Skip to main content
Log in

Is ‘cause’ ambiguous?

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Causal pluralists hold that that there is not just one determinate kind of causation. Some causal pluralists hold that ‘cause’ is ambiguous among these different kinds. For example, Hall argues that ‘cause’ is ambiguous between two causal relations, which he labels dependence and production. The view that ‘cause’ is ambiguous, however, wrongly predicts zeugmatic conjunction reduction, and wrongly predicts the behaviour of ellipsis in causal discourse. So ‘cause’ is not ambiguous. If we are to disentangle causal pluralism from the ambiguity claim, we need to consider what other linguistic approaches are available to the causal pluralist. I consider and reject proposals that ‘cause’ is a general term, that the term is an indexical, and that the term conveys different kinds of causation through implicature or presupposition. Finally, I argue that causal pluralism is better handled by treating ‘cause’ as a univocal term within a dynamic interpretation framework.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See Phys. 195a4, 29, Meta. 983a26, 1013b4, 1052b48, De An. 415b9. My name-dropping here is not intended as scholarship. But we will return to Aristotle’s association of causal pluralism and questions. Readers interested in the scholarly issues around Aristotle’s application of homonymy to causation might begin with Stein (2011).

  2. Causal pluralists include Anscombe (1993), Skyrms (1984), Sober (1985), De Vreese (2006), Cartwright (2007), Godfrey-Smith (2010), Illari and Russo (2014), and McDonnell (2018).

  3. Hall’s specific version of determinate causal pluralism has received considerable attention. Some have embraced the distinction between production and dependence: see, for example, Illari and Russo (2014), and McDonnell (2018). Others have responded with unitary analyses of causation that nonetheless employ the distinction: for example, Beckers and Vennekens (2018) argue that dependence is an unnecessary but sufficient condition for causation, and production is an insufficient but necessary condition; and Andreas and Günther (2020) offer an analysis of causation by complementing production with a weak condition of difference-making. Hall’s pluralism has also received its share of criticism. Some criticize the sufficiency of production and dependence for causation: for example, Schaffer (2001, 2016) describes cases where an event causes an effect but neither does the cause produce the effect nor does the effect depend on the cause. Others criticize the necessity of the distinction: for example, Strevens (2013) argues that a single causal relation suffices to explain Hall’s double prevention cases.

  4. The theses that causation is univocal or multivocal could be seen as conceptual positions, and not linguistic claims. For example, Hitchcock (2001) associates causal pluralism with the rejection of the thesis that causation is univocal, and it is unclear whether this association is with a conceptual or a linguistic thesis. But Hitchcock (2007) explicitly endorses the linguistic ambiguity claim, and Hall and Hitchcock both confirm in personal correspondence that a linguistic ambiguity claim was their original intention. Other authors who contrast pluralism with an explicitly linguistic univocality thesis include De Vreese (2006, 2009), Love (2012) and Schaffer (2016). Authors who contrast pluralism with a conceptual univocality thesis include Longworth (2006, 2010) and Reiss (2009).

  5. For these two tests, I’m drawing largely on Zwicky and Sadock (1975). For a recent survey of ambiguity from a philosophical perspective, see Sennet (2016). And for a recent use of such tests within metaphysics, see Shaheen (2017a), who argues that ‘because’ is ambiguous between causation and grounding from alleged zeugmatic conjunction reduction.

  6. For critical discussion of these tests, see for example Norrick (1981) and Geeraerts (1993).

  7. I indirectly owe my appreciation of this point to Schaffer’s (2012) discussion of pragmatic mechanisms for conveying contextually variant causal contrasts.

  8. For discussion of this controversy, see for example Lewis (2017). The application of one approach or another to a specific issue of philosophical interest also generates controversy. See for example, Gillies (2007) and Moss (2012) on handling reverse Sobel sequences with either a dynamic semantics or dynamic pragmatics, and the implications for counterfactuals.

References

  • Andreas, H., & Günther, M. (2020). Causation in terms of production. Philosophical Studies, 177(6), 1565–1591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1993). Causality and determination. Orig 1971. In E. Sosa (Ed.), Causation and Conditionals (pp. 63–81). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beckers, S., & Vennekens, J. (2018). A principled approach to defining actual causation. Synthese, 195(2), 835–862.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brocher, A., Foraker, S., & Koenig, J.-P. (2016). Processing of irregular polysemes in sentence reading. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory and Cognition, 42(11), 1798–1813.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brocher, A., Koenig, J.-P., Mauner, G., & Foraker, S. (2018). About sharing and commitment: The retrieval of biased and balanced irregular polysemes. Language, Cognition and Neuroscience, 33(4), 443–466.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2012). Word meaning and concept expressed. The Linguistic Review, 29(4), 607–623.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (2021). Polysemy: Pragmatics and sense conventions. Mind & Language, 36, 108–133.

  • Cartwright, N. (2007). Hunting causes and using them. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1980). The individuation of events. Orig. 1969. Essays on actions and events (pp. 163–180). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2013). Is there a place for truth-conditional pragmatics? Teorema, 32, 85–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2020). Overlooking conventions: The trouble with linguistic pragmatism. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2021). Semantic polysemy and psycholinguistics. Mind & Language, 36(1), 134–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Vreese, L. (2006). Causal pluralism and scientific knowledge: An underexposed problem. Philosophica, 77, 125–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Vreese, L. (2009). Disentangling causal pluralism. In R. Vanderbeeken & B. D’Hooghe (Eds.), Worldviews, Science and Us: Studies of Analytical Metaphysics (pp. 207–223). World Scientific Publishing.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Falkum, I. L. (2015). The how and why of polysemy: A pragmatic account. Lingua, 157, 83–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falkum, I. L. (2017). The lexical pragmatics of count-mass polysemy. Semantics and Pragmatics, 10(20), 52–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frisson, S., & Pickering, M. (2001). Obtaining a figurative interpretation of a word: Support for underspecification. Metaphor and Symbol, 16, 149–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geeraerts, D. (1993). Vagueness’s puzzles, polysemy’s vagaries. Cognitive Linguistics, 4, 223–272.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, A. (2007). Counterfactual scorekeeping. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30, 329–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2010). Causal pluralism. In H. Beebee, C. Hitchcock, & P. Menzies (Eds.), Oxford Handbook of Causation (pp. 326–337). Oxford: Oxford University Press. uCcbloelimshNheidlo Hsoapllhy of causation.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1989). Dynamic montague grammar: A first sketch. ITLI/Department of Philosophy, University of Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groenendijk, J., & Stokhof, M. (1991). Dynamic predicate logic. Linguistics and Philosophy, 14(1), 39–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2004). Two concepts of causation. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 225–276). MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, N. (2006). Philosophy of causation: Blind alleys exposed; promising directions highlighted. Philosophy Compass. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1747-9991.2006.00002.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1982). The Semantics of Definite and Indefinite Noun Phrases. PhD dissertation, University of Massachusetts.

  • Heim, I. (1983). File change semantics and the familiarity theory of definiteness. In R. Bäuerle, C. Schwarze, & A. von Stechow (Eds.), Meaning, Use and Interpretation of Language (pp. 164–189). De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1992). Presupposition projection and the semantics of attitude verbs. Journal of Semantics, 9, 183–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (2001). A tale of two effects. The Philosophical Review, 110, 361–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (2007). How to be a causal pluralist. In P. Machamer & G. Wolters (Eds.), Thinking about causes: From Greek philosophy to modern physics (pp. 200–221). University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P., & Russo, F. (2014). Causality: Philosophical theory meets scientific practice. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff, R. (1992). What is a concept, that a person may grasp it? Languages of the mind: Essays on mental representation (pp. 21–52). MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H. (1981). A theory of truth and semantic representation. In J. Groenendijk, T. Janssen, & M. Stokhof (Eds.), Formal methods in the study of language (pp. 277–322). Mathematisch Centrum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kamp, H., & Reyle, U. (1993). From discourse to logic. Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lepore, E., & Stone, M. (2015). Imagination and convention. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, K. (2017). Dynamic semantics. Oxford Handbooks Online. https://doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199935314.013.14

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longworth, F. (2006). Causation, pluralism and responsibility. Philosophica, 77, 45–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longworth, F. (2010). Review: Cartwright’s causal pluralism: A critique and an alternative. Analysis, 70, 310–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Love, A. (2012). Hierarchy, causation and explanation: Ubiquity, locality and pluralism. Interface Focus, 2, 115–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McCawley, J. D. (1981). What linguists have always wanted to know about logic but were ashamed to ask. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. (2nd edition, 1993.)

  • McDonnell, N. (2018). Making a contribution and making a difference. American Philosophical Quarterly, 55, 303–312.

  • Moss, S. (2012). On the pragmatics of counterfactuals. Noûs, 46, 561–586.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norrick, N. (1981). Semiotic principles in semantic theory. John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ortega-Andres, M., & Vicente, A. (2019). Polysemy and co-predication. Glossa, 4, 1–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. (1978). Bound variables and other anaphors. In D. Waltz (Ed.), Theoretical issues in natural language processing 2 (TINLAP-2). Urbana, IL: University of Illinois, pp. 79–85. Reprinted in Compositionality in formal semantics: Selected papers by Barbara H. Partee. (2004) Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 110–121.

  • Pustejovsky, J. (1995). The generative Lexicon. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quilty-Dunn, J. (2021). Polysemy and thought: Towards a generative theory of concepts. Mind & Language, 36(1), 158–185.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2004). Literal meaning. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Recantati, F. (2010). Truth-conditional pragmatics. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati, F. (2017). Contextualism and polysemy. Dialectica, 71, 379–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J. (2009). Causation in the social sciences: Evidence, inference, and purpose. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 39, 20–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, L. (1984). Ambiguity vs. generality. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 14, 295–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, L. (1987). Intuitions and ambiguity tests. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 17, 189–197.

  • Roberts, C. (1996). Information structure: towards an integrated theory of formal pragmatics. OSU Working Papers in Linguistics, vol. 49: Papers in Semantics, pp. 91–136.

  • Roberts, C. (2004). Discourse context in dynamic interpretation. In L. Horn & G. Ward (Eds.), Handbook of contemporary pragmatic theory (pp. 197–220). Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Rothschild, D., & Yalcin, S. (2016). Three notions of dynamicness in language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 39, 333–355.

  • Ruhl, C. (1989). On monosemy: A study in linguistic semantics. State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2001). Causes as probability-raisers of processes. Journal of Philosophy, 98, 75–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2012). Causal contextualisms. In M. Blaauw (Ed.), Contrastivism in Philosophy: New perspectives (pp. 35–63). Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2016). The metaphysics of causation. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2016 Edition), E. Zalta (Ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/causation-metaphysics/>.

  • Sennet, A. (2016). Ambiguity. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition), E. Zalta (Ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/ambiguity/>.

  • Shaheen, J. (2017a). Ambiguity and explanation. Inquiry, 60(8), 839–866.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaheen, J. (2017b). The causal metaphor account of metaphysical explanation. Philosophical Studies, 174, 553–578.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (1984). EPR: Lessons for metaphysics. In P. French & T. H. UehlingWettstein (Eds.), Midwest studies in Philosophy IX (pp. 245–255). University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. (1985). Two concepts of cause. In P. Asquith and P. Kitcher (Eds.), PSA 1984 (Volume 2), East Lansing: Philosophy of Science Association, pp. 405–24.

  • Stalnaker, R. (1974). Pragmatic presuppositions. In M. K. Munitz and P. K. Unger (Eds.), Semantics and Philosophy. New York: New York University Press, pp. 197–214. Reprinted in Stalnaker (1999), pp. 47–62.

  • Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics 9: Pragmatics (pp. 315–322). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1999). Context and content. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stein, N. (2011). Aristotle’s causal pluralism. Archiv Für Geschichte Der Philosophie, 93(2), 121–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2013). Causality reunified. Erkenntnis, 78, 299–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vicente, A. (2018). Polysemy and word meaning: An account of lexical meaning for different kinds of content words. Philosophical Studies, 175(4), 947–968.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, D., & Carston, R. (2007). A unitary approach to lexical pragmatics: Relevance, inference and ad hoc concepts. In N. Burton-Roberts (Ed.), Pragmatics (pp. 230–259). Palgrave.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Zwicky, A., & Sadock, J. (1975). Ambiguity tests and how to fail them. In J. Kimball (Ed.), Syntax and semantics, 4 (pp. 1–36). Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwicky, A., & Sadock, J. (1987). A non-test for ambiguity. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 17, 185–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Christopher Hitchcock, Michael Hymers, Tom Vinci and the auditors of talks given at Dalhousie University and the APA Central. Thanks especially to Ned Hall for magnanimous comments. I gratefully acknowledge financial support from SSHRC Insight Development Grant #430-2020-00713.

Funding

N/A.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Phil Corkum.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Corkum, P. Is ‘cause’ ambiguous?. Philos Stud 179, 2945–2971 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01809-2

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-022-01809-2

Keywords

Navigation