Skip to main content
Log in

Leges sine moribus vanae: does language make moral thinking possible?

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Does language make moral cognition possible? Some authors like Andy Clark have argued for a positive answer whereby language and the ways people use it mark a fundamental divide between humans and all other animals with respect to moral thinking (Clark, Mind and morals: essays on cognitive science and ethics. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1996; Moral Epistemol Nat Can J Philos Suppl XXVI, 2000a; Moral Epistemol Nat Can J Philos Suppl XXVI, 2000b; Philosophy of mental representation. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 37–43 and discussion, 44–61, 2002). I take issue with Clark’s view and argue that language is probably unnecessary for the emergence of moral cognition. I acknowledge, however, that humans unlike other animals seem to posses what Haugeland in Philosophy of mental representation. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2002) terms ‘norm-hungriness’: an idiosyncratic need or desire to create and abide by a multitude of norms. Our peculiar norm-hungriness, I suggest, depends on what can be called florid control rather than on language.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The fact that some non-human animals engage in altruistic behaviour does not clash with my suggestion that non-human animals cannot be motivated to engage in biologically-arbitrary behaviour. In fact, unlike biologically-arbitrary behaviour as characterised above, altruistic behaviour is defined as behaviour that has both costly fitness consequences to the actors and beneficial fitness consequences to others.

  2. Churchland (2011, p. 26) writes: ‘Of course only humans have human morality. But that is not news, simply a tedious tautology. One might as well note that only marmoset have marmoset morality, and so on down the line. We can agree that ants are not moral in the way humans are, and that baboon and bonobo social behavior is much closer to our own.’

References

  • Bermúdez JL (2003) Thinking without words. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bicchieri C, Xiao E (2008) Do the right thing: but only if others do so. J Behav Decis Mak 21:1–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bovet D, Washburn DA (2003) Rhesus macaques (Macaca mulatta) categorize unknown conspecifics according to their dominance relations. J Comp Psych 117:400–405

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers P (2002) The cognitive functions of language. Behav Brain Sci 25:657–726

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PM (1995) The engine of reason, the seat of the soul: a philosophical journey into the brain. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PM (1996) The neural representation of the social world. In: May L, Friedman M, Clark A (eds) Mind and morals: essays on cognitive science and ethics. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PM (2000) Rules, know-how, and the future of moral cognition. In: Campbell R, Hunter B (eds) Moral epistemology naturalized: Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume XXVI, pp 291–306

  • Churchland PS (2011) Braintrust: what neuroscience tells us about morality. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Cialdini R (2003) Crafting normative messages to protect the environment. Curr Dir Psych Sci 12:105–109

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clapin H (ed) (2002) Philosophy of mental representation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1996) Connectionism, moral cognition and collaborative problem solving. In: May L, Friedman M, Clark A (eds) Mind and morals: essays on cognitive science and ethics. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1997) Being there: putting brain, body and world together again. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1998) Magic words: how language augments human computation. In: Carruthers P, Boucher J (eds) Language and thought: interdisciplinary themes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2000a) Word and action: reconciling rules and know-how in moral cognition. In: Campbell R, Hunter B (eds) Moral epistemology naturalized: Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume XXVI, pp 267–290

  • Clark A (2000b) Making moral space. A reply to Churchland. In: Campbell R, Hunter B (eds) Moral epistemology naturalized: Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary Volume XXVI, pp 307–312

  • Clark A (2002) The roots of norm-hungriness. Response to John Haugeland. In: Clapin H (ed) Philosophy of mental representation. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 37–43 and discussion, 44–61

  • Clark A (2006a) Material symbols. Phil Psych 19:291–307

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2006b) Language embodiment and the cognitive niche. Trends Cog Sci 10:370–374

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (2008) Supersizing the mind: embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A, Thornton C (1997) Trading spaces: computation, representation, and limits of uninformed learning. Behav Brain Sci 20:57–90

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen JD, Braver TS, Brown JW (2002) Computational perspectives on dopamine function in prefrontal cortex. Curr Opin Neurobiol 12:223–229

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasser V (1988) A social concept in Java monkeys. Anim Behav 36:225–230

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Waal FBM (1996) Good natured: the origins of right and wrong in humans and other animals. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal FBM, Tyack PL (eds) (2003) Animal social complexity: intelligence, culture and individualized societies. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett D (1991) Consciousness explained. Little Brown, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Doll BB, Jacobs WJ, Sanfey AG, Frank MJ (2009) Instructional control of reinforcement learning: a behavioral and neurocomputational investigation. Brain Res 1299:74–94

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forbes CE, Grafman J (2010) The role of the human prefrontal cortex in social cognition and moral judgment. Annu Rev Neurosci 33:299–324

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frank RH (1988) Passions within reason: the strategic role of the emotions. WW Norton and Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuster JM (2008) The prefrontal cortex, 4th edn. Academic Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard A (1990) Wise choices, apt feelings: a theory of normative judgment. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein N, Cialdini R, Griskevicius R (2008) A room with a viewpoint: using social norms to motivate environmental conservation in hotels. J Cons Res 35:472–482

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking I (1995) The looping effects of human kinds. In: Sperber D, Premack D, Premack AJ (eds) Causal cognition: a multidisciplinary debate. Clarendon Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland J (2002) Andy Clark on cognition and representation. In: Clapin H (ed) Philosophy of mental representation. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaas JH, Preuss TM (2008) Human brain evolution. In: Squire LR, Berg D, Bloom FE, du Lac S, Ghosh A, Spizer NC (eds) Fundamental neuroscience, 3rd edn. Academic Press, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirsh D, Maglio P (1992) Reaction and reflection in Tetris. In: Hendler J (ed) Artificial intelligence planning systems: proceedings of the first annual conference AIPS. Morgan Kaufmann, San Mateo, CA

    Google Scholar 

  • Li J, Delgado MR, Phelps EA (2011) How instructed knowledge modulates the neural systems of reward learning. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 108:55–60

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahajan N, Martinez M, Gutierrez N, Diesendruck G, Banaji M, Santos L (2011) The evolution of intergroup bias: perception and attitudes in rhesus macaques. J Pers Soc Psych 100:387–405

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montague PR (2007) Your brain is almost perfect: how we make decisions. Plume, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague PR, Hyman SE, Cohen JD (2004) Computational roles for dopamine in behavioural control. Nature 431:760–767

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preuss TM (2009) The cognitive neuroscience of human uniqueness. In: Gazzaniga MS (ed) The cognitive neurosciences, 4th edn. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Preuss TM (2011) The human brain: rewired and running hot. Ann NY Acad Sci 1225(Suppl 1):E182–E191

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raghanti MA, Stimpson CD, Marcinkiewicz JL, Erwin JM, Hof PR, Sherwood CC (2008) Cortical dopaminergic innervation among humans, chimpanzees, and macaque monkeys: a comparative study. Neuroscience 155:203–220

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Redgrave P (2007) Basal ganglia. Scholarpedia 2(6):1825. URL=<http://www.scholarpedia.org/article/Basal_ganglia>

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins T, Arnsten A (2009) The neuropsychopharmacology of fronto-executive function: monoaminergic modulation. Annu Rev Neurosci 32:267–287

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands M (2012) Can animals be moral?. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Seamans J, Durstewitz D (2008) Dopamine modulation. Scholarpedia 3(4):2711. URL=<http://www.scholarpedia.org/article/Dopamine_modulation>

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (1995) The construction of social reality. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sripada CS, Stich S (2007) A framework for the psychology of moral norms. In: Carruthers P, Laurence S, Stich S (eds) Innateness and the structure of the mind, vol II. Oxford University Press, London, pp 280–302

  • Stone VE (2007) The evolution of ontogeny and human cognitive uniqueness: selection for extended brain development in the hominid line. In: Platek SM, Keenan JP, Shackelford TK (eds) Evolutionary cognitive neuroscience. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Suhler CL, Churchland PS (2009) Control: conscious and otherwise. Trends Cog Sci 13:341–347

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson RKR, Oden DL (1998) Why monkeys and pigeons, unlike certain apes, cannot reason analogically. In: Holyoak K, Gentner D, Kokinov B (eds) Advances in analogy research: integration of theory and data from the cognitive, computational, and neural sciences. New Bulgarian University Press, Sofia

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson RKR, Oden DL, Boysen ST (1997) Language-naive chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes) judge relations between relations in a conceptual matching-to-sample task. J Exp Psychol Anim Behav Process 23:31–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M, Call J (1997) Primate cognition. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am sincerely grateful to Andy Clark, Liz Irvine, Julian Kiverstein, Mike Wheeler, Chiara Lisciandra and Jan Sprenger for their generous feedback on previous versions of this paper. A special thank you to an anonymous referee for this journal and to the editor, Kim Sterelny, for their constructive comments and helpful suggestions. This work was supported by a grant from the Deutsche Forschungsgemeinschaft (DFG) as part of the priority program “New Frameworks of Rationality” (SPP 1516). The usual disclaimers about any error or mistake in the paper apply.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Matteo Colombo.

Additional information

From Horace, Odes, III, 24. Transl.: “Laws without morals [are] empty.”

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Colombo, M. Leges sine moribus vanae: does language make moral thinking possible?. Biol Philos 28, 501–521 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-012-9346-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-012-9346-y

Keywords

Navigation