Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Taking health needs seriously: against a luck egalitarian approach to justice in health

  • Scientific Contribution
  • Published:
Medicine, Health Care and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In recent works, Shlomi Segall suggests and defends a luck egalitarian approach to justice in health. Concurring with G. A. Cohen’s mature position he defends the idea that people should be compensated for “brute luck”, i.e. the outcome of actions that it would be unreasonable to expect them to avoid. In his defense of the luck egalitarian approach he seeks to rebut the criticism raised by Norman Daniels that luck egalitarianism is in some way too narrow and in another too wide to uphold justice in health and health care distribution. He points out that a pluralistic outline of luck egalitarianism taking into account the moral requirement of meeting everyone’s basic needs can avoid this line of criticism. In this article I argue against the application of such pluralistic luck egalitarianism in matters of health distribution. First of all, Segall has not shown that luck egalitarianism handles well health distributions above a threshold of basic needs. Secondly, his way of avoiding Elizabeth Anderson’s abandonment objection is theoretically problematic. Finally, I argue that luck egalitarianism in general fails to acknowledge the moral foundation of health and health care as a basic human entitlement. Thus I conclude that luck egalitarianism fails to take health needs seriously and that it cannot therefore uphold justice in health.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This means that there is a case for a luck egalitarian tiebreak if patients are perfectly equal in terms of their lack of basic needs but differs even to the smallest degree in responsibility, and if patients are almost equal in terms of their lack of basic needs but sufficiently different in terms of their degree of responsibility. To see this, consider two cases, A and B. In A, two patients are equally in lack of basic needs (−100; −100) but differ only slightly in terms of responsibility (100; 99). Due to the perfect equality of neediness, the slight difference in responsibility would be a tiebreaker. In B, two patients are almost equal in terms of their lack of basic needs (−100; −99) but differ to a significant degree with respect to responsibility (100; 0). The large difference in the degree of responsibility might possibly outweigh the small difference in neediness and could therefore be a tiebreaker. It seems as though both A and B could be cases for a luck egalitarian tiebreak.

  2. Some might find this a rather strange outline of luck egalitarianism, since it seems to imply that we ought to fund treatment for disadvantages that everybody suffers due to reasons beyond their control. However, this seems to ignore the relative aspect that we do normally ascribe to luck egalitarianism. To avoid this ignorance, I choose to read “disadvantageous” interpersonally.

  3. In fact, I suggest a capability-based understanding of normal functioning, also taking social disabilities into account. See Nussbaum (2000) and Sen (1985).

  4. Some claim that since this is an inevitable trade-off between an innocent and a reckless patient, it is in fact not harsh at all. I take this to be a valid point but will set it aside for now, since Segall himself finds this to be too harsh (Segall 2010a, p. 71).

  5. In fact, I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for pointing out that if this was the case of my argument, it would be dogmatic.

References

  • Anderson, E. 1999. What is the point of equality? Ethics 109: 287–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arneson, R.J. 2000. Luck egalitarianism and prioritarianism. Ethics 110: 339–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, A., D.W. Brock, N. Daniels, and D. Wikler. 2000. From chance to choice: Genetics and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G.A. 1989. On the currency of egalitarian justice. Ethics 99(4): 906–944.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G.A. 2004. Expensive taste rides again. In Dworkin and his critics, ed. J. Burley, 3–29. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, G.A. 2008. Rescuing justice and equality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. 2008. Just health: Meeting health needs fairly. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniels, N. 2009. Just health: Replies and further thoughts. Journal of Medical Ethics 35: 36–41.

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Darwall, S. 2002. Welfare and rational care. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 1981. What is equality? Part II: Equality of resources. Philosophy & Public Affairs 10(3): 185–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. 1971. Legal paternalism. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 1(1): 105–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. 1987. The moral limits of the criminal law volume 1: Harm to others. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J. 2007. Enhancing evolution: The ethical case for making better people. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. 1997. What kind of equality should the Left pursue? In Equality, ed. J. Franklin, 83–99. London: Institute for Public Policy Research.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M.C. 2000. Women and human development. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1999. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T.M. 1975. Preference and urgency. The Journal of Philosophy 72(19): 655–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segall, S. 2010a. Health, luck, and justice. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Segall, S. 2010b. Is health (really) special? Health policy between Rawlsian and luck egalitarian justice. Journal of Applied Philosophy 27(4): 344–358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. 1985. Well-being, agency and freedom: The Dewey Lectures 1984. The Journal of Philosophy 82(4): 169–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Voigt, K. 2007. The harshness objection: is luck egalitarianism too harsh on the victims of option luck? Ethical Theory and Moral Practice 10: 389–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am very grateful to Shlomi Segall, Nir Eyal, Zofia Stemplowska, Matthew Clayton, Robert van der Veen, Kasper Lippert-Rasmussen, Søren Flinch Midtgaard, David Vestergaard Axelsen, Rasmus Sommer Hansen, Per Mouritsen, Tore Vincent Olsen and Morten Brænder for their useful comments on earlier versions of this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lasse Nielsen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Nielsen, L. Taking health needs seriously: against a luck egalitarian approach to justice in health. Med Health Care and Philos 16, 407–416 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-012-9399-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11019-012-9399-3

Keywords

Navigation