Skip to main content
Log in

Sequential procurement auctions with risk-averse suppliers

  • Published:
Journal of Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We compare two procurement mechanisms, bundling and unbundling, in a two-stage auction model with risk-averse suppliers. The mechanisms differ in that the two tasks of investment and production are procured through a single auction or two sequential auctions. Suppliers’ production costs are affected by two risk factors, aggregate risk and idiosyncratic risk, as well as by the cost-reducing investment. We show that the bundling mechanism is optimal for a buyer and socially desirable if the aggregate risk is below certain thresholds. The result may not hold true for idiosyncratic risk.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Engineering News-Record (ENR) annually reports the top 100 design-build firms (ENR 2012).

  2. We allow the case that \(\bar{\theta } = \infty \). In this case, we also assume that \(E[\exp (r \theta _i)] < \infty \), which guarantees that an associated risk premium is finite. Here, \(E[\cdot ]\) is the expectation operator.

  3. We write \(f > 0\) if \(f(\theta _i) > 0\) for any \(\theta _i \in [\underline{\theta }, \bar{\theta }]\). We use the same notation for other functions.

  4. We allow \(\underline{\theta }\) and \(\bar{\theta }\) to depend on \(\kappa \). We also assume that if \(\bar{\theta } = \infty \) for some \(\kappa \), then there exists \(m > 0\) such that \(f(\theta ; \kappa ') \le f(\theta ; \kappa )\) for any \(\theta \ge m\) and any \(\kappa '\) with \(\kappa ' < \kappa \). See Hanoch and Levy (1969) for the definition of second-order stochastic dominance.

  5. That is, \(F(\theta ; \kappa ) \rightarrow 0\) as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\) for any \(\theta < 0\), and \(F(\theta ; \kappa ) \rightarrow 1\) as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\) for any \(\theta > 0\).

  6. We assume that if there is a tie, then the supplier submitting the lowest bid wins with equal probability. All results hold for any other tie-breaking rule.

  7. It will be shown that the first-stage bid and the identity of the first-stage winner have no effect on either the investment level or the second-stage bid in equilibrium.

  8. For any random variable \(\pi \), the certainty equivalent \(E[\pi ] - \rho \) with the risk premium \(\rho \) is determined by \(u(E[\pi ] - \rho ) = E[u(\pi )]\). The risk premium is calculated as \(\rho = E[\pi ] + \frac{1}{r} \ln E[\exp (- r \pi ) ]\).

  9. This contract is suggested by an anonymous referee.

  10. Under this assumption, all suppliers know the first-stage winner’s private parameter from the announced reserve price with the investment level and the realized value of the aggregate risk.

  11. We implicitly assume that \(n \ge 3\). However, even if \(n =2\), all results are still valid, assuming that a first-stage winner offers a price equal to his production cost to the other supplier.

  12. Even if \(\bar{\theta } = \infty \), we can find such number \(m\) using the assumption detailed in footnote 4.

References

  • Auriol E, Laffont JJ (1992) Regulation by duopoly. J Econ Manag Strateg 1(3):507–533

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ENR (2012) The top 100 design-build firms. http://enr.construction.com/toplists/DesignBuild/001-100.asp

  • Gibson GEJ, O’Connor JT, Migliaccio G, Walewski J (2007) Key implementation issues and lessens learned with design-build projects. In: Molenaar KR, Yakowenko G (eds) Alternative project delivery, procurement, and contracting methods for highways. American Society of Civil Engineers

  • Grimm V (2007) Sequential versus bundle auctions for recurring procurement. J Econ 90(1):1–27

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hanoch G, Levy H (1969) The efficiency analysis of choices involving risk. Rev Econ Stud 36(3):335–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart O (2003) Incomplete contracts and public ownership: remarks, and an application to public-private partnerships. Econ J 113:C69–C76

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holt C (1980) Competitive bidding for contracts under alternative auction procedures. J Polit Econ 88(3):433–445

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hoppe EI, Kusterer DJ, Schmitz PW (2013) Public-private partnerships versus traditional procurement: an experimental investigation. J Econ Behav Organ 89:145–166

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iossa E, Spagnolo G, Vellez M (2007) Contract design in public-private partnerships. Report prepared for the World Bank, Washington, DC

  • Kay M (2009) Transportation megaproject procurement: Benefits and challenges for PPPs and alternative delivery strategies, and the resulting implications for Crossrail. PhD thesis, Massachusetts Institute of Technology, Cambridge

  • Li S, Yu J (2011) Bundling decisions in procurement auctions with sequential tasks. http://riem.swufe.edu.cn/riem/uploadfile/201110/18/10300593.pdf

  • Martimort D, Pouyet J (2008) To build or not to build: normative and positive theories of public-private partnerships. Int J Ind Organ 26(2):393–411

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • OECD (2008) Public-private partnerships—in pursuit of risk sharing and value for money. OECD

  • Yescombe ER (2007) Public-private partnerships: principles of policy and finance. Butterworth-Heinemann, UK

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank an editor and two anonymous referees for their invaluable suggestions and comments. I am grateful to my advisor Akira Okada for his invaluable guidance and encouragement. I would like to thank Reiko Aoki, Yasuhiro Arai, Chiaki Hara, Ron Harstad, Kazumi Hori, Hideshi Itoh, Takashi Kunimoto, Nozomu Muto, Daisuke Oyama, Hamid Sabourian, Hannu Salonen, Giulio Seccia, Yasuhiro Shirata, Toshihiro Tsuchihashi, and seminar participants at Hokkaido University, Kansai Game Theory Seminar, Contract Theory Workshop, 16th Decentralization Conference, Hitotsubashi G-COE Lectures and Workshop on Choice, Games, and Welfare, 2011 Asian Meeting of Econometric Society, Kyoto University for their thoughtful comments and suggestions. The support of the Global COE program and the Research Unit for Statistical and Empirical Analysis in Social Sciences at Hitotsubashi University is gratefully acknowledged.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Takeshi Nishimura.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Proposition 1

First, the efficient investment level \(\tilde{a}\) minimizes \(\psi (a) + E[\theta _{(n)} + \omega ] - \delta a \); thus, the level is uniquely determined by the first-order condition

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{d \psi }{da}(\tilde{a}) = \delta . \end{aligned}$$
(10)

In the bundling mechanism, a winner chooses an investment level to maximize the certainty equivalent \(p^1_i - \psi (a) + \delta a - \rho ^*\). Since the risk premium \(\rho ^*\) does not depend on \(a\), the equilibrium investment level is the same as the efficient level \(\tilde{a}\). Next, the auction is equivalent to the Bertrand competition among symmetric suppliers. Thus, in any symmetric equilibrium, all suppliers submit the same bid \(\psi (\tilde{a}) -\delta \tilde{a} + \rho ^{*}\). \(\square \)

Proof of Lemma 1

We must show that for any \(a\) and \(\omega \), a supplier with \(\theta \) cannot gain by deviating from a bid \(p^2(a, \theta , \omega )\) when the other suppliers follow the strategy \(p^2(\cdot )\). Note that \(p^2(\cdot )\) is increasing and continuous in \(\theta \).

First, we can assume without loss of generality that no supplier submits a bid \(p \not \in [p^2(a, \underline{\theta }, \omega ), p^2(a, \bar{\theta }, \omega )]\). If a supplier bids \(p > p^2(a, \bar{\theta }, \omega )\), then he loses with probability one. By bidding \(p^2(a, \bar{\theta }, \omega )\), he can obtain the same utility. If a supplier bids \(p < p^2(a, \underline{\theta }, \omega )\), then he wins with probability one. By bidding \(p^2(a, \underline{\theta }, \omega )\), he can win with probability one and obtain higher utility.

Second, we show that it is optimal for a supplier with \(\theta \) to bid \(p = p^2(a, \theta , \omega )\). Consider the following two cases: The supplier wins or loses in the first stage. If the supplier loses in the first-stage auction, then his expected utility from bidding \(p^2(a, \hat{\theta }, \omega )\) is

$$\begin{aligned}&\ (1-F_{(n-1)}(\hat{\theta })) u(p^2(a, \hat{\theta }, \omega ) - c(a, \theta ,\omega ) ) + F_{(n-1)}(\hat{\theta }) u(0) \\&\quad = (1-F_{(n-1)}(\hat{\theta })) \int \limits _{\hat{\theta }}^{\bar{\theta }} \left[ 1 - \exp (-r (s - \theta )) \right] \frac{f_{(n-1)}(s)}{1-F_{(n-1)}(\hat{\theta })} ds \\&\quad = \int \limits _{\hat{\theta }}^{\bar{\theta }} u(s - \theta ) f_{(n-1)}(s) ds. \end{aligned}$$

The equalities follow from the definitions of \(u(\cdot )\) and \(p^2(\cdot )\). The difference between the expected utility from bidding \(p^2(a, \theta , \omega )\) and that from bidding \(p^2(a, \hat{\theta }, \omega ) \not = p^2(a, \theta , \omega )\) is

$$\begin{aligned} \int \limits _{\theta }^{\hat{\theta }} u(s - \theta ) f_{(n-1)}(s) ds > 0. \end{aligned}$$

In contrast, if the supplier wins with a bid \(p^1\) in the first-stage auction, then his expected utility from bidding \(p^2(a, \hat{\theta }, \omega )\) is given by

$$\begin{aligned}&\ (1-F_{(n-1)}(\hat{\theta })) u(p^1 - \psi (a) + p^2(a, \hat{\theta }, \omega ) - c(a, \theta , \omega ) ) {+} F_{(n-1)}(\hat{\theta }) u(p^1 - \psi (a)) \\&\quad = u(p^1 - \psi (a)) + \exp (-r(p^1 - \psi (a))) \left\{ \int \limits _{\hat{\theta }}^{\bar{\theta }} u(s - \theta ) f_{(n-1)}(s) ds \right\} . \end{aligned}$$

The equality follows from some additional calculations. The difference between the expected utility from bidding \(p^2(a, \theta , \omega )\) and that from bidding \(p^2(a, \hat{\theta }, \omega ) \not = p^2(a, \theta , \omega )\) is

$$\begin{aligned} \exp (-r(p^1 - \psi (a))) \left\{ \int \limits _{\theta }^{\hat{\theta }} u(s - \theta ) f_{(n-1)}(s) ds \right\} > 0. \end{aligned}$$

Therefore, it is optimal for a supplier with \(\theta \) to bid \(p = p^2(a, \theta , \omega )\) regardless of whether he wins or loses in the first stage. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 2

(i) First, Lemma 1 implies that \(p^2(\cdot )\) constitutes a symmetric equilibrium in the second-stage auction. Second, a winner in the first-stage auction chooses an investment level to maximize the certainty equivalent (6). Since the certainty equivalent decreases in \(a\), the winner optimally chooses \(a = 0\). Third, in the first-stage auction, every supplier submits a bid which makes him indifferent between winning and losing, in any symmetric equilibrium. Even if a supplier loses the first-stage auction, he can obtain the positive expected utility in the second-stage auction. The certainty equivalent is given by \(E[ (1-F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i)) (b(\theta _i) - \theta _i) ] - \rho ^{**}\). Hence, all suppliers submit the same bid \(\psi (0)\) in the first-stage auction.

(ii) Since a supplier with \(\theta _{(n)}\) wins the second-stage auction in equilibrium, the buyer’s expected utility is \(EU_B^{**} = v - \psi (0) -E[p^2(0, \theta _{(n)}, \omega )]\). The expected payment in the second-stage auction \(E[p^2(0, \theta _{(n)}, \omega )]\) can be rewritten as

$$\begin{aligned} E [ b(\theta _{(n)}) ] + E[\omega ]&= \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\bar{\theta }} b(s) f_{(n)}(s) ds + E [\theta _{(n)}] - \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\bar{\theta }} s f_{(n)}(s) ds \\&= E [\theta _{(n)}] + \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\bar{\theta }} [b(s) - s] \cdot n (1-F_{(n-1)}(s)) f(s) ds \\&= E [\theta _{(n)}] + n E [(1-F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i)) (b(\theta _i) - \theta _i)]. \end{aligned}$$

The second equality follows from the definition of \(f_{(n)}(\cdot )\). Thus, \(EU_B^{**} = v - \bigl \{ \psi (0) + E[\theta _{(n)}] + n E[(1-F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i)) (b(\theta _i) - \theta _i)] \bigr \}\). Since every supplier wins the first-stage auction with equal probability, his equilibrium expected utility is given by \(EU_i^{**} = u(E[ (1-F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i)) (b(\theta _i) - \theta _i) ] - \rho ^{**})\). Finally, the social welfare is given by \( W^{**} = EU_B^{**} + n \cdot u^{-1}(EU_i^{**}) = v - \left\{ \psi (0) + E[\theta _{(n)}] + n \rho ^{**} \right\} \). \(\square \)

Proof of Theorem 1

(i) It follows from the first-order condition (10) that \(\tilde{a}\) does not depend on \(\lambda \). Since \(G(\cdot ; \lambda )\) second-order stochastically dominates \(G(\cdot ; \lambda ')\) if \(\lambda ' > \lambda \), the risk premium \(\rho ^*\) under bundling increases in \(\lambda \). Thus, both \(EU_B^*\) and \(W^*\) decrease in \(\lambda \). On the other hand, under unbundling, the second-stage winner’s profit \(b(\theta _i) - \theta _i\) does not depend on \(\lambda \); therefore, the risk premium \(\rho ^{**}\) is invariant to \(\lambda \). Thus, both \(EU_B^{**}\) and \(W^{**}\) are invariant to \(\lambda \). Proposition 2 (ii) also implies that \(EU_B^{**} < W^{**}\).

Then, we have thresholds \(\underline{\lambda }\) and \(\bar{\lambda }\) with the properties in part (i) of the theorem. If \(EU_B^* > EU_B^{**}\) (resp., \(W^* > W^{**}\)) for each \(\lambda \in (0,1)\), then we set \(\bar{\lambda } = 1\) (resp., \(\underline{\lambda } = 1\)). If \(EU_B^* < EU_B^{**}\) (resp., \(W^* < W^{**}\)) for each \(\lambda \in (0,1)\), then we set \(\bar{\lambda } = 0\) (resp., \(\underline{\lambda } = 0\)).

(ii) First, we claim that \(\underline{\lambda }\) is greater than zero in the limit as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\). We show that as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\) and \(\lambda \rightarrow 0\), the difference between \(W^* (= EU_B^*)\) and the first-best utility \(v - \{ \psi (\tilde{a}) + E[\theta _{(n)}] - \delta \tilde{a} \}\) converges to zero. According to the definition of the convergence in law, for any \(\theta > 0,F(\theta ; \kappa ) \rightarrow 1\) as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\). Also, for any \(\kappa ,\lim _{m \rightarrow \infty } \int \limits _m^{\infty } \exp (r \theta ) d F(\theta ; \kappa ) = 0\). This implies that, for any \(\varepsilon > 0\), there exist positive numbers \(\delta , m\) with \(0 < \delta < m\) and \(\bar{\kappa } > 0\) such that for any \(\kappa < \bar{\kappa }\), the following inequalities remain true:Footnote 12

$$\begin{aligned} \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\bar{\theta }} \exp (r \theta ) d F(\theta ; \kappa )&= \int \limits _{-\infty }^\delta \exp (r \theta ) d F(\theta ; \kappa ) + \int \limits _\delta ^m \exp (r \theta ) d F(\theta ; \kappa ) \\&\quad {+}\!\! \int \limits _m^{\infty } \exp (r \theta ) d F(\theta ; \kappa ){<} \exp (r \delta ) {+} \exp (r m) \left[ F(m; \kappa ){-} F(\delta ; \kappa )\!\right] \\&\quad + \int \limits _m^{\infty } \exp (r \theta ) f(\theta ; \kappa ) d\theta < \left( 1 + \frac{\varepsilon }{3} \right) + \frac{\varepsilon }{3} + \frac{\varepsilon }{3} = 1 + \varepsilon . \end{aligned}$$

Since \(E [\exp (r \theta _i)] > \exp (r E[\theta _i]) = 1\) always remains true, \(\ln E[\exp (r \theta _i)] \rightarrow 0\) as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\). Similarly, \(\ln E[\exp (r \omega )] \rightarrow 0\) as \(\lambda \rightarrow 0\). Hence, the risk premium \(\rho ^*\) converges to zero as \(\kappa , \lambda \rightarrow 0\). Also, according to the definition of the convergence in law, for any \(\theta < 0,F(\theta ; \kappa ) \rightarrow 0\) as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\). Hence, a similar argument shows that \(E[\theta _{(n)}] \rightarrow 0\) as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\). On the other hand, the difference between \(W^{**}\) and the first-best utility is strictly smaller than zero even in the limit as \(\kappa , \lambda \rightarrow 0\). This is because \(0 < \tilde{a}\). Therefore, \(\underline{\lambda } > 0\) in the limit as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\).

Next, we claim that \(\bar{\lambda }\) is smaller than one in the limit as \(n \rightarrow \infty \) and \(\delta \rightarrow 0\). Using integration by parts, we transform the bidding function \(b(\cdot )\) in Lemma 1 into

$$\begin{aligned} b(\theta _i)&=\! - \frac{1}{r} \ln \left\{ - \left[ \exp (- r s) \frac{1 - F_{(n-1)} (s)}{1 - F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i)} \right] _{\theta _i}^{\bar{\theta }} {-} r \int \limits _{\theta _i}^{\bar{\theta }} \exp (- r s) \frac{1 - F_{(n-1)} (s)}{1 - F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i)} d s \right\} \nonumber \\&= - \frac{1}{r} \ln \left\{ \exp (- r \theta _i) - r \int \limits _{\theta _i}^{\bar{\theta }} \exp (- r s) \left( \frac{1 - F (s)}{1 - F(\theta _i)} \right) ^{n-1} d s \right\} . \end{aligned}$$
(11)

Lebesgue’s dominated convergence theorem implies that as the number \(n\) of suppliers goes to infinity, the term \(b(\theta _i)\) converges to \(\theta _i\) for each \(\theta _i\). Based on this fact, we can easily verify that \(E[n(1-F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i)) (b(\theta _i)-\theta _i)]\) converges to zero as \(n \rightarrow \infty \). Moreover, \(E[\theta _{(n)}]\) converges to \(\underline{\theta }\) as \(n \rightarrow \infty \). Thus, \(EU_B^{**}\) converges to \(v - \{ \psi (0) + \underline{\theta } \}\) as \(n \rightarrow \infty \). In contrast, \(EU_B^*\) is invariant to \(n\). It follows from the first-order condition (10) that \(\tilde{a} \rightarrow 0\) as \(\delta \rightarrow 0\). Therefore, \(\bar{\lambda } = 0\) for sufficiently large \(n\) and small \(\delta \). This establishes the claim. \(\square \)

Proof of Example 1

Assume that \(F(\theta _i; \kappa ) = 1 - \exp (-\theta _i/\kappa -1)\) for each \(\theta _i \ge - \kappa \). From the distribution, the bidding function \(b(\cdot )\) in the second-stage auction is given as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} b(\theta _i)&= -\frac{1}{r} \ln \int \limits _{\theta _i}^\infty \exp (-rs) \frac{n-1}{\kappa } \exp \left( {-}(n{-}1) \left( \frac{s}{\kappa }{+}1 \right) \right) \exp \left( (n{-}1) \left( \frac{\theta _i}{\kappa }{+}1 \right) \right) ds \\&= \theta _i + \frac{1}{r} \left( \ln (\kappa r + n-1) - \ln (n-1) \right) . \end{aligned}$$

Therefore, a simple calculation shows that

$$\begin{aligned} E[(1-F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i)) (b(\theta _i) - \theta _i)] = \frac{1}{nr} \left( \ln (\kappa r + n-1) - \ln (n-1) \right) , \end{aligned}$$

which increases in \(\kappa \). The equality follows from \(E[(1-F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i))] = 1/n\).

We next show that \(\rho ^* > n \rho ^{**}\). From the distribution of \(\theta _i,\rho ^*\) is given as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} \rho ^*&= \frac{1}{r} \ln \int \limits _{-\kappa }^\infty \exp (r s) \frac{1}{\kappa } \exp \left( -\frac{s}{\kappa } - 1 \right) ds + \frac{1}{r} \ln E[\exp (r \omega )] \\&= - \frac{1}{r} \ln (1- \kappa r) - \kappa + \frac{1}{r} \ln E[\exp (r \omega )]. \end{aligned}$$

This is well-defined because \(\kappa r \in (0,1)\). We can compute \(n \rho ^{**}\) as follows:

$$\begin{aligned} n \rho ^{**}&= \frac{n}{r} \ln E \left[ (1-F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i)) \frac{n-1}{\kappa r + n-1} + F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i) \right] \\&\ \ \ + n E[(1-F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i))] \frac{1}{r}(\ln (\kappa r + n-1) - \ln (n-1) ) \\&= \frac{n-1}{r} \left[ \ln (n-1) - \ln (\kappa r + n-1) \right] + \frac{n}{r} \left[ \ln (\kappa r + n) - \ln (n) \right] . \end{aligned}$$

It is easy to show that \(\rho ^* \rightarrow \frac{1}{r} \ln E[\exp (r \omega )] > 0\) and \( n \rho ^{**} \rightarrow 0\) as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\). Also, a simple calculation shows that

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial \rho ^*}{\partial \kappa } = \frac{\kappa r}{1-\kappa r} > \frac{\kappa r}{(\kappa r + n)(\kappa r + n-1)} = \frac{\partial (n \rho ^{**})}{\partial \kappa } \end{aligned}$$

for each \(\kappa , r\) with \(\kappa r \in (0,1)\) and \(n \ge 2\). Therefore, it holds that \(\rho ^* > n \rho ^{**}\). \(\square \)

Proof of Remark 1

We claim that if the idiosyncratic risks \(\theta _i \)’s are exponentially distributed as in Example 1, then for sufficiently small \(\lambda ,\kappa \) and \(n\), the buyer’s expected utility \(EU_B^*\) in the bundling mechanism is greater than the following expected utility in the unbundling mechanism with the sophisticated contract; i.e.,

$$\begin{aligned}&\ v - \left\{ \psi (\tilde{a}) - \delta \tilde{a} + E[\theta _{(n)}] + n E[(1-F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i)) (b(\theta _i)-\theta _i)] \right\} \nonumber \\&\quad = v - \left\{ \psi (\tilde{a}) - \delta \tilde{a} - \left( \frac{n-1}{n} \right) \kappa + \frac{1}{r} \left( \ln (\kappa r + n-1) - \ln (n-1) \right) \right\} . \end{aligned}$$
(12)

The difference between the expected utility (12) and the first-best utility converges to zero as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\). For the expected utility (12), the derivative with respect to \(\kappa \) is given by

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{n-1}{n} - \frac{1}{\kappa r + n -1}. \end{aligned}$$
(13)

As shown in the proof of Theorem 1, the difference between the buyer’s expected utility \(EU_B^*\) in the bundling mechanism and the first-best utility converges to zero as \(\lambda \rightarrow 0\) and \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\). The derivative with respect to \(\kappa \) is

$$\begin{aligned} \frac{\partial EU_B^*}{\partial \kappa } = - \frac{\partial \rho ^*}{\partial \kappa } = - \frac{\kappa r}{1 - \kappa r}. \end{aligned}$$
(14)

The derivative (14) is greater than (13) when \(\kappa \) is close to zero and \(n=2\). Therefore, \(EU_B^*\) is greater than the expected utility (12) for sufficiently small \(\lambda ,\kappa \) and \(n = 2\). \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 3

First, using the envelope theorem, we can show that \(\frac{\partial EU_B^*}{\partial \delta } = \frac{\partial W^*}{\partial \delta } = \tilde{a}\). Next, the assumption of additively separable production cost implies that neither the second-stage winner’s profit \(b(\theta _i) - \theta _i\) nor the risk premium \(\rho ^{**}\) under unbundling depends on \(\delta \). Hence, \(\frac{\partial EU_B^{**}}{\partial \delta } = \frac{\partial W^{**}}{\partial \delta } = 0\). Since \(\tilde{a} > 0,\frac{\partial EU_B^*}{\partial \delta } = \frac{\partial W^*}{\partial \delta } = \tilde{a} > 0 = \frac{\partial EU_B^{**}}{\partial \delta } = \frac{\partial W^{**}}{\partial \delta }\). Proposition 2 (ii) also implies that \(EU_B^{**} < W^{**}\).

Then, we have thresholds \(\underline{\delta }\) and \(\bar{\delta }\) with the properties in the proposition. If \(EU_B^* > EU_B^{**}\) (resp., \(W^* > W^{**}\)) for any \(\delta > 0\), then we set \(\underline{\delta } = 0\) (resp., \(\bar{\delta } = 0\)). Also, \(\underline{\delta }, \bar{\delta } < \infty \) because \(W_B^* > W_B^{**}\) and \(EU_B^* > EU_B^{**}\) for some sufficiently large \(\delta \). This completes the proof. \(\square \)

Proof of Lemma 3

(i) First, Lemma 2 implies that \(p(\cdot )\) is an equilibrium bidding strategy in the subcontracting auction. Second, a first-stage winner chooses an investment level to maximize the certainty equivalent (9). Differentiating the certainty equivalent yields the first-order condition (10). Hence, the winner chooses the efficient investment level. Third, in the first-stage auction, every supplier submits a bid which makes him indifferent between winning and losing, in any symmetric equilibrium. Even if supplier \(i\) loses the first-stage auction, he can obtain the positive expected utility in the subcontracting auction. The certainty equivalent is given by

$$\begin{aligned}&\ E \left[ F(\theta _j) E_{\theta _i} [(1-F_{(n-2)}(\theta _i)) (b(\theta _i, \theta _j) - \theta _i) \mid \theta _i < \theta _j] \right] - \rho _l. \end{aligned}$$

Hence, all suppliers submit the following bid:

$$\begin{aligned}&\ \psi (\tilde{a}) + E \left[ (1-F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i))\theta _i + \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\theta _i} b(s,\theta _i) f_{(n-1)}(s)ds + \omega - \delta \tilde{a} \right] + \rho _w \\&\qquad +E \left[ \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\theta _i} (1-F_{(n-2)}(s)) (b(s, \theta _i)-s) f(s) ds \right] - \rho _l \\&\quad = \psi (\tilde{a}) -\delta \tilde{a} + E \left[ \frac{n}{n-1} \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\theta _i} b(s, \theta _i) f_{(n-1)}(s) ds \right] + \rho _w - \rho _l. \end{aligned}$$

The equality follows from the interchange of the integrals.

(ii) It is obvious that \(EU_B^s\) and \(EU_i^s\) are given as in the proposition. The social welfare \(W^s = EU_B^s + n \cdot u^{-1}(EU_i^s)\) can be rewritten as

$$\begin{aligned}&\ v - \left\{ \psi (\tilde{a}) -\delta \tilde{a} + E \left[ \frac{n}{n-1} \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\theta _i} b(s, \theta _i) f_{(n-1)}(s) ds \right] + \rho _w - \rho _l \right\} \\&\qquad + n E \left[ \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\theta _i} (1-F_{(n-2)}(s)) (b(s, \theta _i)-s) f(s) ds \right] - n \rho _l \\&\quad = v - \left\{ \psi (\tilde{a}) -\delta \tilde{a} + E[\theta _{(n)}] + \rho _w + (n-1) \rho _l \right\} . \end{aligned}$$

\(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 4

As a preliminary, we prove that \(EU_i^s = EU_i^{**}\); thus, \(W^s - EU_B^s = W^{**} - EU_B^{**}\). From Proposition 2 (ii) and Eq. (11), the supplier’s expected utility \(EU_i^{**}\) in the unbundling mechanism can be rewritten as

$$\begin{aligned}&\ 1 - E[ (1-F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i)) \exp (-r (b(\theta _i) - \theta _i)) + F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i)] \nonumber \\&\quad = 1 - \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\bar{\theta }} \left\{ (1-F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i)) \left[ 1 - r \int \limits _{\theta _i}^{\bar{\theta }} \frac{\exp (-rs)}{\exp (-r \theta _i)} \left( \frac{1-F(s)}{1-F(\theta _i)} \right) ^{n-1} ds \right] \right. \nonumber \\&\qquad \left. + F_{(n-1)}(\theta _i) \right\} f(\theta _i) d \theta _i = r \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\bar{\theta }} \int \limits _{\theta _i}^{\bar{\theta }} \frac{\exp (-rs)}{\exp (-r \theta _i)} \left( 1-F(s) \right) ^{n-1} f(\theta _i) ds d \theta _i.\quad \end{aligned}$$
(15)

Using integration by parts, we transform the bidding function \(b(\cdot , \cdot )\) in Lemma 2 into

$$\begin{aligned} b(\theta _i, \theta )&= - \frac{1}{r} \ln \left\{ \int \limits _{\theta _i}^{\theta } \exp (- r s) \frac{f_{(n-2)} (s)}{1 - F_{(n-2)}(\theta _i)} d s {+} \int \limits _{\theta }^{\bar{\theta }} \exp (- r \theta ) \frac{f_{(n-2)} (s)}{1 - F_{(n-2)}(\theta _i)} d s \right\} \nonumber \\&= - \frac{1}{r} \ln \left\{ \int \limits _{\theta _i}^{\theta } \exp (- r s) \frac{f_{(n-2)} (s)}{1 - F_{(n-2)}(\theta _i)} d s + \exp (- r \theta ) \left( \frac{1 - F (\theta )}{1 - F(\theta _i)} \right) ^{n-2} \right\} \nonumber \\&= - \frac{1}{r} \ln \left\{ \exp (- r \theta _i) - r \int \limits _{\theta _i}^{\theta } \exp (- r s) \left( \frac{1 - F (s)}{1 - F(\theta _i)} \right) ^{n-2} d s \right\} . \end{aligned}$$
(16)

From Lemma 3 (ii) and Eq. (16), the supplier’s expected utility \(EU_i^s\) in the bundling mechanism with subcontracting can be rewritten as

$$\begin{aligned}&\ 1 - E \bigl [ F(\theta _j) E_{\theta _i} [(1-F_{(n-2)}(\theta _i)) \exp ( -r (b(\theta _i, \theta _j)-\theta _i)) + F_{(n-2)}(\theta _i) \mid \theta _i \nonumber \\&\quad < \theta _j] + (1-F(\theta _j)) \bigr ] = \frac{1}{2} - \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\bar{\theta }} \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\theta _j} \left\{ (1-F_{(n-2)}(\theta _i)) \right. \nonumber \\&\qquad \left. \times \left[ 1 {-} r \int \limits _{\theta _i}^{\theta _j} \frac{\exp (-rs)}{\exp (-r \theta _i)} \left( \frac{1-F(s)}{1-F(\theta _i)} \right) ^{n-2} ds \right] {+} F_{(n-2)}(\theta _i) \right\} \ f(\theta _i) d \theta _i f(\theta _j) d \theta _j \nonumber \\&\quad = r \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\bar{\theta }} \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\theta _j} \int \limits _{\theta _i}^{\theta _j} \frac{\exp (-rs)}{\exp (-r \theta _i)} \left( 1-F(s) \right) ^{n-2} f(\theta _i) f(\theta _j) ds d \theta _i d \theta _j\nonumber \\&\quad = r \int \limits _{\underline{\theta }}^{\bar{\theta }} \int \limits _{\theta _i}^{\bar{\theta }} \frac{\exp (-rs)}{\exp (-r \theta _i)} \left( 1-F(s) \right) ^{n-1} f(\theta _i) ds d \theta _i. \end{aligned}$$
(17)

The first two equalities follows from \(E[1-F(\theta _j)] = 1/2\), and the third equality follows from Fubini’s theorem. Hence, it follows from (15) and (17) that \(EU_i^{**} = EU_i^s\).

(i) It follows from the first-order condition (10) and the definition of the first-stage loser’s risk premium \(\rho _l\) that neither \(\tilde{a}\) nor \(\rho _l\) depends on the parameter \(\lambda \) of the aggregate risk \(\omega \). According to the definition of the second-order stochastic dominance, the first-stage winner’s risk premium \(\rho _w\) increases in \(\lambda \). Hence, both \(EU_B^s\) and \(W^s\) decrease in \(\lambda \). Now, the above preliminary result implies that \(EU_B^s > EU_B^{**}\) iff \(W^s > W^{**}\). Therefore, we have a threshold \(\hat{\lambda }\) such that \(EU_B^s > EU_B^{**}\) iff \(\lambda < \hat{\lambda }\), and \(W^s > W^{**}\) iff \(\lambda < \hat{\lambda }\).

Now, we claim that \(\hat{\lambda } > 0\) in the limit as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\). From Eq. (16), it is easy to see that \(b(\theta _i, \theta )\) increases in \(\theta _i\) and \(b(\theta , \theta ) = \theta \) for each \(\theta \). Using this fact, a similar argument to that for the proof of Theorem 1 shows that as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\) and \(\lambda \rightarrow 0\), the difference between \(W^s\) and the first-best utility converges to zero. The difference between \(W^{**}\) and the first-best utility is strictly smaller than zero, even in the limit, because \(0 < \tilde{a}\). Hence, it holds that \(\hat{\lambda } > 0\) in the limit as \(\kappa \rightarrow 0\).

Next, we claim that \(\hat{\lambda } < 1\) in the limit as \(\delta \rightarrow 0\) and \(n \rightarrow \infty \). From Eq. (16), Lebesgue’s dominated convergence theorem implies that as the number of suppliers, \(n\), goes to infinity, the term \(b(\theta _i, \theta )\) converges to \(\theta _i\) for any \(\theta _i\) and \(\theta \) with \(\theta _i \le \theta \). In the limit as \(n \rightarrow \infty \), subcontracting occurs with probability one, and the subcontracting cost is \(\underline{\theta } + \omega - \delta \tilde{a}\). Hence, as \(n \rightarrow \infty ,\rho _l \rightarrow 0\) and \(\rho _w \rightarrow \frac{1}{r} \ln E[\exp (r \omega )]\), so that \(EU_B^s\) converges to \(v - \{ \psi (\tilde{a}) - \delta \tilde{a} + \underline{\theta } + \frac{1}{r} \ln E[\exp (r \omega )]\}\). The proof of Theorem 1 shows that \(EU_B^{**}\) converges to \(v - \{ \psi (0) + \underline{\theta } \}\) as \(n \rightarrow \infty \). Also, it follows from the first-order condition (10) that \(\tilde{a} \rightarrow 0\) as \(\delta \rightarrow 0\). Since \(\frac{1}{r} \ln E[\exp (r \omega )] > 0\), it holds that \(\hat{\lambda } = 0\) for sufficiently large \(n\) and small \(\delta \). Thus, this establishes the claim.

(ii) The envelope theorem implies that \(\frac{\partial EU_B^s}{\partial \delta } = \frac{\partial W^s}{\partial \delta } = \tilde{a}\). It follows from the proof of Proposition 3 that \(\frac{\partial EU_B^{**}}{\partial \delta } = \frac{\partial W^{**}}{\partial \delta } = 0\). Therefore, we can obtain the threshold \(\hat{\delta }\) in the same way as part (i) of this proposition. \(\square \)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Nishimura, T. Sequential procurement auctions with risk-averse suppliers. J Econ 113, 229–252 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00712-013-0381-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00712-013-0381-1

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation