1 Introduction

In a cost-benefit analysis of climate change policy, benefits and costs that arise in the future are recalculated in present terms. There is a long history of discussion about this time weighting—or discounting—in the policy and academic arenas, and even more has been written since the publication of the Stern Review (Stern 2006) and related studies (e.g., Nordhaus 2008). This is because climate change policy is a typical textbook example of long-run projects, so that even a minor change in the discount rate could change bottom line net benefits, even under the presence of sound sensitivity analysis. The climate discounting literature rediscovers the well-known Ramsey formula, according to which the consumption discount rate can be decomposed into the pure rate of time preference and the product of the elasticity of marginal utility of consumption and the growth rate of consumption. Choosing the right values, if any, for each parameter or scenario has been shown to be a controversial task involving social agreement on not just facts but also values (Dasgupta 2008; Heal and Millner 2014).Footnote 1

Most of these studies assume an aggregate world consumption to derive consumption-based discount rates. However, a salient feature of climate change damage is that it has asymmetric consequences in terms of geography and income groups. Moreover, policies that attempt to address the issue, which are commonly dichotomized between mitigation and adaptation, have differentiated economic impacts on different groups. On the one hand, carbon taxes or emission permits require that emerging as well as developed nations disburse the social cost of carbon, at least in the current policy framework. On the other hand, disaster management, or more generally, adaptation strategies, usually benefit mostly lower income groups in vulnerable nations and islands. The dual practice of mitigation and adaptation would then have mixed effects on intragenerational inequality in the world. In the absence of those measures, it is possible that aggregate consumption continues to grow while income distribution becomes more unbalanced. Put differently, the debate about the temporal substitution of well-being should also take account of how aggregate consumption is divided within each generation (e.g., López 2005).Footnote 2

Thus, a relevant research question is what the discount rate in an increasingly unequal (or equal) world should look like.Footnote 3 The importance of equity weighting in climate change discounting has been highlighted already in a welfare-theoretic approach, including Azar and Sterner (1996), Fankhauser et al. (1997), Azar (1999), Pearce (2003), and Anthoff and Tol (2010). Studies considering non-consumption discounting has also become vast. Weikard and Zhu (2005) consider dual discounting for consumption and the environment; Hoel and Sterner (2007) study relative scarcity price of the environment; Kaplow and Weisbach (2011) separate the nexus from consumption to utility and then to social welfare; Traeger (2011a, b) incorporates limited substitutability of the environment. Yamaguchi (2013) considers consumption discount rates of the rich and poor when there are both consumption goods and the environment; however, imagining differentiated discount rates for different income groups yields practical difficulties. We instead focus on a single discount rate with an aggregate consumption numeraire and investigate the consequences of changing intragenerational distribution of consumption.

In a recent related literature, Emmerling (2018) and Anthoff and Emmerling (2016) carefully include intragenerational equity in discounting and social cost of carbon, and most notably, investigate their link with the Atkinson measure of inequality. Emmerling et al. (2017) propose focusing on the consumption discounting of the median-income household. Gollier (2015), noting the similarity between inequality and uncertainty, separates initial consumption level inequality and growth rate inequality. He shows an intuitive result by which the expectation of economic convergence raises the discount rate when relative prudence is larger than unity. Fleurbaey and Zuber (2015a), also addressing both inequality and uncertainty, find that extremal returns and the position of the worst-off matter. In an emerging literature of solvable model of climate change and social cost of carbon, Rezai and van der Ploeg (2016) test both one and two for the parameter of intergenerational inequality aversion.

In our study, we imagine an instantaneous distribution mechanism that determines mapping of aggregate consumption to individual consumption in each period, given the aggregate consumption growth. Assuming constant relative inequality and risk aversion, we consider the consumption discount rate that is decomposed into the aggregate consumption growth effect and the effect of intragenerational distribution change. Furthermore, we include in the framework the issues of population change in order to determine the social weights of each group, and heterogeneous “distribution” in the environmental quality. Application of the model to numerical examples of climate change reveals that the distribution effect on the consumption discount rate, especially including population or the environment, is not negligible.

The rest of the paper is structured as follows. Section 2 introduces the basic framework, and the consumption discount rate is decomposed into growth and distribution effects. Section 3 includes population as one factor affecting the changing value share of groups. Section 4 introduces unequal benefits of environmental amenity in the basic model. Section 5 illustrates the foregoing by numerical examples used in the RICE (Regional dynamic Integrated model of Climate and the Economy) model. Section 6 provides some discussion and directions for possible future works.

2 Model Description

2.1 Basic Model

The starting point of our discussion is a Bergson–Samuelson social welfare function (Drèze and Stern 1987, 1990; Johansson-Stenman 2000, 2005), which is explicit about income distribution within each generation. We consider discrete, individual groups labeled \(i =1, 2, \ldots , N\). One of the simplest expressions is:

$$\begin{aligned} W(0)= \int _0^\infty V(u(C_1(\tau )), u(C_2(\tau )), \ldots , u(C_N(\tau ))) e^{-\delta \tau } d\tau , \end{aligned}$$
(1)

where \(u(C_i(t))\) is the utility derived from consumption of group i at time t, which might be a country or a person within a group. In addition, we assume that, if it represents a group of people, \(i =1, 2, \ldots , N\) is of the same size or population. The utility discount rate, or the pure rate of time preference, is denoted by \(\delta \).Footnote 4 Furthermore, we assume a constant inequality aversion in mapping individual utility to social welfare, \(V: {\mathbb {R}}^N \rightarrow {\mathbb {R}}\). That is,

$$\begin{aligned} W(0)= \int _0^\infty \frac{1}{1-\sigma } \sum _{i=1}^N [u(C_i (\tau ))]^{1-\sigma } e^{- \delta \tau } d \tau , \end{aligned}$$
(2)

where \(\sigma \le 1\) signifies inequality aversion among different i’s. The case of \(\sigma =0\) makes a Benthamite utilitarian social welfare function. To focus on the distributional considerations, we define an intragenerational distribution mechanism \(\Delta (t): C(t) \rightarrow (C_1(t), C_2(t), \ldots , C_N(t))\), where C(t) is the aggregate consumption at t. In each period, the global aggregate consumption C(t) is given, which then is to be divided among the groups, according to the mechanism \(\Delta (t)\). More specifically, in each period, the mechanism \(\Delta (t)\) is determined so that

$$\begin{aligned} C_i(t) = \alpha _i(t) C(t), \end{aligned}$$
(3)

where \(\alpha _i(t)\) for \(i =1, 2, \ldots , N\) is the share of consumption of group i at t, and \(\sum _{i=1}^N \alpha _i(t)=1\) for all t.

Now we imagine one dollar to be invested at time 0 in a marginal project, which should yield a return of \(e^{r(t)t}\) dollars at time t under a socially efficient discount rate, r(t) (e.g., Gollier 2007).Footnote 5 Converting to the welfare numeraire, the initial investment of \(\partial W(0)/\partial C(0)\) would amount to \(e^{r(t)t} \partial W(0)/\partial C(t)\) in the future, t. This implies that it should be written, provided the social discount rate r(t) is efficient, as

$$\begin{aligned} r(t) = -\frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{\partial W(0)/\partial C(t)}{\partial W(0)/\partial C(0)}. \end{aligned}$$
(4)

It is clear from the above expression that the social consumption discount rate represents the (negative of) change rate of the shadow price of aggregate consumption from 0 to t. Expanding the right-hand side (RHS) of (4) yields, using (3),

$$\begin{aligned} r(t)&= -\frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{\sum _{i=1}^N [u(C_i(t))]^{-\sigma } u_c(C_i(t)) \alpha _i(t) e^{-\delta t} }{\sum _{i=1}^N [u(C_i(0))]^{-\sigma } u_c(C_i(0)) \alpha _i(0)} \nonumber \\&=\delta - \frac{1}{t} \ln \sum _{i=1}^N \phi _i(0) \biggl [ \frac{u(C_i(t))}{u(C_i(0))} \biggr ]^{-\sigma } \frac{u_c(C_i(t))}{u_c(C_i(0))} \frac{\alpha _i(t)}{\alpha _i(0)}, \end{aligned}$$
(5)

where

$$\begin{aligned} \phi _i(0) \equiv \frac{ [u(C_i(0))]^{-\sigma } u_c(C_i(0)) \alpha _i(0)}{\sum _{j=1}^N [ u(C_j(0)) ]^{-\sigma } u_c(C_j(0)) \alpha _j(0)} \end{aligned}$$

can be called the (initial) value share of group i at 0. This is reminiscent of the value share of the environment in Hoel and Sterner (2007), but here, we consider the value share of consumption of different groups of individuals. As can be observed, the value share is inclusive of not only the share of consumption (\(\alpha \)), but also its marginal utility (\(u_c\)) and the utility’s contribution to social welfare (\(u^{-\sigma }\)).

2.2 CRRA Utility

A standard formulation of the utility function, especially in debates on climate change, is of the constant relative risk aversion (CRRA) type. Following the literature, we suppose \(u(C_i(t)) = C_i(t)^{1-\eta }/(1-\eta )\), with \(\eta >1\) being the elasticity of the marginal utility of consumption. Plugging this specified utility into (5), by ordinary calculation, we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} r(t) = \delta - \frac{1}{t} \ln \left( \frac{C(t)}{C(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )-1} - \frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{\sum _{i=1}^N \alpha _i(t)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}{\sum _{j=1}^N \alpha _j(0)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}, \end{aligned}$$
(6)

since aggregate consumption has no suffix and thus, can be inserted prior to the summation. Then, we obtain

Proposition 1

In the case of a CRRA utility function when social groups differ in consumption, the consumption discount rate can be decomposed as

$$\begin{aligned} r(t) = \delta \underbrace{ -\frac{1}{t} \ln \left( \frac{C(t)}{C(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )-1}}_{ growth \ effect } \underbrace{-\frac{1}{t} \ln \sum _{i=1}^N \phi _i(0) \left( \frac{\alpha _i(t)}{\alpha _i(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )} }_{ distribution \ effect }, \end{aligned}$$
(7)

where the initial value share of i is

$$\begin{aligned} \phi _i(0) \equiv \frac{\alpha _i(0)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}{ \sum _{j=1}^N \alpha _j(0)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}} = \frac{c_i(0)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}{ \sum _{j=1}^N c_j(0)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}. \end{aligned}$$
(8)

As indicated, this states that now the consumption discount rate can be decomposed into the aggregate consumption growth effect, sometimes referred to as the wealth effect, and the changing distribution effect of consumption within each generation, apart from the pure rate of time preference.

The distribution effect revealed in the last term in (7) is negative (positive) when \(\sum _{i=1}^N \phi _i(0) [\frac{\alpha _i(t)}{\alpha _i(0)}]^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}\) is larger (smaller) than unity. The distribution effect disappears if \(\sum _{i=1}^N \alpha _i(t)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )} = \sum _{i=1}^N \alpha _i(0)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}\). This is clearly satisfied not only when \(\alpha _i(t)/\alpha _i(0)=1\) for all \(i=1, \ldots , N\), that is, the distribution mechanism is exactly the same between two periods under study, but also when the distribution is the same but the positions of i’s are partially or totally interchanged with each other. The latter case can be paraphrased by the case in which re-ordering all i’s by the level of consumption at t and relabeling them would yield exactly the same distribution at 0. In other words, if there is even the slightest change in the within-generation distribution mechanism, then the distribution term becomes non-zero, be the change “worse” or “better.” This is because when somebody’s consumption share becomes higher, somebody else’s is bound to be lower. In addition, note that even if the aggregate consumption does not change (i.e., \(C(t)=C(0)\)), the distribution effect is generally non-zero, so that \(r(t) \ne \delta \).

Regarding the aggregate consumption effect in (7), we have an additional term \(\sigma (1-\eta )\), besides the usual relative risk aversion, \(\eta \). This is a direct result of our social welfare function (2), in which inequality aversion parameter \(\sigma \) is attached to utility. As it seems, \(\eta \) and \(\sigma \) have precisely the same effect in (7), which is highlighted by the fact that \(\eta + \sigma (1-\eta ) = 1-(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )\). Thus, in this specific sense, they are mathematically redundant; however, in terms of ethical interpretation, they are not: \(\eta \) descriptively represents the relative risk aversion of each group or individual, i, whereas the product of \(\sigma \) and \(1-\eta \) is a normative value for intergenerational inequality aversion, and thus, is required to be determined on ethical grounds (Kaplow 2010).

If we set \(\sigma =0\), the aggregate growth effect takes the familiar form, \(\eta g\), where g is the average growth rate of aggregated consumption, and yet, the distribution remains in the form \(\frac{1}{t} \ln \sum _{i=1}^N \phi _i(0) [ \frac{\alpha _i(t)}{\alpha _i(0)}]^{(1-\eta )}\), because individuals are risk averse. This is because individual utility is still risk averse; what matters is that we have disaggregated the world into more than one individual. Introducing intragenerational heterogeneity gives rise to the distributional effect, even under utilitarian social welfare.

Given that \(\eta >1\), the inequality aversion parameter \(\sigma \) has two consequences if it is smaller than unity: the smaller \(\sigma \) is, the larger the growth effect becomes because of the intergenerational inequality aversion when the economy is growing, and the larger the distribution effect becomes. The latter occurs because the term puts a heavy weight on those whose consumption shares are decreasing. As a result, the overall effect on r(t) is ambiguous. The following simple examples facilitate understanding.

Example 1

(No growth with increasing inequality) Suppose that the economy is made up of two individuals, \(i=1,2\). The ethical parameters are set so that \((1-\sigma )(1-\eta )=-1\) (a plausible example is \(\eta =1.5\) and \(\sigma =-1\), etc.). Assume that the economy is completely stagnant from 0 to t; this zero-sum setting implies that there is no possibility of Pareto improvement. Assume also that the distribution mechanism is expected to “worsen” from \(\Delta (0): 1 \rightarrow (1/2,1/2)\) at 0 to \(\Delta (t): 1 \rightarrow (2/3,1/3)\) at t. It follows that \(\alpha _1(0)=\alpha _2(0)=1/2, \alpha _1(t)=2/3\) and \(\alpha _2(t)=1/3\), and \(\phi _1(0)=\phi _2(0)=1/2\). There is no growth effect as such, but the distribution effect isFootnote 6

$$\begin{aligned} -\frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{(2/3)^{-1}+(1/3)^{-1}}{(1/2)^{-1} + (1/2)^{-1}} =-\frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{3/2+3}{2+2} =-\,0.1178/t. \end{aligned}$$
(9)

In this example, the original state is perfectly equal, so that any change in distribution would result in a lower discount rate, other things being unchanged.

If we put more emphasis on inequality aversion by setting, say, \((1-\sigma )(1-\eta )=-2\), this becomes

$$\begin{aligned} -\frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{(2/3)^{-2}+(1/3)^{-2}}{(1/2)^{-2} + (1/2)^{-2}} =-\frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{9/4+9}{4+4} =-\,0.3409/t, \end{aligned}$$

leading to an even lower discount rate.

Example 2

(No growth toward equality) A similar example with four individuals with \(\Delta (0): 1 \rightarrow (1/2,1/6,1/6,1/6)\) at 0 to \(\Delta (t): 1 \rightarrow (1/4,1/4,1/4,1/4)\) at t indicates that the distribution effect becomes

$$\begin{aligned} -\frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{(1/4)^{-1} + (1/4)^{-1} +(1/4)^{-1} +(1/4)^{-1}}{(1/2)^{-1} +(1/6)^{-1}+(1/6)^{-1} +(1/6)^{-1}} =-\frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{4+4+4+4}{2+6+6+6} = 0.2231/t. \end{aligned}$$

This last example shows that a case is made for a higher consumption discount rate when there is no growth toward more equal (perfectly equal in this context) distribution.

Example 3

(Positive growth vs. unequal distribution) Suppose that the economy is expected to grow at a constant rate during the period [0, t] (e.g., due to an economic stimulus package), but also, that this policy is bound to make distribution more unequal (e.g., due to the policy being targeted at a specific income group). Now, in what circumstances does this distributional change nullify the growth effect in determining the consumption discount rate? Put differently, how much growth does this economy need to compensate the distributional effect on the consumption discount rate? To observe this, both effects cancel each other out if the following happens to hold

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\sum _{i=1}^N \alpha _i(t)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}{\sum _{j=1}^N \alpha _j(0)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}} =\left( \frac{C(t)}{C(0)} \right) ^{1-(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}, \end{aligned}$$

from (7). In Example 1, growth of 5.89% \((=0.1178/2)\) during the whole period is required to cancel out the distribution effect when \(1- (1-\sigma )(1-\eta )=2\). Even faster growth of 11.36% (=0.3409/3) would be required when inequality aversion is such that \(1- (1-\sigma )(1-\eta )=3\). In Example 2, negative growth of \(-11.16\% \, (=-0.2231/2)\) suffices to invalidate the distribution effect.

3 Population Change

Up until this point, we have assumed that each group i is of the same size, or almost equivalently, that i refers to an individual. Although rarely discussed in the discounting debate,Footnote 7 in application, we often want to compare groups of varied sizes, implying that distribution-conscious discounting should embody population in their weighting factors.Footnote 8

Let the objective function (2) slightly change to

$$\begin{aligned} {\bar{W}}(0)= \int _0^\infty \frac{1}{1-\sigma } \sum _{i=1}^N L_i(\tau ) \Biggl [ u \left( \frac{C_i (\tau )}{L_i(\tau )} \right) \Biggr ]^{1-\sigma } e^{- \delta \tau } d \tau , \end{aligned}$$
(10)

where \(C_i\) and \(L_i\) are consumption and population, respectively, of “country” \(i=1, \ldots , N\). Under the same utility function of the CRRA type, it is straightforward to show the following proposition.

Proposition 2

In the case of a CRRA utility function when social groups differ in consumption and population, the consumption discount rate can be decomposed as

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} {\bar{r}}(t)&= \delta -\frac{1}{t} \ln \left( \frac{C(t)}{C(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )-1} -\frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{\sum _{i=1}^N L_i(t) \left( \frac{\alpha _i(t)}{L_i(t)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}{\sum _{i=1}^N L_i(0) \left( \frac{\alpha _i(0)}{L_i(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}} \\&=\delta -\frac{1}{t} \ln \left( \frac{C(t)}{C(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )-1} \\&\quad -\frac{1}{t} \ln \sum _{i=1}^N \varphi _i(0) \left( \frac{ L_i(t)}{L_i(0)} \right) ^{1-(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )} \left( \frac{\alpha _i(t)}{\alpha _i(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )} \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(11)

where the initial value share of i is defined by

$$\begin{aligned} \varphi _i(0) \equiv \frac{L_i(0) \left( \frac{\alpha _i(0)}{L_i(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}{\sum _{j=1}^N L_j(0) \left( \frac{\alpha _j(0)}{L_j(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}. \end{aligned}$$
(12)

The growth effect of aggregate consumption is preserved from Proposition 1. By contrast, the value share of a group in social welfare is altered slightly to include population change. In addition, the distribution effect is now inclusive of population change of individual groups. We observe that with a given distribution mechanism, increasing population of any group i implies a lower discount rate, assuming normal values for inequality and risk aversion parameters. This aspect is more explicitly noted in the following special case.

Corollary 2

If the annualized population growth rate of group i is n for all i, then the consumption discount rate with different population groups is

$$\begin{aligned} {\bar{r}}(t) =\delta -\frac{1}{t} \ln \left( \frac{C(t)}{C(0)} e^{-nt} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )-1} -\frac{1}{t} \ln \sum _{i=1}^N \varphi _i(0) \left( \frac{\alpha _i(t)}{\alpha _i(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}. \end{aligned}$$
(13)

The annualized growth effect in this case changes to the growth rate of aggregate consumption per capita across all the groups, weighted by risk and inequality aversion, whereas the distribution effect is of the same form as Proposition 1. It is also easy to check from (13) that, other things being equal, the higher n is, the lower \({\bar{r}}(t)\) becomes.

4 Unequally Distributed Environmental Amenity

The current literature on the economics of climate change focuses on how aggregate consumption changes along the path. As long as climate change ultimately affects final consumption, this approach should be sufficient. It could be the case, however, that a change in the environment directly affects well-being, rather than by way of the consumption–utility nexus. This typically represents circumstances in which the environment has an amenity value (e.g., Krautkraemer 1985) or pollution causes disutility (e.g., Xepapadeas 2005). Since the substitution possibility between consumption and the environment is considered limited, it is shown by Hoel and Sterner (2007) that consumption discount rates are likely to become even lower in a growing economy with deteriorating environment. Thus, in the current context, it is worth exploring a case in which there is intragenerational equity in terms of the environment as an amenity, as well as intragenerational equity in consumption. To consider such a case, the objective function (2) is now modified to

$$\begin{aligned} {\hat{W}}(0)= \int _0^\infty \frac{1}{1-\sigma } \sum _{i=1}^N [u(C_i (\tau ),E_i (\tau ))]^{1-\sigma } e^{- \delta \tau } d \tau , \end{aligned}$$
(14)

where \(E_i (\tau )\) stands for the benefit i receives from the global environmental quality at \(\tau \), \(E(\tau )\), such as the atmosphere as a carbon sink. When the environmental quality is a pure public good, we assume \(E_i(\tau )=E(\tau )\) for all i. In general, suppose that the environmental quality is not a pure public good, and its benefit is received unevenly between agents according to the enhanced distribution mechanism \({\hat{\Delta }}(t): X(t) \rightarrow (x_1(t), x_2(t), \ldots , x_N(t))\), where \(X(t)=[C(t),E(t)]^{-1}\) and \(x_i(t)=[C_i(t),E_i(t)]^{-1}\) are the vectors of aggregate and individual consumption and environmental quality.

Unless the utility function is separable between consumption and the environment, changing marginal utility involves the relative abundance of the environment, so that a discount rate should include its quantity even if the numeraire is consumption. Following Hoel and Sterner (2007), consider a constant elasticity of substitution (CES), \(0<\epsilon \le 1\), between consumption and the environment:

$$\begin{aligned} u(C_i,E_i)=\frac{1}{1-\eta } \biggl [ (1-\beta ) C_i^{1-\frac{1}{\epsilon }} +\beta E_i^{1-\frac{1}{\epsilon }} \biggr ]^{\frac{\epsilon (1-\eta )}{\epsilon -1}}, \end{aligned}$$
(15)

where \(0<\beta <1\) is a relative weight factor. Define \(\gamma _i(t)=E_i(t)/E(t)\) as the portion i benefits from the environment where \(\sum _i^N \gamma _i(t)=1\). Simple calculation leads to the following proposition.

Proposition 3

In the case of a CES-CRRA utility function that depends on consumption and the environment, when social groups differ in consumption, the consumption discount rate can be written as

$$\begin{aligned} {\hat{r}}(t)&= \delta -\frac{1}{t} \ln \left( \frac{C(t)}{C(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )-1} \nonumber \\&\quad -\,\frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{\sum _{i=1}^N \left( 1 +\frac{\beta }{1-\beta } \bigl [ \frac{\gamma _i(t) E(t)}{\alpha _i(t) C(t)} \bigr ]^{1-\frac{1}{\epsilon }} \right) ^{\frac{\epsilon (1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}{\epsilon -1}-1} \alpha _i(t)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}{\sum _{i=1}^N \left( 1+\frac{\beta }{1-\beta } \bigl [ \frac{\gamma _i(0) E(0)}{\alpha _i(0) C(0)} \bigr ]^{1-\frac{1}{\epsilon }} \right) ^{\frac{\epsilon (1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}{\epsilon -1}-1} \alpha _i(0)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}, \end{aligned}$$
(16)

To separate the last term in (16) into the pure environmental effect and distributional concerns, we consider two sub-classes in the following.

Example 1

(Cobb–Douglas preference) The limiting case in which \(\epsilon \rightarrow 1\) in the above CES utility corresponds to the Cobb–Douglas preference regarding consumption and the environment. That is, we obtain

$$\begin{aligned} u(C_i,E_i)=\frac{1}{1-\eta } \left( C_i^{1-\beta } E_i^{\beta } \right) ^{(1-\eta )}. \end{aligned}$$
(17)

Then, the consumption discount rate is reduced to

$$\begin{aligned} {\hat{r}}(t)&= \delta -\frac{1}{t} \ln \left( \frac{C(t)}{C(0)} \right) ^{(1-\beta )(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )-1} -\frac{1}{t} \ln \left( \frac{E(t)}{E(0)} \right) ^{\beta (1-\sigma )(1-\eta )} \nonumber \\&\quad -\frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{\sum _{i=1}^N \left( \alpha _i(t)^{(1-\beta )} \gamma _i(t)^\beta \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )-1}}{\sum _{i=1}^N \left( \alpha _i(0)^{(1-\beta )} \gamma _i(0)^\beta \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )-1}}. \end{aligned}$$
(18)

This variant is decomposed into the growth, environmental growth, and distribution effects (second, third, and fourth terms in the RHS of (18), respectively). The growth effect is weakened precisely for the portion of consumption that succumbs to the environment in preferences. As long as the environmental quality is improving, the environmental growth effect pushes up the discount rate by its growth rate multiplied by \(\beta (\eta -1)(1-\sigma )\) if \(\sigma <1\). In other words, a better (worse) environmental amenity, to a certain extent, attenuates (amplifies) the effect of the worsening growth or distribution in consumption. This is due to the important limitations we pose in this Example: that consumption goods and the environmental amenity are perfectly substitutable (\(\epsilon \rightarrow 1\)). In addition, note that the distribution effect now reflects how the environment benefits each group. Observe also that this distribution effect differs from the last term in (7) in Proposition 1, unless \(\alpha _i(\tau )=\gamma _i(\tau )\)\(\forall i\) for \(\tau =0,t\), or unless \(\beta = 0\).

Example 2

(Inequality in the environmental amenity can be approximated by consumption inequality) Another way to decouple the environmental effect from the overall discounting is to suppose that the distribution of environmental quality happens to be proportional to distribution in consumption, namely, \(\alpha _i(\tau )=\gamma _i(\tau )\) for \(\tau =0,t\). In fact, Nordhaus and Boyer (2000) suggest that 2.5-degree temperature warming results in damage equivalent to 0.5% of national gross domestic product, implying that environmental damage can be proportional to consumption. Of course, this is just a first approximation and it should be considered that the most vulnerable groups are likely to be damaged disproportionately.Footnote 9 Then, (16) in Proposition 3 is approximately simplified to

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} {\hat{r}}(t) \approx&\ \delta -\frac{1}{t} \ln \left( \frac{C(t)}{C(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )-1} \\&-\frac{1}{t} \frac{\beta }{1-\beta } \left( \frac{\epsilon (1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}{\epsilon -1}-1 \right) \left( \biggl [ \frac{E(t)}{C(t)} \biggr ]^{1-\frac{1}{\epsilon }} - \biggl [ \frac{E(0)}{C(0)}\biggr ]^{1-\frac{1}{\epsilon }} \right) \\&-\frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{\sum _{i=1}^N \alpha _i(t)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}{\sum _{i=1}^N \alpha _i(0)^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}. \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(19)

Observe that the third term on the RHS of (23) represents the changing scarcity of the environment relative to general consumption goods and how much they are valued in the economy. Evidently, the larger \(\beta \) is, the larger this environmental effect becomes. The sign of the environmental effect depends on the choice of parameters, as well as on whether the environment improves relative to the increase in consumption goods. If \(1-(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )>1/\epsilon \) holds, then inequality aversion both at societal and individual levels and substitutability are all high, and thus, an improving (degrading) environmental amenity translates into a higher (lower) consumption discount rate, other things being equal.Footnote 10 Otherwise, the substitutability between consumption and the environment is so poor that inequality aversion does not compensate for it, and together, they lower the discount rate in an improving environment.

An obvious lesson from (23) is that, if the environmental amenity is unevenly distributed in the same manner as general consumption is, the distribution effect in discounting does not change, as is clear from the last term. However, imagine the rural poor with low consumption and high endowment of natural environment.Footnote 11 Since this type of the poor likely enjoy the natural environment, it could be the case that consumption distribution is inversely related to environmental distribution. More generally, there is some evidence that the environmental amenity is even more unequally distributed between developed and developing countries, particularly regarding climate change. Thus, in Sect. 5, we also show an alternative case where environmental distribution is equalized among regions, for want of a sound theory or data of environmental distribution.

4.1 Population- and Environment-Adjusted Discounting

Finally, we consider population adjusted social welfare function that includes consumption and the environment:

$$\begin{aligned} {\tilde{W}}_1(0)= \int _0^\infty \frac{1}{1-\sigma } \sum _{i=1}^N L_i(\tau ) \Biggl [ u \left( \frac{C_i (\tau )}{L_i(\tau )}, E_i (\tau ) \right) \Biggr ]^{1-\sigma } e^{- \delta \tau } d \tau , \end{aligned}$$
(20)

where we have assumed that the environmental amenity is a public good within each region, that is, each individual in a given nation consumes exactly the same amount of amenity. Then, a counterpart to (16) isFootnote 12

$$\begin{aligned} \begin{aligned} {\tilde{r}}_1(t)&= \delta -\frac{1}{t} \ln \left( \frac{C(t)}{C(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )-1} \\&\quad -\,\frac{1}{t} \ln \frac{\sum _{i=1}^N L_i(t) \left( 1 +\frac{\beta }{1-\beta } \bigl [ \frac{\gamma _i(t) L_i(t) E(t)}{\alpha _i(t) C(t)} \bigr ]^{1-\frac{1}{\epsilon }} \right) ^{\frac{\epsilon (1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}{\epsilon -1}-1} \left( \frac{\alpha _i(t)}{L_i(t)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}{\sum _{i=1}^N L_i(0) \left( 1+\frac{\beta }{1-\beta } \bigl [ \frac{\gamma _i(0) L_i(0) E(0)}{\alpha _i(0) C(0)} \bigr ]^{1-\frac{1}{\epsilon }} \right) ^{\frac{\epsilon (1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}{\epsilon -1}-1} \left( \frac{\alpha _i(0)}{L_i(0)} \right) ^{(1-\sigma )(1-\eta )}}. \end{aligned} \end{aligned}$$
(25)

5 An Illustration

To obtain a sense of the order of the magnitude of the effect of distribution on discounting, we expound numerical examples in this section. In this section, we rescale individual utility by assuming

$$\begin{aligned} u(C_i) = \frac{C_i^{1-\eta }}{1-\eta } - \frac{{\underline{C}}^{1-\eta }}{1-\eta }, \end{aligned}$$
(21)

or

$$\begin{aligned} u(C_i,E_i) \!=\!\frac{1}{1\!-\!\eta } \left( \biggl [ (1\!-\!\beta ) C_i^{1-\frac{1}{\epsilon }} \!+\!\beta E_i^{1-\frac{1}{\epsilon }} \biggr ]^{\frac{\epsilon (1\!-\!\eta )}{\epsilon -1}} - \biggl [ (1-\beta ) {\underline{C}}^{1-\frac{1}{\epsilon }} +\beta {\underline{E}}^{1-\frac{1}{\epsilon }} \biggr ]^{\frac{\epsilon (1-\eta )}{\epsilon -1}} \right) ,\nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
(22)

where minimum subsistence consumption and the environment are denoted by \({\underline{C}}\) and \({\underline{E}}\), so that we can take the full rage of \(\eta \) and \(\sigma \), since the utility is now non-negative. Although our central motivation for this specification is technical, this CRRA utility with minimum subsistence level has a good pedigree in the literature.Footnote 13

The basic parameters to be employed for our illustrative purposes are shown in Table 1. For data, we use the “no controls (baseline)” results of the regionally disaggregated RICE model of Nordhaus and Boyer (2000), which divides the world into 12 regions.Footnote 14 More specifically, we employ the already calibrated regional consumption data divided by world consumption as regional shares of consumption.

Table 1 Assumptions in the numerical examples

Figure 1 shows the consumption discount rates with distributional effects without (left panel) or with (right panel) population weights, corresponding to Propositions 1 and 2. Note that consumption discount rate comes largely from aggregate consumption growth effect, represented by the dotted line. Since it is projected in RICE that world consumption growth gradually declines, the growth effect also weakens over time. The distribution effect, represented by the dashed line, is relatively small and crawls around 0 in centuries from now. The latter is in part due to the fact that large emerging economies boost their share of aggregate consumption, while the developed world (the US, the EU, and Japan) decrease their share steeply, so that the overall distribution improves. In particular, in the latter half of the current century, Africa continues to increase its share. As the breakdown of world aggregate consumption does not change dramatically in approximately 1 century from now, it is not surprising then that the distribution effect is also expected to be negligible.

The distribution effect, however, becomes larger when each region is weighted with their population, as is seen in the right panel of Fig. 1. Distribution in consumption actually moderately improves, in the sense that densely populated developing regions increase their share of aggregate consumption. Consequently, consumption discount rate is raised by < 2%.

Fig. 1
figure 1

Decomposition of a consumption discount rate into growth and intragenerational distribution effects. The left panel considers aggregate consumption of individual groups, while the right panel considers consumption per capita, corresponding to Propositions 1 and 2, respectively

Fig. 2
figure 2

Decomposition of a consumption discount rate into growth and intragenerational distribution effects of consumption and the environment, when the environmental distribution matches consumption distribution (the left panel), or when the environmental distribution is equalized among the 12 regions under study (the right panel)

Fig. 3
figure 3

Decomposition of a consumption discount rate into growth and population-adjusted intragenerational distribution effects of consumption and the environment, when the environmental distribution matches consumption distribution (the left panel), or when the environmental distribution is equalized among the 12 regions under study (the right panel)

Figure 2 assumes that utility now depends on both consumption and the environment, without population weighting. For want of sound theory or data on how environmental amenity is distributed in the world, in the left panel it is assumed that inequality in the environmental amenity can be approximated by consumption inequality (Example 2 in Sect. 4), whereas in the right panel it is assumed that the proportions of environmental amenity a region receives are equal across regions in the world, regardless of the population, so that \(\gamma _i=1/12 \forall i\) for [0, t] in our example.Footnote 15 In addition, suppose that the global source of environmental amenity diminishes by 5% each decade, that is, \(E(t)/C(t)=0.95*E(t-1)/C(t-1)\). As a result, again, the consumption discount rate consists largely of the (combined) growth effect, with the distribution effect being minimal.

In Fig. 3, however, it is apparent that considering both the environment and population weighting changes the big picture (see (23)). In particular, the distribution effect becomes negative, being at the order of − 3 to − 1%, which decreases the consumption discount rate.Footnote 16

In summary, the seemingly negligible distribution effect turns positive when population is taken into account, because distribution improves as populous developing nations boost their consumption levels. However, once the distribution in the deteriorating environment enters the formula, the distribution effect is likely to be negative. This suggests that “improvement (worsening)” in distribution may be misleading in the absence of population and environmental concerns.

6 Concluding Remarks

In this study, we showed disaggregation of distributional components from the pure growth effect in consumption discount rates, when groups of agents in the Ramsey model are heterogeneous. In so doing, we highlighted the role of population in social weights of different groups. In addition, if environmental amenity is indeed worth highlighting in the determination of discounting and relative prices, as pointed out by Hoel and Sterner (2007) and Sterner and Persson (2008), then the “distribution” of environmental amenity around the globe should also be incorporated. Our numerical exercise suggests that the order of the magnitude of distribution effects is not overwhelming, but is still non-negligible. It is worthwhile noting that, in particular, the positive distribution effect turns negative when incorporating population and the environment.

We did not address an important aspect of long-term cost-benefit analysis, namely, uncertainty. The effects of uncertainty on discount rates have already been well treated in the literature, in particular, by Emmerling (2018) and Gollier (2012) in the current context. A possible extension of our model in this regard is to consider uncertainty in population. For example, a geometric Brownian motion of future population,

$$\begin{aligned} dL=nLds+\sigma Ldz, \end{aligned}$$

would yield an interesting modification of (11).

It is also important to note that the current approach cannot tell a “better” from a “worse” distribution change, regardless of how they are defined. In other words, the exogenous distribution effect in our model captures only changing distribution, regardless of the direction in which the distributional trend is heading; our motivation is that the current distribution can be set as a benchmark, from which future distribution deviates to an unequal world. An obvious challenge for a better calibration is to obtain empirical data on how environmental amenity is unequally distributed.

In addition, care should be taken which level of inequality we would like to address. As is stated often, international income disparities are increasingly replaced by domestic disparities, while the gap between developed and less developed nations is being narrowed (Milanovic 2016), which is exactly why some of the latter nations are referred to as emerging nations. On the other hand, Milanovic (2010) argues that Asian and European countries are relatively homogeneous within their national borders, but there are wide variations in consumption levels of different countries. Our discussion is more applicable to the latter situation, while it is easy to extend to more multi-layered inequality.