this ambiguity in the interpretation of choice pairs (2) for the test group, if we had allowed for statistical learning not within but only after each question pair was answered. However, when designing the experiment, our concern was to give the subjects no hint that they were actually answering 15 well-structured question pairs rather than 30 similar questions. Although we feared that a detection of this question pair structure might eventually result in some answering bias, we assumed that any difference between π(⋅∣I n ) and π(⋅∣I n+1) would be negligibly small (in the sense of: How great can the impact of a single observation be?).

In the subsequent interpretation of the data, we therefore assume that π(⋅∣I n ) and π(⋅∣I n+1) are indeed sufficiently close so that choice pairs (2) cannot be explained by EU consistent decision making but rather by revealed violations of the STP. If this assumption was violated, however, we would observe, by Doob’s (1949) consistency theorem, that π(⋅∣I n ) and π(⋅∣I n+1) become more and more similar with increasing n. Applied to the experiment, this means that although revealed choices (2) in the first rounds of the experiment (small n) might be EU consistent, revealed choices (2) in the later rounds of the experiment (large n) would rather indicate a violation of the STP. Consequently, an EU consistent decision maker who expressed choice pairs (2) in the beginning of the experiment would eventually switch to choice pairs (1) in the later rounds of the experiment when his conditional probability measures converge through statistical learning in accordance with Doob’s (1949) consistency theorem.

To summarize the caveat: If our maintained assumption that choice pairs (2) always reveal violations of the STP for the test group was not correct, we might observe a decline in the number of choice pairs (2) which is not caused by a decline of violations of the STP.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Nicholls, N., Romm, A.T. & Zimper, A. The impact of statistical learning on violations of the sure-thing principle. J Risk Uncertain 50, 97–115 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-015-9210-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-015-9210-y

Keywords

JEL Classifications

Navigation