Skip to main content
Log in

Understanding standing: permission to deflect reasons

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Standing is a peculiar norm, allowing for deflecting that is rejecting offhand and without deliberation interventions such as directives. Directives are speech acts that aim to give directive-reasons, which are reason to do as the directive directs because of the directive. Standing norms, therefore, provide for deflecting directives regardless of validity (i.e., regardless of whether or not a directive succeeds in giving a directive-reason) or the normative weight of the rejected directive. The logic of the normativity of standing is, therefore, not the logic of invalidating directives or of competing with directive-reasons but of ‘exclusionary permission’. That is, standing norms provide for permission to exclude from practical deliberation directive-reasons if given without the requisite standing, regardless of their normative weight. As such, standing is a type of second-order norm. Numerous everyday practices involve the deflection of directives, such as pervasive practices of deflecting hypocritical and officious directives. Of various possible models, the one that best captures the normative structure of these practices of deflection is the standing model. Accordingly, the normativity of standing is pervasive in our everyday practices. Establishing that standing, although a neglected philosophical idea, is a significant and independent normative concept.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. To be clear, Assad may not discount the reasons Erdogan is pointing out to him—that Assad’s actions are heinous. All that Assad may ignore is Erdogan’s demands and condemnations as reasons in and of themselves.

  2. Briefly on everyday instances of age tuum negotium see Duff (2010), Smith (2007), Wertheimer (1998).

  3. For examples of tu quoque see Cohen (2006), Duff (2010), Friedman (2013) and Todd (2012).

  4. On types of reason see Parfit (2001, p. 17), Scanlon (1988, p. 17).

  5. On the grounds of the legitimacy and validity of directives of political authorites see Rawls (1986) (reasonable consensus), Christiano (2004) (democracy), Locke (1690) (consent), Raz (1986) (instrumentalism).

  6. I use (normative) ‘weight’ and ‘force’ interchangeably, as stylistically fitting.

  7. On ‘antecedent-reasons’ and related ideas see Enoch (2014).

  8. I pose ‘belief’ and ‘attitude’ as alternatives to signal agnosticism as to matters of the cognitivism—non cognitivism distinction. For the cognitivist perhaps what I call ‘evaluative-assertion’ is a sub-category of what Searle and Vanderveken refer to as ‘expressives’. Here I keep them distinct.

  9. By ‘irrational’ I mean open to rational criticism. Parfit (1986, p. 119).

  10. Taking inspiration from John Gardner’s account of the relation between primary and secondary obligations. Gardner (2011). And from Raz (2004, pp. 189–193).

  11. I take Anthony Duff’s account of the state’s standing to hold criminals accountable as charting an instance of such a divergence of validity (in this case state authority) from standing (Duff 2010).

  12. I can’t claim allies for this view or for the view I endorse in the next section. However, some use the term ‘standing’ to explain the nature of hypocritical blaming or condemning, and some understandings of ‘standing’ are incompatible with the invalidation model. Those who I expect would endorse something along the lines of what I called the ‘alteration’ or the ‘exclusion’ models and would reject the invalidation model are Bell (2012) and Duff (2010).

  13. See, e.g., Broome (2004).

  14. On ‘exclusionary reasons’ and ‘exclusionary norms’ see Raz (1990, pp. 40–48 and pp. 73–76 respectively).

References

  • Bell, M. (2012). The standing to blame: A critique. In D. J. Coates & N. A. Tognazzini (Eds.), Blame: Its nature and norms (pp. 263–281). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2004). Reasons. In R. J. Wallace, P. Pettit, S. Scheffler, & M. Smith (Eds.), Reason and value (pp. 36–39). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christiano, T. (2004). The authority of democracy. Journal of Political Philosophy, 12(3), 245–270.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G. A. (2006). Casting the first stone: Who can, and who can’t, condemn the terrorists? Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement, 81(58), 113–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. (2004). Enticing reasons. In R. J. Wallace, P. Pettit, S. Scheffler, & M. Smith (Eds.), Reason and value (pp. 91–118). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. (2006). The second-person standpoint: Morality, respect, and accountability. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, A. (2001). Punishment, communication, and community (pp. 185–188). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, A. (2010). Moral standing and the legitimacy of the criminal trial. Ratio (new series), XXII(2), 125–127.

    Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, D. (2014). Authority and reason-giving. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 89(2), 296–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2013). How to blame people responsibility. Journal of Value Inquiry, 47(3), 275–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, J. (2011). What is tort law for? Part 1. Law and Philosophy, 30(1), 1–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gert, J. (2007). Normative strength and the balance of reasons. Philosophical Review, 116(4), 533–562.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greenspan, P. (2007). Practical reason and moral “ought”. In R. Shafer-Landau (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaethics (Vol. II, pp. 172–194). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1690). Second treatise on civil government.

  • Parfit, D. (1986). Reasons and persons (p. 119). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2001). Rationality and reasons. In D. Egonsson & I. Persson (Eds.), Exploring practical philosophy (p. 17). Farnham: Ashgate Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1986). Political liberalism. New York, NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1977). Promises and obligations. In P. M. S. Hacker & J. Raz (Eds.), Law, morality, and society (pp. 210–228). Oxford: Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1979). The authority of law (pp. 37–52). Oxford: Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom. Oxford: Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1990). Practical reasons and norms (pp. 178–179). Oxford: Oxford Univeristy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (2004). Personal practical conflicts. In P. Baumann & M. Betzler (Eds.), Practical conflicts: New philosophical essays (pp. 189–193). Cambridge: Cambridge Univeristy Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1988). What we owe to each other (p. 17). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (2008). Moral dimensions. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R., & Vanderveken, D. (1985). Foundations of illocutionary logic (pp. 55–56). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smilansky, S. (2006). The paradox of moral complaint. Utilitas, 18(3), 277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. M. (2007). On being responsible and holding responsible. The Journal of Ethics, 11(4), 478–480.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steinvorth, D., & Musharbash, Y. (2010). Shocking images of dead Kurdish fighters: Turkey accused of using chemical weapons against PKK. Spiegel Online International. http://www.spiegel.de/international/world/shocking-images-of-dead-kurdish-fighters-turkey-accused-of-using-chemical-weapons-against-pkk-a-711536.html. Accessed 12 April 2016.

  • Tadros, V. (2009). Poverty and criminal responsibility. The Journal of Value Inquiry, 43(3), 391–413.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Todd, P. (2012). Manipulation and moral standing: An argument for incompatibilism. Philosopher’s Imprint, 12(7), 6–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, R. J. (2010). Hypocrisy, moral address, and the equal standing of persons. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 38(4), 307–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wertheimer, R. (1998). Constraining condemning. Ethics, 108(3), 489–501, 497.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Previous drafts of this paper were presented at the Workshop on Law, Ethics and the State, Tel Aviv University (February, 2014), King’s College London’s Legal Philosophy Workshop (March, 2014), the Analytic Legal Philosophy Conference (Oxford, 2014) and at the Private Law Theory Workshop at Hebrew University (April 2015). I thank the participants for the valuable discussions. I am also grateful to Stephen Darwall, Anthony Duff, David Enoch, Anna Finkelstern, Alon Harel, Miguel Herstein, Michael Ignatieff, Uri D. Leibowitz, Timothy Macklem, Joseph Raz, Irit Samet, Eloise Scotford, Re-em Segev, Assaf Sharon, Matthew N. Smith, Michal Shur-Ofri, Lorenzo Zucca and the referee for Philosophical Studies.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ori J. Herstein.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Herstein, O.J. Understanding standing: permission to deflect reasons. Philos Stud 174, 3109–3132 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0849-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0849-2

Keywords

Navigation