The argument of this paper develops a virtue ethics-based argument that certain consumption actions are moral wrongdoings and their corresponding unilateral reductions are therefore morally obligatory.Footnote 1 The argument is as follows:
-
A.
To remain a member of a harming group is a moral wrongdoing;
-
B.
The performance of consumption actions constitutes remaining a member of a harming group;
-
C.
Therefore, the performance of consumption actions is a moral wrongdoing.
I will firstly present an analogy to the case of environmental problems of an individual remaining a member of a harming group, followed by a first set of defences against a claim of wrongdoing in this context. Next, I will present an account of the nature of the wrongdoing in this context grounded in a virtue ethics formulation of wrong action. Finally, I will transfer the claim to the case of the harming group responsible for environmental problems, and consider some additional defences to the wrongdoing claim that its members might advance.
I begin with the case of Nigel, who is a member of a golf club. Nigel uses the club’s driving range, at the end of which is a steep embankment. The driving range is a little too short, such that occasionally, if Nigel strikes a golf ball particularly fiercely, the ball disappears down the embankment. Otherwise, the balls are swept up by the golf ball picker. After a while of using the driving range, Nigel discovers that not only do his more fiercely-struck golf balls end up down the embankment, but so do all the other balls he strikes, along with all those of his fellow members who use the range, for that is where the golf ball picker, he discovers, dumps its collections. He investigates what is down the embankment and finds a community nature reserve. The pond and woodland in the reserve is now choked with thousands of golf balls and is devoid of wildlife, and members of the local community who helped to create and once enjoyed the reserve no longer visit it. Nigel is appalled by his discovery, petitions the management to desist and makes his fellow members aware of the practice in the hope that they will do likewise, but neither respond to his protests. The practice continues. What should Nigel do? He has found himself a member of a group—in this case, a golf club—that harms. It harms the wildlife in the pond, and the local community by unjustly depriving them of a green space that they once enjoyed. He knows that some of the golf balls in the pond and woodland are his—both from those he has struck down there directly and those that the picker has dumped—but that this amount is negligible compared to the many thousands down there. Resigning his membership of the club will make no difference, either in terms of the number of golf balls that end up in the reserve, or its effects on other members or the actions of the club. In the end, he decides not to resign. Despite still seeing the balls—including his—being dumped down the embankment, he continues going to the club and using the driving range.
What defence could Nigel give if his friend Olivia criticised his failure to resign his membership of the golf club? He might point to his ignorance of the harmful practice when he joined; defend the club’s practice as not being intentionally harmful but one in which the harm was an unintentional by-product of a good business decision (the manager tells him the golf balls are cheap but good for only one strike); defend his own actions as not intentionally harmful but ones in which the harm to which he contributes is unintentional; or defend his contribution to the harm caused by the club’s practice as inconsequential. He might also say that he now tries never to directly hit any balls down the embankment. These defences, whatever their independent strengths, do not answer the charge that his failure to resign his membership now he knows that the group of which he is a member causes harm constitutes a moral wrongdoing. I now develop this charge below.
To remain a member of a harming group is to continue one’s membership (i.e., fail to resign one’s membership and withdraw from the group) after one comes to know (or after the point where one could reasonably be expected to know) that the group causes harm. This definition of what it is to remain a member of a harming group is independent of whether or not the harm resulting from the group’s actions is an intentional consequence of the group’s deliberately adopted policies. What is wrong with remaining a member is not Nigel’s continuing contribution to the harm, since this is inconsequential, but his attitude to the overall level of harm that the club is causing to the wildlife and the local community. Firstly, in remaining a member of the club Nigel is acquiescing in the harm that it is causing. He may not be explicitly assenting to the harm continuing, but he is tacitly doing so by his actions (or, rather, his lack of action in resigning). Secondly, in remaining a member of the club Nigel is complicit in the harm it is causing and the wrongdoing that the harm constitutes. He may not be the manager who instigated the practice, or the treasurer of the club who signs the cheques for the cheap golf balls, or on the committee who approved the practice, or the driver of the cart who pulls the lever and dumps the golf balls, but he is nonetheless a member of the club and as such—even without a specific role in the harm—is complicit in the harm it causes. This complicity is grounded by his membership fees partly contributing towards the practice and his continuing membership lending credibility to the club.
Thirdly, and further grounding his complicity in the harm, in remaining a member Nigel is tacitly approving of or endorsing the practice of dumping golf balls in the reserve. He may protest that he does not approve of it; he rather professes his disapproval to his fellow members and to the manager, as well as to his non-member friends like Olivia. Moreover, if he were the manager, he would stop the practice. But his actions tell a different story. If he were to meet a local resident who once enjoyed the nature reserve and who asked him if he had resigned his membership, and replied that he had not because he did not think his membership made any significant difference, the local resident might agree with him that it did not make a difference in terms of the number of golf balls that were dumped in the reserve, but she would nonetheless be justified in being disgusted that Nigel had remained a member on the grounds that doing so showed that he approved of the practice. Nigel could protest that he did not approve of the practice or the harm that it caused, but the local resident could say that if he really disapproved then he would resign his membership, because not resigning is a form of approval and endorsement of the practice continuing. As O’Neill et al. (2008: 84) observe, ‘actions are not just instrumental means to an end, but a way of expressing attitudes to people and things.’ An action is expressive if it manifests a state of mind, such as a belief, mood, emotion, attitude, desire, intention, or personality trait (Anderson and Pildes 2000: 1506). To determine the expressive content of an action we need to weigh the agent’s intention in performing the action against the social meaning of their action. As Anderson and Pildes (ibid.: 1513) argue, ‘[e]xpressive theories of action hold people accountable for the public meanings of their actions.’ If I raise my hand at an auction, I have made a bid, even if I claim that my intention was only to stretch. Nigel, in being aware of the club’s practices and the harm they cause, and being free to resign his membership of the club but failing to do so, is accountable for the attitude towards the practice and its consequences it expresses, namely, approval and endorsement.Footnote 2
I will now introduce a virtue-oriented account of moral wrongdoing to further my argument. It is widely assumed that for an ethical theory to be adequate it must offer an account of the rightness and wrongness of actions. Therefore, while evaluation of agents and their character traits is foundational in virtue ethics, attempts have been made to provide an account of right action from within the virtue framework (e.g., Hursthouse 1999; Slote 2001, but see Das 2003 for scepticism.). One such account of right action has been advanced by Sandler (2007), itself a modified and expanded version of Swanton’s (2003) account. Before I introduce this account, it is worth distinguishing two helpful notions in Sandler’s (2007: 40–41) account of what distinguishes the virtues from one another: their bases of responsiveness, that is, ‘the types of objects, events, and properties to which they are responsive’, and their forms of responsiveness, that is, ‘the types of reactions and activities that they involve’. For example, ‘the basis of responsiveness for compassion is the suffering of others, and the forms of responsiveness are concern for others, desiring to assist others, and acting to diminish the suffering of others. The basis of responsiveness for gratitude is being benefited by another, and the forms of responsiveness are recognition of the benefit, a desire to acknowledge it, and actions that acknowledge it’ (ibid.: 41). We are now in a position to better understand Sandler’s (ibid.: 94) agent-relative target principle of right action:
An action is right to the extent that it better hits the targets of the operative virtues taken together (i.e., it is more virtuous) than the other courses of action available to a particular agent under the circumstances; and an action is wrong to the extent that it misses the targets of the operative virtues taken together (i.e., it is less virtuous) than the other courses of action available to a particular agent under the circumstances.
Consider the simple case where ‘the aim of a virtue is simply to promote the good of individuals and hitting the target is successfully promoting that good’ (Swanton 2003: 39). In Sandler’s (2007: 92) terms, it is ‘a matter of whether the considerations in the world to which the operative virtue is responsive are adequately addressed by the agent’s action. With respect to compassion, it is a matter of whether the suffering is relieved….With respect to tolerance, it is whether one is able to refrain from interfering with what one finds objectionable.’Footnote 3 Right action in virtue ethics, then, is a matter of hitting the target of the virtue, that is, of one’s forms of responsiveness being appropriate to and adequately addressing the bases of responsiveness.
An account of wrong action—which is not explicitly offered by either Swanton or Sandler—can be derived from this account of right action. Firstly, actions which merely fail to hit the target of the virtues that are operative in a context count as wrong action. But also, missing the target of a virtue will often, although not always, involve hitting the target of a vice.Footnote 4 Just as certain virtues will be operative in particular contexts, so will certain vices. For example, in a situation that calls on people to desire the alleviation of the suffering of others and act to bring about that end, missing those targets of the virtue of compassion may hit the target of the vices of insensitivity, apathy or arrogance.
To say that the target of a vice or virtue has been hit is to make an evaluation of the action itself, not the agent’s intentions and motivations. On this latter point the notion of ‘hitting the target’ of vices and virtues is neutral; whether an act is from virtue or vice depends on the motives of the agent and the state from which she acts, whereas whether an act itself is virtuous is typically independent of these features of the agent (Sandler 2007: 92). Admittedly, the idea of hitting the target does imply some agency and intention, and we may therefore be more comfortable with this notion in relation to virtues (the targets of which we condone aiming for) than vices, but for our purposes, it is purely an evaluation of the action, not the agent’s motives. This is not to say that agents’ inner states are never relevant to an evaluation of their actions; the target of vices and virtues involve not just valuable outcomes but also the acting agent’s desires and emotions.
Using this account, we can now claim that in acquiescing in, being complicit in, and approving of or endorsing the practices of the club and their associated harm, Nigel’s action of remaining a member of the golf club hits the target of certain vices and fails to hit the target of certain virtues.Footnote 5 Firstly, insofar as he is unprepared to withdraw from the group and disassociate himself from its actions and is thereby tacitly acquiescing in and approving of or endorsing the harm it causes, Nigel’s action hits the target of the vices of indifference and disrespectfulness towards the victims of the harm. Even if his membership has caused and is causing little harm in relation to the level of harm caused by the group, the fact that the group of which he is a member is causing considerable harm should be a matter of concern to him that moves him to acknowledge the harm in some way, even if he is incapable of stopping or even mitigating it. In failing to acknowledge it in the ways open to him—which include ceasing to perform the actions which aggregate to cause the harm, but more importantly for our purposes, to resign his membership of the club—he is being indifferent to and disrespectful of its victims by remaining a member.Footnote 6 Secondly, insofar as he appreciates both the harm that the group of which he is a member causes and that his membership associates him with this harm in a morally problematic way, but is nonetheless unmoved to withdraw from the group, remaining a member hits the target of the vice of apathy. Thirdly, insofar as the benefits he accrues from membership of the group lead him to ignore or downplay the harm caused by its practices Nigel’s action hits the target of the vice of selfishness or self-centredness, and insofar as he unjustifiably weighs the benefits he accrues from membership above the harm suffered by the victims of his group’s actions the targets of the vices of arrogance and egoism would be hit. Fourthly, insofar as he professes disapproval of the practice which causes the harm yet continues by choice to reap the benefits his membership and his contribution to the harm affords, remaining a member hits the target of the vice of hypocrisy. Fifthly, insofar as fear of the costs—either material, psychological or social—resulting from withdrawal from the group leads him to remain a member despite recognition of the harm with which he is associated Nigel’s action hits the target of the vice of cowardice.
In addition to, and mirroring, the vices the target of which are hit by remaining a member of the harming group, there are certain operative virtues in this context. Firstly, if Nigel refused to acquiesce in and approve of or endorse the practices of the group and the harm it causes by resigning his membership, his action would hit the target of the virtues of compassion, concern, care, empathy, sympathy and respect. Secondly, if he overcame barriers to his withdrawal from the group, including material, psychological or social costs, resigning his membership would hit the target of the virtue of determination. Thirdly, if he properly weighed the benefits that accrue to him from his membership against the harm that the victims of the group’s practices suffer, the targets of the virtues of honesty and humility would be hit. Fourthly, if he withdrew from the group and thereby made his actions consistent with his professed disapproval of the practice which causes harm, resigning would hit the target of the virtue of integrity. Fifthly, if he withdrew from the group despite harbouring fears of the material, psychological or social costs that it may result in, the target of the virtue of courage would be hit. In failing to hit the target of these virtues, Nigel commits a moral wrongdoing in remaining a member of the harming group. The claim that remaining a member is a moral wrongdoing is thus justified from two directions; from hitting the target of operative vices and failing to hit the target of operative virtues.
To set up the analogy with consumption and environmental harm, let’s imagine that the above charge is put to Nigel by his friend Olivia, who is not a member of the golf club. She, appalled by his failure to resign his membership, accuses him of disrespectfulness, apathy, arrogance and so on. Nigel reflects on her arguments, and (perhaps in order to deflect the conversation from his own situation) retorts that Olivia is no different; she too is a member of a group that harms. Olivia, puzzled, asks which group. He says she is a member of the group of individuals who act in such a way that, in aggregate, the consequences of their actions are global climate change, biodiversity loss, marine pollution and all the other global environmental problems that cause so much harm through drought, disease, starvation, and so on. That is, she drives her car, heats her house, flies on holiday, buys and throws away material goods, eats meat and does all the other things that directly use fossil fuels and other non-renewable resources, and stimulates demand for such resources. These are analogous to Nigel striking golf balls at the driving range. Global climate change and other environmental problems—and the harm they cause to the current global poor, future generations of humans, and current and future nonhumans—have been caused by individuals like Olivia doing all these things. Olivia may protest that, just as Nigel petitioned the management to change their policies, she too engages in political action to promote the establishment of just institutional measures to mitigate environmental problems. And just as Nigel attempts to unilaterally reduce his direct contribution to the problem by avoiding hitting golf balls directly into the reserve, she too unilaterally reduces her contribution to environmental problems in the recommended ways, but like Nigel is restricted in how far she can mitigate her contribution because of institutional constraints. But Nigel dismisses these defences, and presses the analogy with his club membership and reasons to withdraw. If Olivia now remains a member of this harming group, then just as in Nigel’s case, it will not be Olivia’s continuing contribution to the harm that will ground a negative moral evaluation, since her contribution is inconsequential. Rather, what will ground the negative moral evaluation will be the way in which her remaining a member (which is itself constituted by her continuing to inconsequentially contribute to the harm) will be expressive of acquiescence, complicity and tacit approval of the harm, and will therefore hit the target of the operative vices and fail to hit the target of the operative virtues.