Skip to main content
Log in

Idealized Models as Selective Representations

  • Article
  • Published:
Journal for General Philosophy of Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper calls into question one fundamental claim at the basis of an alleged puzzle for veritistic accounts of the value of idealized models: the claim that idealized models cannot be veridical representations of the world. Catherine Elgin has argued that the value of idealized models can only be explained if we construe them as exemplars, which do not represent the world. I argue that Elgin’s proposal is problematic and cannot accommodate central cases of idealization. Nevertheless, there is value in Elgin’s proposal. I rescue her notion of selectiveness in exemplification and incorporate it within a revised account of representation. I provide independent motivation in favour of a form of veritism, which motivates a revision of Elgin’s case against it. I argue that an account based on selective representation has the resources to rescue veritism from the problems raised by Elgin. In the proposal I advance, idealized models are literally veridical representations of the world.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See specially Elgin (2006; 2007; 2009).

  2. I present veritism as identifying veridicality, and not truth, as the fundamental aim of cognition because I want to leave open the possibility of epistemic achievements which do not have propositional (nor conceptual) content, but which do have content with veridicality conditions. For instance, perceptual experiences according to some philosophers (see Dretske (2003), Siegel (2010)). On this view, perceptions can be construed as epistemically valuable by virtue of representing the world veridically.

  3. See Goldman (2001; 1999, especially Ch. 1), for a defence of veritism and a response to a series of objections. See also Alston (2005) for a defence of veritism and a discussion of the different relations to veridicality mentioned here. See also Grimm (2008) for a critical discussion of some of the ideas advanced by Goldman and Alston.

  4. Barberousse and Ludwig (2009, 57), explicitly defend such position.

  5. See Pappas and Swain (1978, 14) for a formulation of the principle along these lines.

  6. See Shope (1983), and Pappas and Swain (1978).

  7. However, this kind of position counts with many actual defenders, independently motivated. For instance, prominently, Bas van Fraassen (1980) has argued in favour of a similar position on entirely independent grounds.

  8. As it will become clear, I do not set aside this worry because I think it is unimportant. Below, I will seek to defend a kind of veritism that explains the value of idealized models without renouncing to the possibility that using idealized models might provide us with knowledge of the phenomena represented by them.

  9. See McMullin (1985), and Weisberg (2007b).

  10. See, for instance, the majority of the essays in Suárez (2009).

  11. See Mizrahi (2012, 241-242) Elgin (2017, 15).

  12. Similar claims can be found in Elgin (2006, 209; 2009, 84; 2017, 14–15, 25–27).

  13. See Elgin (2017, 27–32).

  14. An important source of inspiration for Elgin with respect to these issues is Nancy Cartwright’s work. See Cartwright (1983), especially “Do the Laws of Physics State the Facts?”

  15. See Elgin (2017, 25–27).

  16. Although there are other legitimate uses of “understand”, Elgin’s focus is on objectual understanding, for this seems to be the relevant kind of understanding in scientific practice. Other kinds of understanding include understanding a person; or propositional understanding, such as understanding that something is the case. See Elgin (2017, 33–45).

  17. See Elgin (2007, 39; 2017, 43 − 44).

  18. For discussions on understanding and whether or not it requires truth see Zagzebski (2001), Pritchard (2009), and Kvanvig (2003).

  19. In Sect. 3.3 I explore Michael Strevens (2017) account of understanding. A case can be made for thinking that his view would fall under this category.

  20. See Elgin (2009, 81; 2017, 184–191).

  21. See Elgin (2017, 186-188).

  22. Borges (1975). For philosophical discussion of this story by Borges see Frigg and Nguyen (2017, 52) and Boesch (2019, 5500-5501).

  23. See Elgin (2009, 82 − 83).

  24. This example plays a similar role in Elgin (2009, 81; 2017, 187-188).

  25. The point is merely that abstracta cannot instantiate certain (physical) properties. A fact which might be partly explained by their not being spatio-temporal. This is perfectly consistent with the claim that concreta can, and often do, instantiate abstract properties.

  26. I would like to thank an anonymous reviewer for bringing this important point to my attention.

  27. I thank two anonymous reviewers for this journal for calling my attention to this important point.

  28. See Teller (2008).

  29. I thank an anonymous reviewer for calling my attention to this important point.

  30. Of course, these observations are consistent with the fact that measuring instruments get better as technology advances and that human interference might be abolished by technological improvements, or diminished by practice and care.

  31. On the issue of inexactitude in measurement see Tal (2013) and Chang (2004).

  32. Of course, there might be some specific very strong construals of representation, which make it impossible for any representation to be absolutely precise and exact. Think of a construal of representations according to which a concrete representation needs to occupy the same space occupied by the target phenomena represented. For a defense of the claim that the notion of an absolutely precise and exact representation seems to be logically consistent See Teller (2009; 2008, 437).

  33. Similar examples and issues are discussed by Austin in (1962b, 143; 1950; 1979).

  34. Austin’s own view in the matter of truth is much more complex and subtle tan these quotations (and my discussion of them here) might suggest. See Longworth (2013) for a discussion of the potential ways in which Austin’s view on truth could be fleshed out.

  35. See Van Fraassen (2008) for a similar position.

  36. For useful discussion of the underground example see Contessa (2011, 127 − 130) and Bolinska (2013, 230).

  37. Whether and how an aspect is distorted might respond to desiderata outside the verististic framework, such as simplicity or convinience.

  38. In addition, the model is explicitly advanced as a representation which applies under “normal conditions”. At least in this respect the selectivity of the representation is made explicit.

  39. I thank two anonymous reviewers for calling my attention to this important point.

References

  • Achinstein, Peter. 1983. The Nature of Explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alston, William P. 2005. Beyond Justification. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austing: John L. 1950. Truth. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Supplementary Volume XXIV:111–128. Reprinted in Austin 1979, Philosophical Papers, 3rd ed., J.O. Urmson and G.J. Warnock (eds.), London Oxford University Press.

  • Austin, J. L. 1962a. How to do Things with Words, 2nd ed., M. Sbisà and J.O.Urmson (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975.

  • Austin, J. L. 1962b. Sense and Sensibilia, reconstructed from the manuscript notes by G.J. Warnock, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Austin, J. L. 1979. Unfair to Facts. In Philosophical Papers, 3rd ed., J.O. Urmson and G.J. Warnock (eds.), Oxford University Press.

  • Barberousse, Anouk, and Pascal Ludwig. 2009. Models as Fictions. In Fictions in Science. Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealizations. Mauricio Suárez (ed.), New York: Routledge.

  • Boesch, Brandon. 2019. Scientific Representation and Dissimilarity. Synthese 198: 5496–5513.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bokulich, Alisa. 2016. "Fiction as a Vehicle for Truth: Moving Beyond the Ontic Conception," The Monist?99 (3):260-279.

  • Bolinska, Agnes. 2013. Epistemic Representation, Informativeness and the Aim of Faithful Representation. Synthese 190: 219–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borges, Jorge Luis. 1975. On Exactitude in Science. In A Universal History of Infamy, translated by Norman Thomas de Giovanni, London: Penguin Books.

  • Cartwright, Nancy. 1983. How the Laws of Physics Lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, Hasok. 2004. Inventing Temperature: Measurement and Scientific Progress. Oxford University Press.

  • Contessa, Gabriele. 2011. “Scientific Models and Representation. In The Continuum Compation to the Philosophy of Science, Steven French, and Juha Saatsi, (eds.), London: Continuum. 120–137.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, Fred. 2003. Experience as Representation. Philosophical Issues 13: 67–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, Catherine Z. 2006. From Knowledge to Understanding. In Epistemology Futures, Stephen Hetherington (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press. 199–215.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, Catherine Z. 2007. Understanding and the Facts. Philosophical Studies 132: 33–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, Catherine Z. 2009. Exemplification, Idealization and Scientific Understanding. In Fictions in Science. Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealizations, ed. Mauricio Suárez, New York: Routledge. 77–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, Catherine. 2017. True Enough. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, Roman, and James Nguyen. 2017. Models and Representation. In Lorenzo Magnani and Tommaso New York Bertolotti (eds.), Springer Handbook of Model-Based Science.

  • Frigg, Roman, and James Nguyen. 2021. Mirrors without Warning. Synthese 198: 2427–2447.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, Edmund. 1963. Is Justified True Belief Knowledge. Analysis 23 (6): 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, Alvin I. 1999. Knowledge in a Social World. Oxford: Clarendon Press; New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, Alvin I. 2001. The Unity of Epistemic Virtues. In Virtue Epistemology. Essays on Epistemic Virtue and Responsibility, eds. Linda Zagzebsky, and Arbor Fairweather, New York: Oxford University Press. 30–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, Stephen R. 2008. Epistemic Goals and Epistemic Values. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77 (3): 725–744.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knuuttila, Tarja, and Andrea Loettgers. 2016. Modelling as Indirect Representation? The Lotka-Volterra Model Revisited. British Journal For the Philosophy of Science 0: 2017. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 68(4):1007-1036..

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, Jonathan. 2003. The Value of Knowledge and the Pursuit of Understanding. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lawler, Insa. 2021. Scientific Understanding and Felicitous Legitimate Falsehoods. Synthese 198: 6859–6887.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Le Bihan, Soazig. 2021. Partial Truths versus Felicitous Falsehoods, Synthese 198:5415–5436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lipton, Peter. 2009. “Understanding without Explanation”. Scientific Understanding: Philosophical Perspectives. Eds. Henk W. de Regt, Sabina Leonelli, and Kai Eigner (eds.), Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. 43–63.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longworth, Guy. 2013. John Langshaw Austin. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2015 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/austin-jl/

  • McMullin, Ernan. 1985. Galilean Idealization. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 16 (3): 247–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, Moti. 2012. Idealizations and Scientific Understanding. Philosophical Studies 160 (2): 237–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nawar, Tamer. 2021. Veritism Refuted? Understanding, Idealization, and the facts. Synthese 198: 4295–4313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pappas, George S. and Marshal Swan (eds.). 1978. Essays on Knowledge and Justification, London: Cornell University Press.

  • Pritchard, Duncan. 2009. Knowledge, Understanding and Epistemic Value Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 64: 19–43.

  • Shope, Robert K. 1983. The Analysis of Knowing. A Decade of Research. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siegel, Susanna. 2010. The Contents of Visual Experience. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, Michael. 2017. How Idealizations Provide Understanding. In Stephen Grimm, Christoph Baumberger, and Sabine Ammon (eds.), Explaining Understanding: New Perspectives from Epistemology and London Philosophy of Science. Routledge.

  • Suárez, Mauricio (ed.) 2009. Fictions in Science. Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealizations, New York: Routledge.

  • Sullivan, Emily, and Kareem Khalifa. 2019. Idealizations and Understanding: Much Ado About Nothing? Australasian Journal of Philosophy 97: 673–689. https://doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2018.1564337

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tal, Eran. 2013. Old and New Problems in Philosophy of Measurement. Philosophy Compass 8 (12): 1159–1173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Teller, Paul. 2008. Representation in Science. In The Routledge Companion to the Philosophy of Science, eds. Statis Psillos, and Martin Curd (eds.), Oxford: Routledge.

  • Teller, Paul. 2009. Fictions, Fictionalization and Truth in Science. In Fictions in Science. Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealizations. Mauricio Suárez (ed.), New York: Routledge.

  • Van Fraassen, Bas C. 1980. The Scientific Image, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, Bas C. 2008. Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective. Oxford: Clarendon Press; New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, Michael. 2007a. Who is a Modeler? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 58 (2): 207-233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, Michael. 2007b. Three Kinds of Idealization. InJournal of Philosophy 104 (12): 639–659.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zagzebski, Linda. 2001. Recovering Understanding. In Knowledge, Truth, and Duty: Essay on Epistemic Justification, Responsibility, and Virtue, Steup (ed.), New York: Oxford University Press. 235–253.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Funding

This work was made possible thanks to the financial support of the postdoctoral program of the National Autonomous University of Mexico at the Institute for Philosophical Research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alfonso Anaya.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

Author Alfonso Anaya declares that he has no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

…In that Empire, the Art of Cartography attained such Perfection that the map of a single Province occupied the entirety of a City, and the map of the Empire, the entirety of a Province. In time, those Unconscionable Maps no longer satisfied, and the Cartographers Guilds struck a Map of the Empire whose size was that of the Empire, and which coincided point for point with it.

The following Generations, who were not so fond of the Study of Cartography as their Forebears had been, saw that that vast Map was Useless, and not without some Pitilessness was it, that they delivered it up to the Inclemencies of Sun and Winters. In the Deserts of the West, still today, there are Tattered Ruins of that Map, inhabited by Animals and Beggars; in all the Land there is no other Relic of the Disciplines of Geography.

-Jorge Luis Borges, “On Exactitude in Science”.

Electronic Supplementary Material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary Material 1

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Anaya, A. Idealized Models as Selective Representations. J Gen Philos Sci 54, 189–213 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-022-09612-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10838-022-09612-7

Navigation