Skip to main content
Log in

Idealist Implications of Contemporary Science

  • Original Research
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent developments in contemporary natural science (including the evolutionary study of perception, cognitive science, and interpretations of quantum physics) incorporate central idealist positions relating to the nature of representation, the role our minds play in structuring our experience of the world, and the properties of the world behind our representations. This paper first describes what these positions are, and how they are introduced in the relevant theories in terms of precisely formulated scientific analogues. I subsequently consider how this way of looking at philosophical idealism through selected parts of contemporary science can help us to pursue new ways of developing key idealist questions in a way that is integrated with a naturalistically supported endeavour to understand central features of reality.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. With a few notable exceptions: Foster (1982, 2008), von Kutschera (2006), Sprigge (1983), Taber (2020). See also Farris/Göcke (2022), parts 3–5.

  2. Anderson (2017): 5–6: “I most certainly do not want to recapitulate the realism vs. idealism and epistemic externalism vs. internalism debates […] I’ll simply assert without argument that […] any epistemology that implies internalism and its attendant skepticism has made a mistake somewhere.” Simons (2021: 76) includes idealism in his list of “metaphysical follies”, views he considers to be “bizarre, extreme and unbelievable”.

  3. Dunham et al. (2011) and Goldschmidt/Pearce (2017) provide good surveys of the diversity of idealist traditions.

  4. For some discussion of global advance of science in the late 19th and early 20th century and the contemporaneous rise of philosophical idealism in Europe, India, and China see Garfield/Bushan (2017: 178–216), Makeham (2014).

  5. My claim is not that every position in the history of philosophy ever described as idealism endorses all of these principles, but rather that they subsume a large enough subset of the family to provide sufficient content for the discussion of idealism presented below.

  6. I believe the three principles can be brought into sharper focus by considering their direct opposites, many of which are widely accepted philosophical positions. Representation contradicts various forms of direct or naïve realism which assume that our perception puts us into a direct relation with entities ‘out there’ in the world, without the need for a representational intermediary (for the popular disjunctivist variety of this view see Soteriou 2016). An antithesis of formation is the common-sense realism defended, for example, by Michael Devitt (“Tokens of most current observable common-sense and scientific physical types objectively exist independently of the mental.”, 1997: 24), while non-correspondence is directly opposed to epistemic realism, “the reigning orthodoxy among philosophers for almost a generation”, the view that “especially in the ‘mature’ and well-developed parts of the physical sciences, scientists have come very close to discerning the way the world really is.” (Laudan 1997: 138).

  7. See Hoffman et al., (2015a, b). Hoffman (2019) presents a popularized account of the theory. Hoffman also sets out to build a comprehensive theory of consciousness (“conscious realism”, the view that “the objective world […] consists entirely of conscious agents”, 2008: 103) on the basis of the interface theory. These further theoretical developments are not part of our present discussion.

  8. See Simons (2017: 32).

  9. Prakash (2021).

  10. Hoffman et al., (2015a): 1486, Prakash (2021: 326–327). This is frequently the case. Not enough water is as bad for an organism as too much; that some intake of water increases fitness does not imply that any intake will.

  11. Hoffman (2008: 112) and Prakash (2020) for the relevant technical details behind this claim. We can show that the more experiences a perceiver is able to distinguish the greater the probability that perceptual strategies aiming at fitness the perceiver might adopt will outperform strategies aiming at accurate representation.

    Prakash et al., (2020) examines a set of structures of our representation of the world (total orders, permutation groups, cyclic groups, and measurable spaces), arguing that if these structures were also instantiated in the world, it would be exceedingly unlikely that evolutionarily successful fitness functions ever mirror them.

  12. Hoffman (2015b) notes that “the fundamental dynamical properties of physics—including position, momentum, and spin—do not describe reality as it is, but are instead products of—that is, creations of—the measurement process” (1554) and that “physics is almost surely not causally complete”. (1571).

  13. Such a sharing of structure is assumed, for example, by O’Brien/Opie (2004: 15), who argue that “it is a relation of structural resemblance between mental representing vehicles and their objects that disposes cognitive subjects to behave appropriately towards the latter.”.

  14. Hoffman et al., (2015a, 2015b: 1484, 1501, 1503).

  15. Hoffman et al., (2015a, 2015b: 1496).

  16. Fields et al., (2017: 272–273). ‘Errors’ are here understood not as misrepresentations of the environment, but as actions that decrease fitness (288). See also Prakash (2020: 121) which discusses a formal development of the idea that “a conscious agent can consistently see geometric and probabilistic structures of space that are not necessarily in the world per se but are properties of the conscious agent itself”.

  17. Hoffman et al., (2015a, 2015b: 1490).

  18. Hoffman et al., (2014: 20).

  19. Hoffman et al., (2015a, 2015b: 1483).

  20. Hoffman (2015b: 1565).

  21. Hoffman (2015b: 1563).

  22. Despite the neutrality of the interface theory’s conception of the world behind the representations its proponents use it as a basis on which to build an idealist metaphysics (‘conscious agent theory’), see Hoffman et al., (2015a, 2015b: 1502). For more on conscious agent theory see Hoffman (2008), Hoffman/Prakash (2014).

  23. Helpful surveys of the prediction error minimization theory are provided by Hohwy (2013, 2020), as well as in the collection of papers available at https://predictive-mind.net.

  24. For more discussion of Markov blankets see Westerhoff (2020: 37–40), Menary/Gillett (2021), Bruineberg (2022).

  25. Hohwy (2016: 276).

  26. For further discussion of the notion of ‘directness’ relevant in this context see Snowdown (1992), Westerhoff (2020: 22–32).

  27. Hohwy (2016: 283).

  28. Wiese/Metzinger (2007: 1).

  29. For some accounts that challenge this postulate see Anderson (2017), Clark (2017), Fabry (2017a,b).

  30. Clark (2017: 17). See also Parr et al., (2022: 108–109).

  31. Hohwy (2016: 275).

  32. Fabry (2017b: 406).

  33. Hohwy (2016: 276).

  34. Clark (2017: 16).

  35. On this point see Clark (2017: 16).

  36. A point accepted by Hohwy: “the brain is itself a hidden cause” (2016: 268). See also Shand (2014: 245), note 5.

  37. Hohwy (2013: 179, 221).

  38. For the idea of equating the agent with a model see Hohwy (2017: 3).

  39. See, for example, Swanson (2016), Beni (2018), Piekarski (2017), Zahavi (2018), Gładziejewski (2016: 574), Anderson/Chemero (2013: 204). Links between predictive processing and Berkeley’s idealism are explored by Shand (2014) and Norwich (1993, chs 15, 17).

  40. Swanson (2016: 5–6).

  41. They also include some very specific assumptions, such as that light comes from above (Hohwy 2013:116).

  42. Possible examples of hyperpriors mentioned by Clark (2013:196) include the basic assumption about space that every location contains only a single object, and the basic assumption about time that we can only carry out a single action at any given moment.

  43. Hohwy (2013: 220).

  44. Hohwy (2013: 60, 81).

  45. Gładziejewski (2016: 571).

  46. Feldman (2013).

  47. Westphal (1997: 231).

  48. As for the Kantian the causal relation is to be confined exclusively to the phenomenal realm. See Rescher (1974: 178).

  49. Apart from popular classics in this genre like Capra (1975) and Zukav (1979) see, for example, Goswami (1989), Wendt (2015), Kastrup (2021).

  50. I also lack the space to discuss the work of Markus Müller, whose approach has stronger idealist implications than QBism. See, for example Ball (2017), Müller (2018, 2020).

  51. The philosophical implications of QBism are subject to extensive discussion in the literature, and not all philosophers and physicists writing on this agree about all of them. Nevertheless, I hope that the account given below faithfully represents the view of key contributors to this debate.

  52. Fuchs et al. (2014: 749). For criticism of this understanding of the wavefunction see Brown (2019).

  53. For some discussion see von Baeyer (2016: 135–137), Fuchs et al. (2014: 750).

  54. Fuchs et al. (2014: 750).

  55. Norsen (2016: 234).

  56. Fuchs (2010: 21–22).

  57. Mermin (2014b: 422–423).

  58. Fuchs (2017: 119, note 5).

  59. Glick (2021: 17–18), Fuchs (2017: 119).

  60. Glick (2021: 8).

  61. Mohrhoff (2020: 29).

  62. 2017: 121. How, according to QBism, the world manages to ‘kick’ in a way that shows up in our experience remains entirely mysterious. As Brown (2019: 81) notes, the “part of QBism which relates to “a theory of stimulation and response” between the agent and the world is not grounded in known physics.” Nor, one might add, is prediction error minimization’s theory of the interaction of entities on both sides of the Markov blanket.

  63. For further discussion of attempts trying to establish a mind-independent world by kicking see Simons (2017), Massin (2019).

  64. That QBism doesn not reduce to solipisism, understood as the position that only I myself am fundamentally real is evident once we realize that the world as we construct it from our experience contains minds other than our own. As we represent the world, distinct minds are included at the level of representation. And if QBism does not speak about the world as it is in itself it obviously cannot say that the world understood in this way only contains my mind. Since there is no third conception of the world, the world according to QBism cannot be understood along solipsist lines.

  65. 2008: 592.

  66. von Baeyer (2016: 221).

  67. Brown (2019: 80).

  68. Fuchs et al. (2014: 751).

  69. Unless we assume that this world can be accessed by pure reasoning, or by something like artistic or mystical intuition. The number of philosophers who want to rely on these when arguing against idealist accounts of the world is presumably small.

  70. Peres (1978: 746), von Baeyer (2016: 142–143), Hoffman (2105b: 1553).

  71. Glick (2021: 4).

  72. Peres (1978: 746).

  73. Mermin (2012: 8).

  74. Mermin (2014a: 20) suggests that this coordination takes place through language, though he unfortunately does not make clear how language is supposed to move across sets of subject-related experiences. See also Mermin (2014b: 422).

  75. Westerhoff (2020, chapter 3).

  76. A position we have not discussed here that might be able to combine the advantages of both noumenalism and limitationism is a view that agrees with the noumenalist that we should assert the existence of a world behind the representations, but concedes to the limitationalist that such a world can be only made sense of as one of the representations. (See Westerhoff 2016, 2020). According to this position, though we habitually refer to a ‘world out there’ and to entities behind our representations, such references do not differ in type from references to representations like tables and chairs.

  77. Brown (2019: 75, 78–81) refers to the “variant of Berkeleyian idealism which suffuses QBism”. For an attempt to link QBism with an ontology of idealist monism see Mohrhoff (2021).

  78. Hoffman et al., (2015a: 1482).

  79. Hohwy (2016: 264).

  80. Mermin (2012), von Baeyer (2016: 152–155).

  81. In this case the notion of an isomorphic representation of structure constitutes the cut between the representation and the represented, demarcating, in the words of Hermann Weyl “the self-evident insurmountable boundary of cognition” (1949: 26).

  82. For some remarks on this see Fields et al., (2017: 268).

  83. See e.g. Fields et al., (2022).

References

  • Anderson, M., Of Bayes and bullets: an embodied, situated, targeting-based account of predictive processing. Thomas Metzinger, Wanja Wiese (eds): Philosophy and Predictive Processing 4. Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group (2017).

  • Anderson, M., & Chemero, T. (2013). The problem with brain GUTs: Conflation of different senses of “prediction” threatens metaphysical disaster. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36(3), 204–205.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ball, P., Consciously quantum. New Scientist, 8th November (2017)

  • Bhushan, N., & Garfield, J. L. (2017). Minds without fear: philosophy in the Indian renaissance. Oxford University Press.

  • Beni, M. D. (2018). Commentary: The predictive processing paradigm has roots in Kant. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience, 11(98), 1–3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berman, D. (2022). The Essential Berkeley and Neo-Berkeley. Bloomsbury Academic, London.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H. (2019). The reality of the wavefunction: Old arguments and new. In A. Cordero (Ed.), Philosophers Look at Quantum Mechanics (pp. 63–86). Springer International Publishing, Cham.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bruineberg, J., Dolega, K., Dewhurst, J., Baltieri, M., The emperor’s new Markov blankets. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 45: e183 (2022)

  • Capra, F. (1975). The Tao of Physics. Bantam Books, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christopher, A., Fuchs, N., Mermin, D., & Schack, R. (2014). An introduction to QBism with an application to the locality of quantum mechanics. American Journal of Physics, 82(8), 749–754.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Christopher, A. (2017). Fuchs: On participatory realism. In Ian Durham, Dean Rickles (Eds.) Information and Interaction: Eddington, Wheeler, and the Limits of Knowledge (pp. 113–134). Springer International Publishing, Cham.

    Google Scholar 

  • Christopher Gordon Timpson. (2008). Quantum Bayesianism: A study. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 39, 579–609.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., How to knit your own Markov blanket: Resisting the second law with metamorphic minds. Thomas Metzinger, Wanja Wiese (eds): Philosophy and Predictive Processing 4. Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group, (2017).

  • Clark, A. (2012). Dreaming the whole cat: Generative models, predictive processing, and the enactivist conception of perceptual experience. Mind, 121(483), 753–771.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2013). Whatever next? Predictive brains, situated agents, and the future of cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 36, 181–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2016). Busting out: Predictive brains, embodied minds, and the puzzle of the evidentiary veil. Noûs, 51, 727–753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Ray, C. (2022). An evolutionary sceptical challenge to scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 87, 969–989.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (1997). Realism and Truth (2nd ed.). Princeton University Press, Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunham, J., Grant, I. H., & Watson, S. (2011). Idealism. The History of a Philosophy, Acumen, Durham.

  • Fabry, R. E., Predictive processing and cognitive development. Thomas Metzinger, Wanja Wiese (eds): Philosophy and Predictive Processing 4. Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group (2017a).

  • Fabry, R. E. (2017b). Transcending the evidentiary boundary: Prediction error minimization, embodied interaction, and explanatory pluralism. Philosophical Psychology, 30(4), 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farris, J., Paul Göcke, B. (eds) (2022). The Routledge Handbook of Idealism and Immaterialism: A Historical and Philosophical Study, Routledge, London.

  • Feldman, J. (2013). Tuning your priors to the world. Topics in Cognitive Science, 5(1), 13–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fields, C., Friston, K., Glazebrook, J. F., & Levin, M. (2022). A free energy principle for generic quantum systems. Progress in Biophysics & Molecular Biology, 23, 5894.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fields, C., Hoffman, D. D., Prakash, C., & Prentner, R. (2017). Eigenforms, interfaces and holographic encoding. Toward an evolutionary account of objects and spacetime. Constructivist Foundations, 12(3), 265–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foster, J. (1982). The Case for Idealism. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Foster, J. (2008). A World for Us. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, C. A., (2010). QBism, the perimeter of Quantum Bayesianism. https://arxiv.org/abs/1003.5209

  • Gładziejewski, P. (2016). Predictive coding and representationalism. Synthese, 193, 559–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glick, D. (2021). QBism and the limits of scientific realism. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 11(53), 1–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldschmidt, T., Pearce, K. L. (eds) (2017). Idealism. New Essays in Metaphysics. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

  • Goswami, A. (1989). The idealistic interpretation of quantum mechanics. Physics Essays, 2, 385–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, D. D. (2008). Conscious realism and the mind-body problem. Mind & Matter, 6(1), 87–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, D. D. (2019). The Case Against Reality. Why Evolution Hid the Truth from our Eyes, W.W. Norton & Company, New York.

  • Hoffman, D., & Prakash, C. (2014). Objects of consciousness. Frontiers of Psychology, 5(577), 1–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, D. D., Singh, M., & Prakash, C. (2015a). The interface theory of perception. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 22(6), 1480–1506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoffman, D. D., Singh, M., & Prakash, C. (2015). Probing the interface theory of perception: Reply to commentaries. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 22, 1551–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J., “How to entrain your evil demon”, Thomas Metzinger, Wanja Wiese (eds): Philosophy and Predictive Processing 4. Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group, 2017.

  • Hohwy, J. (2016). The self-evidencing brain. Nôus, 50(2), 259–285.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hohwy, J. (2020). “New directions in predictive processing”, Mind & Language. Mind & Language, 35, 209–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howhy, J. (2013). The Predictive Mind. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kastrup, B. (2021). Science Ideated, iff Books, Winchester.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. (1997). Explaining the success of science: Beyond epistemic realism and relativism. In A. I. Tauber (Ed.), Science and the Quest for Reality (pp. 137–161). Palgrave Macmillan, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Makeham, J. (2014). Transforming Consciousness. Yogācāra Thought in Modern China. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

  • Massin, O. (2019) “Realism’s kick.” in Christoph Limbeck-Lilienau, Friedrich Stadler (eds): The Philosophy of Perception. Proceedings of the 40th International Ludwig Wittgenstein Symposium. de Gruyter, Berlin. 39–56.

  • Menary, R., James Gillett, A., (2021). Are Markov blankets real and does it matter?” In: Dina Mendonça, Manuel Curado, Steven S. Gouveia (eds): The Philosophy and Science of Predictive Processing, Bloomsbury Academic, London, 39–58.

  • Mermin, D. N. (2014a). QBism in the New Scientist. https://arxiv.org/abs/1406.1573v1.

  • Mermin, D. N. (2012). Quantum mechanics: Fixing the shifty split. Physics Today, 65, 7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mermin, D. N. (2014). QBism puts the scientist back into science. Nature, 26, 421–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mohrhoff, U. (2020). “QBism: A Critical Appraisal”. https://arxiv.org/abs/1409.3312

  • Mohrhoff, U. (2020) .“A QBist ontology”. https://arxiv.org/abs/2005.14584

  • Müller, M P. (2018). Mind before matter: Reversing the arrow of fundamentality. https://arxiv.org/abs/1812.08594

  • Müller, M. P. (2020). Law without law: From observer states to physics via algorithmic information theory.https://arxiv.org/abs/1712.01826

  • Norsen, T. (2016). Quantum solipsism and non-locality. In M. Bell & S. Gao (Eds.), Quantum Nonlocality and Reality: 50 Years of Bell’s Theorem (pp. 204–237). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Norwich, K. (1993). Information, Sensation, and Perception. Academic Press, San Diego.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, G., & Opie, J. (2004). Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation. In H. Clapin, P. Staines, & P. Slezak (Eds.), Representation in Mind: New Approaches to Mental Representation (pp. 1–20). Elsevier, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parr, T., Pezzulo, G., Friston, K. J. (2022). Active Inference. The free energy principle in mind, brain, and behavior. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

  • Peres, A. (1978). Unperformed experiments have no results. American Journal of Physics, 46, 745–747.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piekarski, M. (2017). Commentary: Brain, mind, world: Predictive coding, neo-kantianism, and transcendental idealism. Frontiers in Psychology, 8(2077), 1–3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakash, C. (2020). On invention of structure in the world: Interfaces and conscious agents. Foundations of Science, 25, 121–134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prakash, C., Fields, C., Hoffman, D. D., Prentner, R., & Singh, M. (2020). Fact, fiction, and fitness. Entropy, 22(514), 1–23.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prakash, C., Stephens, K. D., Hoffman, D. D., Singh, M., & Fields, C. (2021). Fitness beats truth in the evolution of perception. Acta Biotheoretica, 69(3), 319–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Purves, D., Morgenstern, Y., & Wojtach, W. T. (2015). Perception and reality: Why a wholly empirical paradigm is needed to understand vision. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience, 9(156), 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1974). “Noumenal causality” In Lewis White Beck (ed): Kant’s Theory of Knowledge, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, 175–183.

  • Shand, J. (2014). Predictive mind, cognition, and chess. Analysis, 74(2), 244–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simons, P. (2017). Road safety. Why agency and intentionality were made for each other (and how this refutes idealism). In J. Padilla-Galvez & M. Gaffal (Eds.), Intentionality and Action (pp. 23–34). de Gruyter, Berlin.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Simons, P. (2021). The long and winding road. Folly and feedback in metaphysics. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 98, 75–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Snowdown, P. (1992). How to interpret ‘direct perception.’ In T. Crane (Ed.), The Contents of Experience (pp. 48–78). Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Soteriou, M. (2016). Disjunctivism. Routledge, London.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sprigge, T. (1983). The Vindication of Absolute Idealism. Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swanson, L. R. (2016). The predictive processing paradigm has roots in Kant. Frontiers in Systems Neuroscience, 10, 79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taber, J. (2020). “Philosophical Reflections on the sahopalambhaniyama argument”, in Birgit Kellner, Patrick McAllister, Horst Lasic, Sara McClintock (eds): Reverberations of Dharmakīrti‘s Philosophy. Proceedings of the Fifth International Dharmakīrti Conference Heidelberg August 26 to 30, 2014, Austrian Academy of Sciences Press, Vienna, pp. 441–462.

  • von Kutschera, F. (2006). Die wege des Idealismus, Paderborn. Mentis.

  • von Baeyer, H. C. (2016). QBism. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, London.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wendt, A. (2015). Quantum Mind and Social Science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Westerhoff, J. (2016). What it means to live in a virtual world generated by our brain. Erkenntnis, 81(3), 507–528.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Westerhoff, J. (2020). The Non-Existence of the Real World. Oxford University Press, Oxford.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Westphal, K. R. (1997). Noumenal causality reconsidered: Affection, agency, and meaning in Kant. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 27(2), 209–245.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. (1949). Philosophy of Mathematics and Natural Science. Princeton University Press, Princeton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiese, W., Metzinger, T. (2017). Vanilla PP for philosophers: a primer on predictive processing. Thomas Metzinger, Wanja Wiese (eds): Philosophy and Predictive Processing 4. Frankfurt am Main: MIND Group.

  • Zahavi, D. (2018). Mind, brain, world: Predictive coding, neo-Kantianism, and transcendental idealism. Husserl Studies, 34, 47–61.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zukav, G. (1979). The Dancing Wu Li Masters. William Morrow and Company, New york.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jan Westerhoff.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

The author has no conflict of interest to declare.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Westerhoff, J. Idealist Implications of Contemporary Science. Erkenn (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-023-00738-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-023-00738-8

Navigation