Skip to main content
Log in

Sustainability Matrix: Interest Groups and Ethical Theories as the Basis of Decision-Making

  • Articles
  • Published:
Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

During the past few decades, the global food system has confronted new sustainability challenges related not only to public health and the environment but also to ethical concerns over the treatment of farmed animals. However, the traditional threedimensional framework of sustainable development is ill equipped to take ethical concerns related to non-human animals into account. For instance, the interests of farmed animals are often overridden by objectives associated with social, economic or environmental sustainability, despite their vast numbers and influence on contemporary societies. Moreover, sustainability policies necessarily involve an element of ethical evaluation; yet this element is not explicitly incorporated in prevailing frameworks of sustainable development. Our purpose in this article is to address these shortcomings by developing a Sustainability Matrix that recognizes the need to consider food system sustainability from the perspective of all interest groups affected by the issue under consideration, from a plurality of ethical standpoints. Combing sustainability principles with the basic idea of an ethical evaluation tool, the proposed Sustainability Matrix evaluates the sustainability of food-related systems, decisions and policies from the perspectives of three major strands of ethical theory and from the perspectives of human beings, farmed animals and wildlife. In terms of policy implications, the Sustainability Matrix can be applied in deciding on the specific targets of food system sustainability that can then be utilized as a basis for designing policies and measures towards the achievement of these goals.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Throughout the text, we will employ the term “food system” instead of e.g. “food production”. This is because the implications of considering farmed animals as an interest group are not limited to the production phase but extend to other parts of the supply chain as well (e.g. transport, retail).

  2. Throughout the paper, we will utilize farmed animals and agricultural animals interchangeably.

  3. This differs from Mepham’s (2000) concept of biota in that our notion of wildlife only includes sentient actors. Our rationale for this choice was that securing the interests of sentient wildlife will lead to wider ecosystem conservation and/or to sustainable mutual coexistence. Yet, we are fully aware of the difficulties in determining which animals, or organisms for that matter, should have moral status and to what extent (see Jaworska and Tannenbaum 2013).

  4. Nearly half of the world’s 200 largest companies report their ethical responsibilities toward animals although they tend to approach these ethical responsibilities in consequentialist, not rights-based, terms (Janssens and Kaptein 2016).

References

  • Adamo, S. A. (2016). Do insects feel pain? A question at the intersection of animal behaviour, philosophy and robotics. Animal Behaviour, 118, 75–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aiking, H. (2011). Future protein supply. Trends in Food Science & Technology, 22(2–3), 112–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alcott, B. (2008). The sufficiency objective: Would rich-world frugality lower environmental impact? Ecological Economics, 64(4), 770–786.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, L., & Moore, M. (2015). Deontological ethics. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2015 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/ethics-deontological/. Accessed November 12, 2015.

  • Allievi, F., Vinnari, M., & Luukkanen, J. (2015). Meat consumption and production-analysis of efficiency, sufficiency and consistency of global trends. Journal of Cleaner Production, 92(1), 142–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amos, N., & Sullivan, R. (2017). The business benchmark on farm animal welfare: 2016 report. https://www.bbfaw.com/media/1450/bbfaw-2016-report.pdf. Accessed April 19, 2017.

  • Appleby, M. (2005). Sustainable agriculture is humane, humane agriculture is sustainable. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 18(3), 293–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arluke, A., & Sanders, C. R. (1996). Regarding animals. Philadelphia: Temple University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arneson, R. (2013). Egalitarianism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/egalitarianism/. Accessed November 12, 2015.

  • Barnosky, A. (2008). Megafauna biomass tradeoff as a driver of quaternary and future extinctions. PNAS, 105(suppl. 1), 11543–11548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barron, A. B., & Klein, C. (2016). What insects can tell us about the origins of consciousness. PNAS, 113(18), 4900–4908.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beauchamp, T., & Childress, J. (2001). Principles of biomedical ethics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruers, S. (2013). The ethical consistency of animal equality. Sept 2013, DRAFT. Cited 24.08.16. https://stijnbruers.files.wordpress.com/2013/05/the-ethical-consistency-of-animal-equality5.pdf.

  • Buller, H., & Morris, C. (2003). Farm animal welfare: A new repertoire of nature-society relations or modernism re-embedded? Sociologia Ruralis, 43(3), 216–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burlingame, B., & Dernini, S. (2010). Sustainable diets and biodiversity—Directions and solutions for policy, research and action. Rome: Food and Agriculture Organization of the United Nations (FAO).

    Google Scholar 

  • Cawthorn, D., & Hoffman, L. (2014). The role of traditional and non-traditional meat animals in feeding a growing and evolving world. Animal Frontiers, 4(4), 6–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chapagain, A., & Hoekstra, A. (2004). Water footprints of nations (Vol. 1). Delft: UNESCO-IHE.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daly, H. (1992). Allocation, distribution, and scale: Towards an economics that is efficient, just, and sustainable. Ecological Economics, 6, 185–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, S., & Kymlicka, W. (2011). Zoopolis: A political theory of animal rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Driver, J. (2014). The history of utilitarianism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/utilitarianism-history/. Accessed November 12, 2015.

  • FAO/WUR. (2013). Edible insects: Future prospects for food and feed security. Rome: FAO.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiems, L. (2012). Double muscling in cattle: Genes, husbandry, carcasses and meat. Animals, 2(3), 472–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forsberg, E.-M. (2007a). Value pluralism and coherentist justification of ethical advice. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 20, 81–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forsberg, E.-M. (2007b). Pluralism, the ethical matrix, and coming to conclusions. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 20, 455–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Francione, G. (2010). The abolition of animal exploitation. In G. Francione & R. Garner (Eds.), The animal rights debate. Abolition or regulation?. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franklin, A. (1999). Animals and modern cultures: A sociology of human–animal relations in modernity. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giddings, B., Hopwood, B., & O’Brien, G. (2002). Environment, economy and society: Fitting them together into sustainable development. Sustainable Development, 10(4), 187–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanski, I. (2016). Tutkimusmatkoja saarille (in Finnish: Explorations to Islands). Helsinki: Gaudeamus.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harari, Y. (2011). Sapiens: A brief history of humankind. Sweden: Bazar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haughton, G. (1999). Environmental justice and the sustainable city. Journal of Planning Education and Research, 18(3), 233–243.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hobson, K. (2007). Political animals? On animals as subjects in an enlarged political geography. Political Geography, 26, 250–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopwood, B., Mellor, M., & O’Brien, G. (2005). Sustainable development: Mapping different approaches. Sustainable Development, 13, 38–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huber, J. (2000). Towards industrial ecology: Sustainable development as a concept of ecological modernization. Journal of Environmental Policy & Planning, 2, 269–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Janssens, M. R. E., & Kaptein, M. (2016). The ethical responsibility of companies towards animals: A study of the expressed commitment of the Fortune Global 200. Journal of Corporate Citizenship, 63, 42–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaworska, A., & Tannenbaum, J. (2013). The grounds of moral status. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2013 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2013/entries/grounds-moral-status/. Cited 15.12.2016.

  • Kaiser, M., & Forsberg, E.-M. (2001). Assessing fisheries—using an ethical matrix in a participatory process. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 14, 191–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaiser, M., Millar, K., Thorstensen, E., & Tomkins, S. (2007). Developing the ethical matrix as a decision support framework: GM fish as a case study. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 20, 65–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kidd, C. (1992). The evolution of sustainability. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 5(1), 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lam, M. (2016). The ethics and sustainability of capture fisheries and aquaculture. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 29, 35–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, K. (2000). Global sustainable development: Its intellectual and historical roots. In K. Lee, A. Holland, & D. McNeill (Eds.), Global sustainable development in the 21st century (pp. 31–47). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machovina, B., Feeley, K., & Ripple, W. (2015). Biodiversity conservation: The key is reducing meat consumption. Science of the Total Environment, 536, 419–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McMichael, J., Powles, C., & Butler, R. (2007). Food, livestock production, energy, climate change, and health. Lancet, 370, 1253–1263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meade, J. (1993). Liberty, equality and efficiency. New York: NYU Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mebratu, D. (1998). Sustainability and sustainable development: Historical and conceptual review. Environmental Impact Assessment Review, 18(6), 493–520.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mepham, B. (1996). Ethical analysis of food biotechnologies: An evaluative framework. In B. Mepham (Ed.), Food ethics (pp. 101–119). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mepham, T. B. (2000). A framework for the ethical analysis of novel foods: The ethical matrix. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 12, 165–176.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mepham, T. B. (2006). The ethical matrix as a decision-making tool with specific reference to animal sentience. In J. Turner & J. D’Silva (Eds.), Animals, ethics and trade (pp. 134–145). London: Earthscan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millar, K., & Tomkins, S. (2007). Ethical analysis of the use of GM fish: Emerging issues for aquaculture development. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 20(5), 437–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Munasinghe, M. (1993). Environmental economics and sustainable development. Environment paper No. 3, World Bank, Washington, DC.

  • Ng, M., Fleming, T., Robinson, M., Thompson, B., Graetz, N., et al. (2014). Global, regional, and national prevalence of overweight and obesity in children and adults during 1980–2013: A systematic analysis for the Global Burden of Disease Study 2013. The Lancet, 384(9945), 766–781.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Sullivan, S. (2011). Animals, equality and democracy. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pachirat, T. (2011). Every twelve seconds: Industrialized slaughter and the politics of sight. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peggs, K. (2012). Animals and sociology. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Princen, T. (2005). The logic of sufficiency. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Probyn-Rapsey, F., Donaldson, S., Loannides, G., Lea, T., Marsh, K., Neimanis, A., et al. (2016). A sustainable campus: The Sydney declaration on interspecies sustainability. Animal Studies Journal, 5(1), 110–151.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachels, J. (1990). Created from animals—The moral implications of Darwinism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, J. (2015). On not defining sustainability. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 28, 1075–1087.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rawles, K. (2010). Developing ethical, sustainable and compassionate food policies. In J. D’Silva & J. Webster (Eds.), The meat crisis: Developing more sustainable production and consumption. London: Earthscan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1993). Political liberalism. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Regan, T. (1985). The case for animal rights. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ripple, W. J., Estes, J. A., Beschta, R. L., Wilmers, C. C., Ritchie, E. G., Hebblewhite, M., et al. (2014). Status and ecological effects of the world’s largest carnivores. Science, 343(6167), 1241484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ripple, W. J., Newsome, T. M., Wolf, C., Dirzo, R., Everatt, K. T., Galetti, M., et al. (2015). Collapse of the world’s largest herbivores. Science Advances, 1(4), 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rockström, J., Steffen, W., Noone, K., Persson, A., Chapin, F., Lambin, E., et al. (2009). A safe operating space for humanity. Nature, 461, 472–475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Singer, P. (1975). Animal liberation: A new ethics for our treatment of animals. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steinfeld, H., Gerber, P., Wassenaar, T., Castel, V., & Haan, C. (2006). Livestock’s long shadow: Environmental issues and options. Rome: Food and Agriculture Organization of the United Nations.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tovey, H. (2003). Theorising nature and society in sociology: The invisibility of animals. Sociologia Ruralis, 43(3), 196–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vallentyne, P. (2005). Of mice and men: Equality and animals. Journal of Ethics, 9, 403–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van den Bergh, J. (2011). Environment versus growth—A criticism of “degrowth” and a plea for “a-growth”. Ecological Economics, 70, 881–890.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vinnari, M., & Vinnari, E. (2014). A framework for sustainability transition: The case of plant-based diets. Journal of Agricultural and Environmental Ethics, 27(3), 369–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vucetich, J., & Nelson, M. (2010). Sustainability: Virtuous or vulgar? BioScience, 60(7), 539–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • WCED (UN World Commission on Environment and Development). (1987). Our common future: Report of the world commission on environment and development. Gland: WCED.

    Google Scholar 

  • Webster, A. (2002). Rendering unto Caesar: Welfare problems in Belgian Blue Cattle. The Veterinary Journal, 163, 228–229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • WHO. (2009). Global health risks: Mortality and burden of disease attributable to selected major risks. Geneva: World Health Organization.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wirsenius, S., Hedenus, F., & Mohlin, K. (2011). Greenhouse gas taxes on animal food products: Rationale, tax scheme and climate mitigation effects. Climatic Change, 108(1), 159–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • WWF. (2016). Living Planet Report 2016. Risk and resilience in a new era. Gland: WWF International.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We wish to thank the reviewers and editor for their valuable comments. This paper was partly funded by the project “Politics, practices and the transformative potential of sustainable diets” (POPRASUS), decision No. 296702. The funding from the Academy of Finland is gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Markus Vinnari.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Vinnari, M., Vinnari, E. & Kupsala, S. Sustainability Matrix: Interest Groups and Ethical Theories as the Basis of Decision-Making. J Agric Environ Ethics 30, 349–366 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-017-9670-y

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10806-017-9670-y

Keywords

Navigation