Advertisement

Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy

, Volume 18, Issue 1, pp 23–32 | Cite as

Unequal treatment of human research subjects

  • David B. ResnikEmail author
Scientific Contribution

Abstract

Unequal treatment of human research subjects is a significant ethical concern, because justice in research involving human subjects requires equal protection of rights and equal protection from harm and exploitation. Disputes sometimes arise concerning the issue of unequal treatment of research subjects. Allegedly unequal treatment occurs when subjects are treated differently and there is a genuine dispute concerning the appropriateness of equal treatment. Patently unequal treatment occurs when subjects are treated differently and there is not a genuine dispute about the appropriateness of equal treatment. Allegedly unequal treatment will probably always occur in research with human subjects due to disagreements about fundamental questions of justice. The best way to deal with allegedly unequal treatment is to promote honest and open discussions of the issues at stake. Research regulations can help to minimize patently unequal treatment by providing rules for investigators, ethical review boards, institutions, and sponsors to follow. However, patently unequal treatment may still occur because the regulations are subject to interpretation. Federal agencies have provided interpretive guidance that can help promote consistent review and oversight of human subjects research. Additional direction may be needed on topics that are not adequately covered by current guidance or regulations. International guidelines can help promote equal treatment of human subjects around the globe. While minor variations in the treatment of research subjects should be tolerated and even welcomed, major ones (i.e. those that significantly impact human rights or welfare) should be avoided or minimized.

Keywords

Human subjects research Justice Equal treatment Ethics Regulation 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Bruce Androphy for helpful comments. This research supported by the National Institute of Environmental Health Sciences (NIEHS), National Institutes of Health (NIH). It does not represent the views of the NIEHS or NIH.

References

  1. Afifi, R.Y. 2007. Biomedical research ethics: An Islamic view part II. International Journal of Surgery 5(6): 381–383.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Angell, M. 1997. The ethics of clinical research in the third world. New England Journal of Medicine 337(12): 847–849.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Aristotle. (2003) [350 BCE]. Nichomachean ethics, ed. H. Tredennick, Transl. J.A. Thomson. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  4. Ballantyne, A.J. 2010. How to do research fairly in an unjust world. American Journal of Bioethics 10(6): 26–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Barnes, B. 1996. Justice as impartiality. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Berlin, I. 1955/1956. Equality. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 56: 301–326.Google Scholar
  7. Bonham, V., and J. Moreno. 2011. Research with captive populations: Prisoners, students, and soldiers. In The Oxford textbook of clinical research ethics, ed. E.J. Emanuel, C. Grady, R.A. Crouch, R.K. Lie, F.G. Miller, and D. Wendler, 461–474. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Brandt, R.B. 1992. Morality, utilitarianism, and rights. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Carr, C.L. 1981. The concept of formal justice. Philosophical Studies 39(3): 211–226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Council for International Organizations of Medical Sciences. 2002. International ethical guidelines for biomedical research involving human subjects. http://www.cioms.ch/publications/layout_guide2002.pdf. Accessed 17 Dec 2013.
  11. Department of Health and Human Services. 2009. Protection of human subjects. 45 CFR 46. http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/humansubjects/guidance/45cfr46.html. Accessed 15 Dec 2013.
  12. Dworkin, R. 2000. Sovereign virtue: The theory and practice of equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Emanuel, E.J., D. Wendler, and C. Grady. 2000. What makes clinical research ethical? Journal of the American Medical Association 283(20): 2701–2711.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Emerson, R.W. 1841. Self-reliance. http://www.emersoncentral.com/selfreliance.htm. Accessed 15 Apr 2014.
  15. Feinberg, J. 1987. Harm to others. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Food and Drug Administration. 2012. Information Sheet Guidance for Institutional Review Boards (IRBs), Clinical investigators, and sponsors. http://www.fda.gov/ScienceResearch/SpecialTopics/RunningClinicalTrials/GuidancesInformationSheetsandNotices/ucm113709.htm. Accessed: 15 Dec 2013.
  17. Food and Drug Administration. 2013a. Institutional Review Boards. 21 CFR 56. http://www.accessdata.fda.gov/scripts/cdrh/cfdocs/cfcfr/CFRSearch.cfm?CFRPart=56. Accessed 15 Dec 2013.
  18. Food and Drug Administration. 2013b. Protection of Human Subjects. 21 CFR 50. http://www.accessdata.fda.gov/scripts/cdrh/cfdocs/cfcfr/CFRSearch.cfm?CFRPart=50. Accessed 15 Dec 2013.
  19. Glickman, S.W., N. Ndubuizu, K.P. Weinfurt, C.D. Hamilton, L.T. Glickman, K.A. Schulman, and C.B. Cairns. 2011. Perspective: The case for research justice: inclusion of patients with limited English proficiency in clinical research. Academic Medicine 86(3): 389–393.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Gold, J.L., and C.S. Dewa. 2005. Institutional review boards and multisite studies in health services research: is there a better way? Health Services Research 40: 291–307.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Goodin, R.E. 1985. Protecting the vulnerable: A reanalysis of our social responsibilities. Chicago: Universityof Chicago Pres.Google Scholar
  22. Gosepath, S. 2007. Equality. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/equality/. Accessed 6 Dec 2013.
  23. Grady, C. 2005. Payment of clinical research subjects. Journal of Clinical Investigation 115(7): 1681–1687.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Grady, C., and C. Denny. 2011. Research involving women. In The Oxford textbook of clinical research ethics, ed. E.J. Emanuel, C. Grady, R.A. Crouch, R.K. Lie, F.G. Miller, and D. Wendler, 407–422. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Grady, C., N. Dickert, T. Jawetz, G. Gensler, and E.J. Emanuel. 2005. An analysis of U.S. practices of paying research participants. Contemporary Clinical Trials 26(3): 365–375.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Green, L.A., J.C. Lowery, C.P. Kowalski, and L. Wyszewianski. 2006. Impact of institutional review board practice variation on observational health services research. Health Services Research 41: 214–230.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Iltis, A. 2007. Pediatric research posing a minor increase over minimal risk and no prospect of direct benefit: challenging 45 CFR 46.406. Accountability in Research 14(1): 19–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Jansen, L.A., and S. Wall. 2013. Rethinking exploitation: A process-centered account. Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 23(4): 381–410.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Klitzman, R. 2011. How local IRBs view central IRBs in the US. BMC Medical Ethics 12: 13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Kopelman, L.M. 2000. Moral problems in assessing research risk. IRB 22(5): 7–10.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Krogstad, D.J., S. Diop, A. Diallo, F. Mzayek, J. Keating, O.A. Koita, and Y.T. Touré. 2010. Informed consent in international research: The rationale for different approaches. American Journal of Tropical Medicine and Hygiene 83(4): 743–747.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Levine, R.J. 1988. Ethics and regulation of clinical research, 2nd ed. New Haven: Yale University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Levine, R.J. 1991. Informed consent: Some challenges to the universal validity of Western model. Law, Medicine and Health Care 19: 107–213.Google Scholar
  34. Lurie, P., and S.M. Wolfe. 1997. Unethical trials of interventions to reduce perinatal transmission of the human immunodeficiency virus in developing countries. New England Journal of Medicine 337(12): 853–856.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Mansbach, J., U. Acholonu, S. Clark, and C.A. Camargo Jr. 2007. Variation in institutional review board responses to a standard, observational, pediatric research protocol. Academic Emergency Medicine 14: 377–380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Marshall, P.A. 2006. Informed consent in international health research. Journal of Empirical Research on Human Research Ethics 1(1): 25–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Martinson, B.C., M.S. Anderson, A.L. Crain, and R. de Vries. 2006. Scientists’ perceptions of organizational justice and self-reported misbehaviors. Journal of Empirical Research on Human Research Ethics 1(1): 51–66.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Mastroianni, A., and J. Kahn. 2001. Swinging on the pendulum. Shifting views of justice in human subjects research. Hastings Center Report 31(3): 21–28.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. McWilliams, R., J. Hoover-Fong, A. Hamosh, S. Beck, T. Beaty, and G. Cutting. 2003. Problematic variation in local institutional review of a multicenter genetic epidemiology study. Journal of the American Medical Association 290: 360–366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Mill, J.S. 2003 [1859, 1863]. Utilitarianism and on liberty. New York: Wiley-Blackwell.Google Scholar
  41. Muniyappa, R., S. Lee, H. Chen, and M.J. Quon. 2008. Current approaches for assessing insulin sensitivity and resistance in vivo: Advantages, limitations, and appropriate usage. American Journal of Physiology, Endocrinology, and Metabolism 294(1): E15–E26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. National Bioethics Advisory Commission. 1998. Research Involving Persons with Mental Disorders that May Affect Decisionmaking Capacity. https://bioethicsarchive.georgetown.edu/nbac/capacity/TOC.htm. Accessed 19 Apr 2014.
  43. National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. 1979. The Belmont report: Ethical principles and guidelines for the protection of human subjects of research. Washington, DC: Department of Health, Education, and Welfare. http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/humansubjects/guidance/belmont.html. Accessed 6 Dec 2013.
  44. Nielsen, K. 1979. Radical egalitarian justice: Justice as equality. Social Theory and Practice 5(2): 209–226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Nozick, R. 1975. Anarchy, state, utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  46. Office of Human Research Protections. 2013a. Policy and guidance. http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/policy/index.html. Accessed: 14 Dec 2013.
  47. Office of Human Research Protections. 2013b. 2014 Edition of the International Compilation of Human Research Standards. http://www.hhs.gov/ohrp/international/intlcompilation/2014intlcomp.doc.doc. Accessed 15 Dec 2013.
  48. Pike, E.R. 2014. In need of remedy: US policy for compensating injured research participants. Journal of Medical Ethics 40(13): 182–185.Google Scholar
  49. Rawls, J. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  50. Rawls, J. 1993. Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  51. Resnik, D.B. 1998. The ethics of HIV research in developing nations. Bioethics 12(4): 285–306.Google Scholar
  52. Resnik, D.B. 2003. Exploitation in biomedical research. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics 24(3): 233–259.Google Scholar
  53. Resnik, D.B. 2005. Eliminating the daily life risks standard of minimal risk. Journal of Medical Ethics 31(1): 35–38.Google Scholar
  54. Resnik, D.B. 2012. Centralized institutional review boards: Assessing the arguments and evidence. Journal of Clinical Research Best Practices 8(11): 1–13.Google Scholar
  55. Resnik, D.B., G. Babson, and G.E. Dinse. 2012. Minor changes to previously approved research: a study of IRB policies. IRB 34(4): 9–14.Google Scholar
  56. Resnik, D.B., E. Parasidis, K. Carroll, J.M. Evans, E.R. Pike, and G.E. Kissling. 2014. Research-related injury compensation policies of U.S. research institutions. IRB 36(1): 12–20.Google Scholar
  57. Rhodes, R. 2005. Justice in medicine and public health. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 14(1): 13–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Rhodes, R. 2010. Rethinking research ethics. American Journal of Bioethics 10(10): 19–36.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Rhodes, R., M.P. Battin, and A. Silvers. 2002. Medicine and social justice. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  60. Sandel, M.J. (ed.). 2007. Justice: A reader. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  61. Sen, A. 2011. The idea of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  62. Shah, S., A. Whittle, B. Wilfond, G. Gensler, and D. Wendler. 2004. How do institutional review boards apply the federal risk and benefit standards for pediatric research? Journal of the American Medical Association 291(4): 476–482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Silberman, G., and K.L. Kahn. 2011. Burdens on research imposed by institutional review boards: The state of the evidence and its implications for regulatory reform. Milbank Quarterly 89: 599–627.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  64. Snyder, J., C.L. Miller, and G. Gray. 2011. Relative versus absolute standards for everyday risk in adolescent HIV prevention trials: Expanding the debate. American Journal of Bioethics 11(6): 5–13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  65. Stark, A.R., J.E. Tyson, and P.L. Hibberd. 2010. Variation among institutional review boards in evaluating the design of a multicenter randomized trial. Journal of Perinatology 30(3): 163–169.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  66. Varmus, H., and D. Satcher. 1997. Ethical complexities of conducting research in developing countries. New England Journal of Medicine 337(12): 1000–1005.Google Scholar
  67. World Medical Association. 2013. Declaration of Helsinki: Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving Human Subjects, 2013 revision. http://www.wma.net/en/30publications/10policies/b3/. Accessed: 17 Dec 2013.

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.National Institute of Environmental Health SciencesNational Institutes of HealthResearch Triangle ParkUSA

Personalised recommendations