Skip to main content
Log in

A Normative Pragmatic Theory of Exhorting

  • Published:
Argumentation Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We submit a normative pragmatic theory of exhorting—an account of conceptually necessary and potentially efficacious components of a coherent strategy for securing a sympathetic hearing for efforts to urge and inspire addressees to act on high-minded principles. Based on a Gricean analysis of utterance-meaning, we argue that the concept of exhorting comprises making statements openly urging addressees to perform some high-minded, principled course of action; openly intending to inspire addressees to act on the principles; and intending that addressees’ recognition of the intentions to urge and inspire creates reasons for addressees to grant a sympathetic hearing to what the speaker has to say. We show that the theory accounts for the design of Abraham Lincoln’s Cooper Union address. By doing so we add to the inventory of reasons why social actors make arguments, continue a line of research showing the relationship of arguing to master speech acts, and show that making arguments can be an effective strategy for inspiring principled action.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. We use the phrase “making arguments” and related terms such as “argumentation” in the sense of O’Keefe’s (1982) “argument1-making”.

  2. Researchers who approach argumentation from a pragma-dialectical perspective have also described their theorizing as normative pragmatic and also make use of speech act theory in developing pragma-dialectical theory (e.g., van Eemeren and Grootendorst 1984, 2004; van Eemeren et al. 1993). Whereas pragma-dialectical theory is based on integrating Grice’s maxims with Searle’s conditions for the performance of speech acts (e.g., Andone 2013; Houtlosser 1998; Snoeck Henkemans 2014), normative pragmatic theory is based on Grice’s analysis of utterance-meaning (1957, 1969) as amended and explained by Strawson (1964) and Stampe (1967). Normative pragmatic theory explains why a speaker can reasonably expect her utterance to secure her intended response from addressees without recourse to a notion of rules applied to a communicative interaction (Kauffeld 1987, 2009b; Strawson 1964). Instead, a normative pragmatic account explains or makes intelligible how social actors themselves design messages that regulate the activity (e.g., Jacobs 1989, 2000, 2006).

  3. See Kauffeld (1987, 2001, 2009a, b) for more detail on Grice’s analysis.

  4. We maintain that exhortations must urge and inspire principled action, a position compatible with the fact that news sources have described as exhortation some of U.S. President Donald Trump’s calls to deplorable action (Hoefler 2016; Sweeny 2017). We believe utterances such as a call to “get ‘em” (protestors) at one of his March 2016 presidential campaign rallies are more accurately described as “inciting violence” than “exhorting violence,” as indicated by both public outrage at Trump’s calls to violent action and questions about whether Trump “incited” violence. Nonetheless, even if one wants to describe calls to deplorable action as exhortation, we submit that such exhortations may not be practically efficacious because they are easy to dismiss with impunity as immoral, unethical, wrong, not the right thing to do, and so on (see also Cooper and Zeleny 2011). As arguments can be weak or poor, so can exhortations.

References

  • Andone, C. 2013. Argumentation in political interviews: Analyzing and evaluating responses to accusations of inconsistency. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Asen, R. 2005. Pluralism, disagreement, and the status of argument in the public sphere. Informal Logic 25(2): 117–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Black, E. 1965. Rhetorical criticism: A study in method. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Briggs, J.C. 2005. Lincoln’s speeches reconsidered. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conley, T.M. 1984. The enthymeme in perspective. Quarterly Journal of Speech 70(2): 168–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, H., and J. Zeleny. 2011, January 13. Obama calls for a new era of civility in U.S. politics. New York Times. Retrieved January 18, 2018 from www.nytimes.com.

  • Corry, J.A. 2003. Lincoln at Cooper Union: The speech that made him president. Bloomington: Xlibris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Current, R.N. 2009. The master politician. In The best American history essays on Lincoln, ed. S. Wilentz, 129–148. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. 2013. Honor, history, and relationship: Essays in second-personal ethics II. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Egerton, D.R. 2010. Year of meteors: Stephen Douglas, Abraham Lincoln, and the election that brought on the Civil War. New York: Bloomsbury Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frazer, M. 2010. The enlightenment of sympathy: Justice and the moral sentiments in the eighteenth century and today. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, J. 2011. Accounting for the appeal to the authority of experts. Argumentation 25(3): 285–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H.P. 1957. Meaning. Philosophical Review 66(3): 377–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H.P. 1969. Utterer’s meaning and intention. Philosophical Review 78(2): 147–177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hample, D., and A.L. Irions. 2015. Arguing to display identity. Argumentation 29(4): 389–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoefler, J. 2016, August 10. Do menacing comments about Hillary Clinton cross the First Amendment line? Washington Post. Retrieved January 18, 2018 from www.washingtonpost.com.

  • Holzer, H. 2004. Lincoln at Cooper Union: The speech that made Abraham Lincoln president. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Houtlosser, P. 1998. Points of view. Argumentation 12(3): 387–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ieţcu-Fairclough, I. 2009. Legitimation and strategic maneuvering in the political field. In Examining argumentation in context: Fifteen studies in strategic maneuvering, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, 131–151. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Innocenti, B. 2011a. Countering questionable tactics by crying foul. Argumentation and Advocacy 47(3): 178–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Innocenti, B. 2011b. Arguing by apostrophizing. In Argumentation: Cognition and community, ed. F. Zenker. CD-ROM. Windsor, ON: Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation.

    Google Scholar 

  • Innocenti, B. 2011c. Analyzing repetition in argumentation. In Proceedings of the seventh international conference of the international society for the study of argumentation, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, B. Garssen, D. Godden, and G. Mitchell, 868–874. CD-ROM. Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

  • Innocenti, B., and F.J. Kauffeld. 2013. Connecting commitments to actions by exhorting. Presented at the National Communication Association Annual Convention, Washington DC.

  • Innocenti, B., and N. Kathol. 2018. The persuasive force of demanding. Philosophy and Rhetoric 51(1): 50–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Innocenti, B., and E. Miller. 2016. The persuasive force of political humor. Journal of Communication 66(3): 366–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, S. 1983. When worlds collide: An application of field theory to rhetorical conflict. In Argument in transition: Proceedings of the third summer conference on argumentation, ed. D. Zarefsky, M.O. Sillars, and J. Rhodes, 749–755. Annandale: Speech Communication Association.

  • Jacobs, S. 1989. Speech acts and arguments. Argumentation 3(4): 345–365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, S. 2000. Rhetoric and dialectic from the standpoint of normative pragmatics. Argumentation 14(3): 261–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, S. 2006. Nonfallacious rhetorical strategies: Lyndon Johnson’s Daisy ad. Argumentation 14(3): 261–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffeld, F.J. 1987. Rhetoric and practical necessity: A view for the study of speech acts. In Proceedings of the fifth SCA/AFA conference on argumentation: Argument and critical practices, ed. J.W. Wenzel, 83–95. Annandale: Speech Communication Association.

  • Kauffeld, F.J. 1995. On the difference between assumptions and presumptions. In Argumentation and values: Proceedings of the ninth SCA/AFA Conference on Argumentation, ed. S. Jackson, 509–514. Annandale: Speech Communication Association.

  • Kauffeld, F.J. 1998. Presumptions and the distribution of argumentative burdens in acts of proposing and accusing. Argumentation 12(2): 245–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffeld, F.J. 2001. Argumentation, discourse, and the rationality underlying Grice’s analysis of utterance-meaning. In Cognition in language use, ed. T.E.T. Németh, 149–163. Antwerp: International Pragmatics Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffeld, F.J. 2003. The ordinary practice of presuming and presumption with special attention to veracity and the burden of proof. In Anyone who has a view: Theoretical contributions to the study of argumentation, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, J.A. Blair, C.A. Willard, and A.F. Snoeck Henkemans, 133–146. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffeld, F.J. 2009a. Grice’s analysis of utterance-meaning and Cicero’s Catilinarian apostrophe. Argumentation 23(2): 239–257.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kauffeld, F.J. 2009b. What we are learning about the pragmatics of the arguers’ obligations? In Concerning argument, ed. S. Jacobs, 1–31. Washington DC: National Communication Association.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffeld, F.J., and B. Innocenti. 2016. Inducing a sympathetic (empathic) reception for exhortation. In Argumentation, objectivity and bias: Proceedings of the 11 th international conference of the Ontario society for the study of argumentation (OSSA), 1821 May 2016, ed. P. Bondy and L. Benaquista, 1–15. Windsor, ON: Ontario Society for the Study of Argumentation. Retrieved January 18, 2018 from http://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA11/papersandcommentaries/127.

  • Kauffeld, F.J., and May, L. 2006. Exhorting and inciting. In Engaging argument: Selected papers from the 2005 NCA/AFA summer conference on argumentation, ed. P. Riley, 318–325. Washington, DC: National Communication Association.

  • Krause, S.R. 2002. Liberalism and honor. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leff, M. 2001. Lincoln at Cooper Union: Neo-classical criticism revisited. Western Journal of Communication 65(3): 232–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leff, M.C., and G.P. Mohrmann. 1974. Lincoln at Cooper Union: Rhetorical analysis of the text. Quarterly Journal of Speech 60(3): 346–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lincoln, A. 1860. Cooper Union address. Reprinted in: H. Holzer (2004) Lincoln at Cooper Union: The speech that made Abraham Lincoln president, 249-284. New York: Simon and Schuster.

  • Marinelli, K. 2016. Revisiting Edwin Black: Exhortation as a prelude to emotional-material rhetoric. Rhetoric Society Quarterly 46(5): 465–485.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moldovan, Andrei. 2016. Presumptions in communication. Studia Humana 5(3): 104–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Keefe, D.J. 1982. The concepts of argument and arguing. In Advances in argumentation theory and research, ed. J.R. Cox and C.A. Willard, 3–23. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinto, R.C. 1991. Generalizing the notion of argumentation. In Proceedings of the second international conference on argumentation, ed. F. H. van Eemeren, R. Grootendorst, J. A. Blair, and C. A. Willard, vol. 1, 137–146. Amsterdam: SIC SAT.

  • Pinto, R.C. 2007. Burdens of rejoinder. In Reason reclaimed: Essays in honor of J. Anthony Blair and Ralph H. Johnson, ed. H.V. Hansen and R.C. Pinto, 75–88. Newport News: Vale Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shakespeare, W. 1993. Julius Caesar. Retrieved January 18, 2018 from http://shakespeare.mit.edu/julius_caesar/.

  • Snoeck Henkemans, A.F. 2014. Speech act theory and the study of argumentation. Studies in Logic, Grammar and Rhetoric 36: 41–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stampe, D.W. 1967. On the acoustic behavior of rational animals. Madison: University of Wisconsin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stampe, D.W. 1975. Meaning and truth in the theory of speech acts. In speech acts, ed. P. Cole and J.L. Morgan, 1–39. New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. 1964. Intention and convention in speech acts. Philosophical Review 73(4): 439–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P.F. 1974. Freedom and resentment and other essays. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sweeny, J. 2017, April 29. Not covered under the first amendment: The ACLU is wrong about Trump and incitement to violence. Salon. Retrieved January 18, 2018 from www.salon.com.

  • van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 1984. Speech acts in argumentative discussions: A theoretical model for the analysis of discussions directed towards solving conflicts of opinion. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 2004. A systematic theory of argumentation: The pragma-dialectical approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., and P. Houtlosser. 2000. Rhetorical analysis within a pragma-dialectical framework: The case of R. J. Reynolds. Argumentation 14(3): 293–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., R. Grootendorst, S. Jackson, and S. Jacobs. 1993. Reconstructing argumentative discourse. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F.H., B. Garssen, E.C.W. Krabbe, A.F. Snock Henkemans, B. Verheij, and J.H.M. Wagemans. 2014. Handbook of argumentation theory. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilentz, S. 2009, July 14. Who Lincoln was and was not: The images and illusions of this momentous bicentenntial year. The New Republic. Retrieved January 18, 2018 from www.newrepublic.com.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Beth Innocenti.

Additional information

Fred Kauffeld: Deceased

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kauffeld, F.J., Innocenti, B. A Normative Pragmatic Theory of Exhorting. Argumentation 32, 463–483 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-018-9465-y

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10503-018-9465-y

Keywords

Navigation