Skip to main content
Log in

Institutional design and moral conflict in health care priority-setting

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Priority-setting policy-makers often face moral and political pressure to balance the conflicting motivations of efficiency and rescue/non-abandonment. Using the conflict between these motivations as a case study can enrich the understanding of institutional design in developed democracies. This essay presents a cognitive-psychological account of the conflict between efficiency and rescue/non-abandonment in health care priority-setting. It then describes three sets of institutional arrangements—in Australia, England/Wales, and Germany, respectively—that contend with this conflict in interestingly different ways. The analysis yields at least three implications for institutional design in developed democracies: (1) indeterminacy at the level of moral psychology can increase the probability of indeterminacy at the level of institutional design; (2) situational constraints in effect require priority-setting policy-makers to adopt normative-moral pluralism; and (3) the U.S. health care system may be in an anti-priority-setting equilibrium.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Efficiency has other, less prototypical forms as well, such as satisficing forms. Thus, a health care system that, for example, declines to provide unusually cost-ineffective treatments can be usefully understood as promoting efficiency, even if the system does not thereby maximize population health.

  2. Fojo and Grady (2009, 1045) reported that a drug called cetuximab could provide this health gain at a cost of about $80,000 (about $115,000 in 2024 dollars).

  3. For ease of exposition, the essay hereafter mostly omits the qualification about developed democracies. The reader may find it helpful to keep in mind that, if only because policy-makers in non-democratic regimes are less accountable to the public, they can more easily side-step goal conflicts by fiat.

  4. More precisely, this essay discusses a variant of CEA called “cost-utility analysis” (CUA). Collapsing the distinction between CEA and CUA is innocuous here, although the distinction matters in some more specialized contexts.

  5. The QALY is a construct that combines quantity and quality of life into a single measure by weighting the former by the latter. It ranks health states on a scale of zero (dead) to one (perfect health). To take two toy examples, suffering from rheumatoid arthritis (but being in perfect health otherwise) may receive a score of 0.90, and suffering from depression (perfect health otherwise) may receive a score of 0.85. The QALY allows a policy-maker to compare health gains across different disease areas. For example, a person who lives for one year in perfect health, for one year with rheumatoid arthritis, and for one year with depression gains 2.75 QALYs ((1.0 • 1) + (0.9 • 1) + (0.85 • 1) = 2.75).

  6. One World Health Organization working group (2014, 22) has deemed it “unacceptable” for a country such as Kenya to provide public funding for dialysis because “[m]oney spent on dialysis could instead save 300 times as many healthy life years if spent on tuberculosis control.” However one judges this argument’s merits, it is a moral argument.

  7. For a given individual and a given medical treatment, CEA is intrinsically interested only in the magnitude and duration of the treatment effect. It is not intrinsically interested in considerations such as the patient’s age or the quality of the patient’s life prior to treatment. As Nord (1999, 21–22) has noted, the specialists who first applied CEA to the health care context in the 1960s and 70s simply assumed a utilitarian social welfare function and thus stipulated that the social or aggregate value of a medical treatment was equal to the sum of the health gains that it produced in the people who received it. More recently, Nord (e.g., 2015) has proposed ways of integrating distributive moral considerations into the formal structure of CEA.

  8. Earlier exponents of similar views include, for instance, Eddy (1991), Gustavsson and Tinghög (2020), and Weale (2016).

  9. In presenting this hypothesis, I join the many researchers in psychology who have argued that the concrete-abstract distinction partly explains aspects of human moral mentation or behavior (e.g., Aguilar et al. 2013; Conway and Gawronski 2013; Kogut and Ritov 2015; Kvaran et al. 2013; Redelmeier and Tversky 1990).

  10. Much research in psychology, and especially in psycho-linguistics, suggests that abstract representation is generally more difficult and more effortful than is its concrete equivalent. For a discussion of some of this research, including citations, see Schwanenflugel (1991).

  11. Consider here that “opportunity cost neglect” seems to be a general feature of human cognition (e.g., Frederick et al. 2009). At least one research team (Persson and Tinghög 2020) has reported that even people with experience in health care priority-setting exhibit it.

  12. Consider here Jonsen’s (1986, 174) statement that “[e]ven the most evangelical utilitarian would find it difficult to expunge the rule of rescue from the psychological dynamics of technology assessors.”

  13. This does not mean that all specialists tend toward efficiency or that all laypersons tend toward rescue/non-abandonment.

  14. For example, in U.S. tort law, many specialists (e.g., judges, lawyers, legal economists) believe that the primary purpose of awarding punitive damages is to incentivize optimal deterrence, but most members of the public reject this view and believe that the primary purpose of doing so is to punish, in the retributive sense of that word (e.g., Sunstein et al. 2000).

  15. For a more detailed description of PBAC’s work, see, e.g., Whitty and Littlejohns (2015, 130).

  16. For a more detailed description of NICE’s work, see, e.g., Charlton (2020).

  17. Although NICE aims to produce more rather than fewer QALYs at a given cost, it is more accurate to state that the agency satisfices rather than maximizes in this regard (Rumbold et al. 2017, 113–14). For example, NICE “makes no effort to identify and prioritise those interventions that offer the least cost per QALY gain out of all those interventions that might be funded” (ibid., 113). The basic point here applies to health technology assessment agencies in other countries as well. No such agency maximizes QALYs in the strict sense of that word.

  18. The four drugs were bevacizumab, sorafenib, sunitinib, and temsirolimus. According to one researcher, NICE relied on the following ICERs: bevacizumab: £171,000 per QALY; sorafenib: £103,000 per QALY; sunitinib: £72,000 per QALY; temsirolimus: £103,000 per QALY (Raftery 2009, 271).

  19. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for emphasizing this point.

  20. Charlton (2022) has reported that another institutional design that NICE oversees—the Highly Specialised Technologies Programme, by which the agency evaluates drugs for very rare and very debilitating conditions—also sacrifices a degree of efficiency in a way that honors rescue/non-abandonment.

  21. For a more detailed description of IQWiG’s work, see, e.g., Wright et al. (2017, 72–73).

  22. More recently, IQWiG (2023, 112) seems to have moved away from EFA. For ease of exposition, however, this essay describes EFA in the present tense.

  23. The following description of EFA draws on Gandjour (2011).

  24. Consider here Kieslich’s (2012, 378) statement that “cost effectiveness considerations play a secondary role in health priority setting in Germany.”

  25. Consider here one research team’s (Wright et al. 2017, 74) statement that “the Efficiency Frontier offers the opportunity to make cost-effectiveness analysis. work in the German context without having to reveal willingness to pay.”

  26. One research team that interviewed German health policy-makers (Klingler et al. 2013, 275) attributed to them the view that “German methods for [health technology assessment] which rely on ad-hoc thresholds that have not to be set in advance, are less visible and therefore perhaps less politically problematic than fixed thresholds.”

  27. Consider here Luyten’s and Denier’s (2019, 162) statement that “explicit [cost-effectiveness] thresholds can prove to be counterproductive for sensible policy-making because people may simply ‘[not] want to know.’”

  28. Consider here Daniels’s and Sabin’s (2002, 2) statement that “no democratic society we are aware of has achieved consensus on. distributive principles for health care.”

  29. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for prompting me to make this point.

  30. This is not to deny that priority-setting policy-makers can apply in their work discrete ideas from one or another normative-moral theory.

  31. Consider here Jonsen’s (1986, 173) statement that “[m]odern health planners. . are not utilitarians in theory. But they are, to some extent, utilitarians in practice.”

  32. For a broader argument to the effect that restricted consequentialism does not accurately describe the work that priority-setting policy-makers do, see Wilson (2017, 159–60).

  33. The foregoing is not a criticism of Hausman, who does not argue that restricted consequentialism provides a general descriptor of the work of priority-setting policy-makers.

References

  • Afzali, Hossein Haji Ali et al. 2016. Should the Lambda (λ) Remain Silent? PharmacoEconomics 34: 323.

  • Aguilar, Pilar et al. 2013. Psychological Distance Increases Uncompromising Consequentialism. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 49: 449.

  • Alexander, Larry. 2000. Deontology at the Threshold. San Diego Law Review 37: 893.

  • Australian Government Department of Health, Guidelines for Preparing a Submission to the Pharmaceutical Benefits Advisory Committee, Version 5.0. 2016.

  • Brock, Dan. 2004. Ethical Issues in the Use of Cost-Effectiveness Analysis for the Prioritization of Health Resources. In Handbook of Bioethics: Taking Stock of the Field From a Philosophical Perspective, ed. George Khushf, 353.

  • Burki, Talha. 2018. From Health Service to National Identity: The NHS at 70. Lancet 392: 15.

  • Busschbach, Jan J. V. 1993. The Utility of Health at Different Stages in Life: A Quantitative Approach. Social Science and Medicine 37: 153.

  • Caro, J. Jaime et al. 2010. The Efficiency Frontier Approach to Economic Evaluation of Health-Care Interventions. Health Economics 19: 1117.

  • Chalkidou, Kalipso. 2012. Evidence and Values: Paying for End-of-Life Drugs in the British NHS. Health Economics, Policy and Law 7: 393.

  • Charlton, Victoria. 2020. NICE and Fair? Health Technology Assessment Policy Under the UK’s National Institute for Health and Care Excellence, 1999–2018. Health Care Analysis 28: 193.

  • Charlton, Victoria. 2022. Does NICE Apply the Rule of Rescue in Its Approach to Highly Specialised Technologies? Journal of Medical Ethics 48: 118.

  • Chim, Lesley et al. 2010. Are Cancer Drugs Less Likely to Be Recommended for Listing by the Pharmaceutical Benefits Advisory Committee in Australia? PharmacoEconomics 28: 463.

  • Choudhry, Niteesh et al. 1997. Distributional Dilemmas in Health Policy: Large Benefits for a Few or Smaller Benefits for Many? Journal of Health Services Research and Policy 2: 212.

  • Claxton, Karl et al. 2015a. Causes for Concern: Is NICE Failing to Uphold Its Responsibilities to All NHS Patients? Health Economics 24: 1.

  • Claxton, Karl et al. 2015b. Methods for the Estimation of the National Institute for Health and Care Excellence Cost-Effectiveness Threshold. Health Technology Assessment 19(14).

  • Collins, Marissa, and Nicholas Latimer. 2013. NICE’s End of Life Decision Making Scheme: Impact on Population Health. BMJ 346: 22.

  • Conway, Paul, and Bertram Gawronski. 2013. Deontological and Utilitarian Inclinations in Moral Decision Making: A Process Dissociation Approach. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 104: 216.

  • Cookson, Richard. 2013. Can the NICE End-of-Life Premium Be Given a Coherent Ethical Justification? Journal of Health Politics, Policy and Law 38: 1129.

  • Dakin, Helen et al. 2015. The Influence of Cost-Effectiveness and Other Factors on NICE Decisions. Health Economics 24: 1256.

  • Daniels, Norman. 1986. Why Saying No to Patients in the United States Is So Hard: Cost Containment, Justice, and Provider Autonomy. New England Journal of Medicine 314: 1380.

  • Daniels, Norman, and James E. Sabin. 2002. Setting Limits Fairly: Can We Learn to Share Medical Resources?

  • Davies, Simon P. 2005. Planning and Problem Solving in Well-Defined Domains. In The Cognitive Psychology of Planning, eds. Robin Morris and Geoff Ward, 35.

  • Eddy, David M. 1991. The Individual vs. Society: Is There a Conflict? Journal of the American Medical Association 265: 1446.

  • Ettelt, Stefanie. 2020. Access to Treatment and the Constitutional Right to Health in Germany: A Triumph of Hope Over Evidence? Health Economics, Policy, and Law 15: 30.

  • Fojo, Tito, and Christine Grady. 2009. How Much Is Life Worth? Cetuximab, Non-Small Cell Lung Cancer, and the $440 Billion Question. Journal of the National Cancer Institute 101: 1044.

  • Frederick, Shane et al. 2009. Opportunity Cost Neglect. Journal of Consumer Research 36: 553.

  • Gandjour, Afschin. 2011. Germany’s Decision Rule for Setting Ceiling Prices of Drugs: A Comparative Analysis With Other Decision Rules. Applied Health Economics and Health Policy 9: 65.

  • Gerber-Grote, Andreas et al. 2014. Decision Making in Germany: Is Health Economic Evaluation as a Supporting Tool a Sleeping Beauty? Zeitschrift für Evidenz, Fortbildung und Qualität im Gesundheitswesen 108: 390.

  • Gustavsson, Erik, and Gustav Tinghög. 2020. Needs and Cost-Effectiveness in Health Care Priority Setting. Health and Technology 10: 611.

  • Ham, Chris, and Glenn Robert. 2003. Conclusions. In Reasonable Rationing: International Experience of Priority Setting in Health Care, eds. Chris Ham and Glenn Robert, 141.

  • Harris, Anthony H. 2008. The Role of Value for Money in Public Insurance Coverage Decisions for Drugs in Australia: A Retrospective Analysis 1994–2004. Medical Decision Making 28: 713.

  • Hausman, Daniel M. 2015. Valuing Health: Well-Being, Freedom, and Suffering.

  • Institute for Quality and Efficiency in Health Care, General Methods for the Assessment of the Relation of Benefits to Costs, Version 1.0. 2009.

  • Institute for Quality and Efficiency in Health Care, General Methods, Version 7.0. 2023.

  • Jonsen, Albert R. 1986. Bentham in a Box: Technology Assessment and Health Care Allocation. Law, Medicine, and Health Care 14: 172.

  • Karlsberg Schaffer, Sarah et al. 2016. Opportunity Costs and Local Health Service Spending Decisions: A Qualitative Study From Wales. BMC Health Services Research 16: 103.

  • Kieslich, Katharina. 2012. Social Values and Health Priority Setting in Germany. Journal of Health Organization and Management 26: 374.

  • Kieslich, Katharina. 2020. Paradigms in Operation: Explaining Pharmaceutical Benefit Assessment Outcomes in England and Germany. Health Economics, Policy, and Law 15: 370.

  • Klingler, Corinna et al. 2013. Regulatory Space and the Contextual Mediation of Common Functional Pressures: Analyzing the Factors That Led to the German Efficiency Frontier Approach. Health Policy 109: 270.

  • Kogut, Tehila, and Ilana Ritov. 2015. Target Dependent Ethics: Discrepancies Between Ethical Decisions Toward Specific and General Targets. Current Opinion in Psychology 6: 145.

  • Kohn, Rachel et al. 2011. Rule of Rescue or the Good of the Many? An Analysis of Physicians’ and Nurses’ Preferences for Allocating ICU Beds. Intensive Care Medicine 37: 1210.

  • Kvaran, Trevor et al. 2013. The Effect of Analytic and Experiential Modes of Thought on Moral Judgment. Progress in Brain Research 202: 187.

  • Landwehr, Claudia, and Dorothea Klinnert. 2015. Value Congruence in Health Care Priority Setting: Social Values, Institutions, and Decisions in Three Countries. Health Economics, Policy, and Law 10: 113.

  • Luyten, Jeroen, and Yvonne Denier. 2019. Explicit Cost-Effectiveness Thresholds in Health Care: A Kaleidoscope. Social Justice Research 32: 155.

  • Lybrand, Sean, and Michael Wonder. 2020. Analysis of PBAC Submissions and Outcomes for Medicines (2010–2018). International Journal of Technology Assessment in Health Care 36: 224.

  • Mariner, Wendy K. 1995. Rationing Health Care and the Need for Credible Scarcity: Why Americans Can’t Say No. American Journal of Public Health 85: 1439.

  • Nadler, Eric et al. 2006. Do Oncologists Believe New Cancer Drugs Offer Good Value? Oncologist 11: 90.

  • Nagel, Thomas. 1979. Mortal Questions.

  • National Institute for Health and Care Excellence, Guide to the Methods of Technology Appraisal. 2013.

  • National Institute for Health and Clinical Excellence, Appraising Life-Extending, End of Life Treatments. 2009.

  • National Institute for Health and Clinical Excellence, Value Based Assessment of Health Technologies. 2014.

  • Nord, Erik. 1993. The Relevance of Health State After Treatment in Prioritising Between Different Patients. Journal of Medical Ethics 19: 37.

  • Nord, Erik. 1999. Cost-Value Analysis in Health Care: Making Sense Out of QALYS.

  • Nord, Erik. 2015. Cost-Value Analysis of Health Interventions: Introduction and Update on Methods and Preference Data. PharmacoEconomics 33: 89.

  • Nord, Erik et al. 1995. Who Cares About Cost? Does Economic Analysis Impose or Reflect Social Values? Health Policy 34: 79.

  • Orr, Shepley, and Jonathan Wolff. 2015. Reconciling Cost-Effectiveness With the Rule of Rescue: The Institutional Division of Moral Labour. Theory and Decision 78: 525.

  • Paulden, Mike. 2017. Recent Amendments to NICE’s Value-Based Assessment of Health Technologies: Implicitly Inequitable? Expert Review of Pharmacoeconomics and Outcomes Research 17: 239.

  • Persson, Emil, and Gustav Tinghög. 2020. Opportunity Cost Neglect in Public Policy. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization 170: 301.

  • Prasad, Vinay et al. 2017. The High Price of Anticancer Drugs: Origins, Implications, Barriers, Solutions. Nature Reviews Clinical Oncology 14: 381.

  • Raftery, James. 2009. NICE and the Challenge of Cancer Drugs. BMJ 338: 271.

  • Rand, Leah Z., and Aaron S. Kesselheim. 2020. An International Review of Health Technology Assessment Approaches to Prescription Drugs and Their Ethical Principles. Journal of Law, Medicine, and Ethics 48: 583.

  • Rawlins, Michael, and Andrew Dillon. 2005. NICE Discrimination. Journal of Medical Ethics 31: 683.

  • Redelmeier, Donald A., and Amos Tversky. 1990. Discrepancy Between Medical Decisions for Individual Patients and for Groups. New England Journal of Medicine 322: 1162.

  • Rittel, Horst. 1972. On the Planning Crisis: Systems Analysis of the First and Second Generations. Bedriftsøkonomen 8: 390.

  • Rumbold, Benedict et al. 2017. Public Reasoning and Health-Care Priority Setting: The Case of NICE. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 27: 107.

  • Sandmann, Frank et al. 2013. Factors That Led to the Implementation of the Efficiency Frontier Approach in Health Economic Evaluation in Germany: Do Not Avoid the Elephant in the Room. Health Policy 112: 297.

  • Sandmann, Frank G. et al. 2018. The Efficiency-Frontier Approach for Health Economic Evaluation Versus Cost-Effectiveness Thresholds and Internal Reference Pricing: Combining the Best of Both Worlds? Expert Review of Pharmacoeconomics and Outcomes Research 18: 475.

  • Schwanenflugel, Paula J. 1991. Why Are Abstract Concepts Hard to Understand? In The Psychology of Word Meanings, ed. Paula J. Schwanenflugel, 223.

  • Sibbald, Shannon L. et al. 2009. Priority Setting: What Constitutes Success? A Conceptual Framework for Successful Priority Setting. BMC Health Services Research 9: 43.

  • Smith, Neale et al. 2014. A Politics of Priority Setting: Ideas, Interests, and Institutions in Healthcare Resource Allocation. Public Policy and Administration 29: 331.

  • Steinbrook, Robert. 2008. Saying No Isn’t NICE—The Travails of Britain’s National Institute for Health and Clinical Excellence. New England Journal of Medicine 359: 1977.

  • Sunstein, Cass R. et al. 2000. Do People Want Optimal Deterrence? Journal of Legal Studies 29: 237.

  • Thokala, Praveen et al. 2020. HTA’d in the USA: A Comparison of ICER in the United States with NICE in England and Wales. Journal of Managed Care and Specialty Pharmacy 26: 1162.

  • Ubel, Peter A. 1999. How Stable Are People’s Preferences for Giving Priority to Severely Ill Patients? Social Science and Medicine 49: 895.

  • Ubel, Peter A., and George Loewenstein. 1996. Distributing Scarce Livers: The Moral Reasoning of the General Public. Social Science and Medicine 42: 1049.

  • Ubel, Peter A. et al. 1996. Cost-Effectiveness Analysis in a Setting of Budget Constraints: Is It Equitable? New England Journal of Medicine 334: 1174.

  • Waxman, Jonathan. 2008. Arrogant, Illogical and Totally out of Touch, NICE Must Be Scrapped. It’s Killing Too Many People, MailOnline, Aug. 12.

  • Weale, Albert. 2016. The Path From Nowhere. Health Economics, Policy and Law 11: 97.

  • Whitty, Jennifer A., and Peter Littlejohns. 2015. Social Values and Health Priority Setting in Australia: An Analysis Applied to the Context of Health Technology Assessment. Health Policy 119: 127.

  • Williams, Alan. 2004. What Could Be Nicer Than NICE?

  • Wilson, James. 2017. Public Value, Maximization, and Health Policy: An Examination of Hausman’s Restricted Consequentialism. Public Health Ethics 10: 157.

  • World Health Organization (Consultative Group on Equity and Universal Health Coverage). 2014. Making Fair Choices on the Path to Universal Health Coverage.

  • Wright, John S. F. et al. 2017. Convergence, Divergence, and Hybridity: A Regulatory Governance Perspective on Health Technology Assessment in England and Germany. Global Policy 8: 69.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Howard Eichenblatt and to the anonymous reviewers for this journal for valuable comments about this article.

Funding

Not applicable.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Philip Petrov.

Ethics declarations

Competing interests

The author has no competing interests to declare.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Petrov, P. Institutional design and moral conflict in health care priority-setting. Med Health Care and Philos (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-024-10201-2

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-024-10201-2

Keywords

Navigation