Skip to main content
Log in

The future of political philosophy: Non-ideal and west of babel

  • Published:
The Review of Austrian Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Within the last decade or so, political philosophers have undergone intense disagreement over the proper methodology of political philosophy. This paper contributes to and tries to move past this debate by offering a new way of thinking about what it is political philosophers are trying to do. Instead of being either ideal or non-ideal theorists, political philosophers can orient themselves east of Eden or west of Babel. After examining different possible research projects, I argue that the most promising route forward for political philosophers is theorizing that is non-ideal and west of Babel. The paper ends by articulating what such a research program might look like.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Sometimes the political philosopher’s predictive model is quite rigorous and explicit, however. For an example of this, see Kogelmann and Ogden (2018).

  2. Indeed, even political philosophers that might initially seem opposed to including such components slip them in the back door. On this point see Gaus (2016: xv-xvi).

  3. This is one of the central insights of the robust political economy research program. For an overview see Pennington (2011).

  4. Ideal theory (and non-ideal theory as well) now means many things, and the way I employ the term in this paper is but one possible meaning. For an excellent overview of other ways of understanding the distinction, see Valentini (2012).

  5. It is a simplification to argue that all ideal theorists (and all non-ideal theorists as well) adopt the same behavioral model. As an example of this, though Rawls’s behavioral model is certainly aspirational and deviates from how persons actually behave, some have criticized it for not being aspirational enough – he still lets some unfortunate aspects of human nature slip in. On this point see Cohen (2008: ch. 1). This diversity among ideal theorists (and non-ideal theorists as well) is inessential to the current paper’s central argument, so we shall ignore it.

  6. Note that assuming persons are wicked and knaves does not necessarily imply that we are using an accurate model of human behavior. Just as the ideal theorist is too optimistic, it is possible to overcorrect and be too pessimistic as well. Non-ideal theory (as we have defined it) seeks an accurate model of human behavior. For more on this point as it relates to Buchanan’s work, see Kogelmann (2015); Kogelmann (2018: 27–28).

  7. Another recent and important Quadrant III work of political philosophy is Moehler (2018). For examination and criticism, see Kogelmann (2019).

  8. For detailed comparison of the two respective projects see Kogelmann (2018).

  9. This, of course, assumes that political philosophers are trying to offer practical, action-guiding advice. Some deny this. In the words of G.A. Cohen (2008: 268): “The question for political philosophy is not what we should do but what we should think, even when what we should think makes no practical difference.”

  10. For the general theory of the second best see Lipsey and Lancaster (1956). For philosophical discussion see Wiens (2016).

  11. Of course, there are other problems with centrally planned economies besides their incentive-compatibility issues: namely, knowledge problems that stem from getting rid of prices, which serve a valuable epistemic function. For an overview see Boettke (2001).

  12. For criticism of Sen on this point see Simmons (2010).

  13. See also White and Ypi (2016).

  14. For more on jurisdictional rights and dispute resolution, see Chung and Kogelmann (forthcoming).

References

  • Boettke, P. J. (2001). Calculation and coordination: Essays on socialism and transitional political economy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonotti, M. (2017). Partisanship and political liberalism in diverse societies. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, James M. 1979/1999. “Politics without romance: A sketch of positive public choice theory and its normative implications.” In The Logical Foundations of constitutional democracy: 45–59. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Buchanan, James M. 1987/2001. “Justification of the compound republic: The Calculus in retrospect.” In Choice, Contract, and Constitutions: 68–75. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Buchanan, James M. and Gordon Tullock. 1962/2004. The Calculus of consent: The logical foundations of constitutional democracy. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Chung, Hun and Brian Kogelmann. Forthcoming. “Diversity and rights: A social choice-theoretic analysis of the possibility of public reason.” In Synthese.

  • Cohen, G. A. (2008). Rescuing justice and equality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • D’Agostino, Fred. 2018. “How can we do political philosophy?” Cosmos + Taxis 5: 29–37.

  • Estlund, D. (2011). Human nature and the limits (if any) of political philosophy. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 39, 207–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farrelly, C. (2007). Justice in ideal theory: A refutation. Political Studies, 55, 844–864.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaus, G. (2016). The tyranny of the ideal: Justice in a diverse society. Princeton: Princeton University Society.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek, F. A. (1988). The fatal conceit: The errors of socialism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hobbes, Thomas. 1688/1994. Leviathan. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

  • Hume, David. 1741/1987. “Of the independency of parliament.” In Essays: Moral, political, and literary, edited by Eugene F. Miller: 42–46. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Jaworski, Peter. 2017. “Canada needs blood plasma. We should pay donors to get it.” National Post. Link: https://nationalpost.com/opinion/peter-jaworski-canada-needs-blood-plasma-we-should-pay-donors-to-get-it.

  • Kavka, G. (1995). Why even morally perfect people would need government. Social Philosophy & Policy, 12, 1–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kogelmann, B. (2015). Modeling the individual for constitutional choice. Constitutional Political Economy, 26, 455–474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kogelmann, B. (2018). Rawls, Buchanan, and the search for a better social contract. In P. Aligica, C. J. Coyne, & S. Haeffele (Eds.), Exploring the Political Economy & Social Philosophy of James M. Buchanan (pp. 17–38). London: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kogelmann, B. (2019). Minimal morality: A multilevel social contract theory, Michael Moehler. Oxford University press, 2018, 272 pages. Economics and Philosophy, 35, 173–179.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kogelmann, B., & Ogden, B. G. (2018). Enough and as good: A formal model of Lockean first appropriation. American Journal of Political Science, 62, 682–694.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, J. (2016). There is no such thing as ideal theory. Social Philosophy & Policy, 33, 312–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipsey, R. G., & Lancaster, K. (1956). The general theory of second best. The Review of Economic Studies, 24, 11–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, John. 1689/2003. The second treatise of government. In John Locke: Political Writings. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Mills, C. W. (2005). Ideal theory’ as ideology. Hypatia, 20, 165–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moehler, M. (2018). Minimal morality: A multilevel social contract theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Muldoon, R. (2016). Social contract theory for a diverse world: Beyond tolerance. New York: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mulligan, T. (2018). Plural voting for the twenty-first century. The Philosophical Quarterly, 68, 286–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. (1986). An agenda for the study of institutions. Public Choice, 48, 3–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. (1990). Governing the commons: The evolution of institutions for collective action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pennington, M. (2011). Robust political economy: Classical liberalism and the future of public policy. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, Karl. 1945/2013. The Open Societies and Its Enemies. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1999). The law of peoples. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (2001). Justice as fairness: A restatement. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riker, W. H. (1980). Implications from the disequilibrium of majority rule for the study of institutions. American Political Science Review, 74, 432–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1755/2011. Discourse on the origin of inequality. In Jean-Jacques Rousseau: The Basic Political Writings. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1762/1987. On the social contract. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Schmidtz, D. (2011). Non-ideal theory: What it is and what it needs to be. Ethics, 121, 772–796.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2006). What do we want from a theory of justice? Journal of Philosophy, 103, 215–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. (2009). The idea of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, A. J. (2010). Ideal and nonideal theory. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 38, 5–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Adam. 1981/1776. An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations. Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.

  • Valentini, L. (2012). Ideal vs. non-ideal theory: A conceptual map. Philosophy Compass, 7, 654–664.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, R. E. (2008). Finding social dilemma: West of babel, not east of Eden. Public Choice, 135, 55–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, J. (1999). Law and disagreement. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • White, J., & Ypi, L. (2016). The meaning of partisanship. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wiens, D. (2015a). Against Ideal Guidance. Journal of Politics, 77, 433–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiens, D. (2015b). Political ideals and the feasibility frontier. Economics and Philosophy, 31, 447–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiens, D. (2016). Assessing ideal theories: Lessons from the theory of the second best. Politics, Philosophy, & Economics, 15, 132–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brian Kogelmann.

Additional information

Publisher’s note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kogelmann, B. The future of political philosophy: Non-ideal and west of babel. Rev Austrian Econ 33, 237–252 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-019-00437-0

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11138-019-00437-0

Keywords

JEL classification

Navigation