1 Introduction

In the recent decades, the international rule of lawFootnote 1 has become a topical yet conceptually challenging idea. The internationalisation of the rule of law has a wide spectrum of applications, from its promotion through a variety of international organisationsFootnote 2 to attempts to implement it as a legal ideology for international law as such,Footnote 3 for example, through its inclusion into Agenda-2030.Footnote 4 Often the meaning and function of the international rule of law is assumed, yet what ‘the international rule of law’ means and what practical differences it entails when we add ‘international’ to ‘the rule of law’, and how and why it should be protected remains unclear. Despite many attempts of conceptualising the international rule of law,Footnote 5 it still lacks shape and appears as a nebulous ideal.

This contribution offers a framework for conceptualising the international rule of law as a meaningful idea. It suggests that the international rule of law, its meaning and function, should not be deduced from the rule of law known domestically. Instead, the two versions of the rule of law should be deconstructed and stripped down of the variety of political, moral, and other layers in order to reveal their common core. The contribution will submit that this core meaning relates to the normative authority any legal order claims and to the conditions under which this claim becomes realisable.

The article will proceed in three steps. I first sketch out an image of the rule of law known domestically and show why it is not appropriate to transplant its theories and underlying histories directly into international law (Sect. 1). In Sect. 2, I show that theories of the rule of law must be deconstructed in order to reveal their core concern which, it will be submitted, relates to the normative authority. Finally, I present the international rule of law as a set of conditions under which international law’s claim to authority is realisable (Sect. 3).

2 The International Rule of Law Between Two ‘Pocket Universes’

Like many other normative ideals, the conceptual shape and meaning of the rule of law, as well as critical points of disagreement over its content, are products of domestic jurisprudential and political discourse. It is, therefore, well known that the idea and the concept of the rule of law strongly relate to how state government and other public authorities affiliated with it may or may not exercise their political powers. Hence a canonical three-headed picture of the rule of law offered by Albert Dicey: (1) predominance of regular laws as opposite to arbitrariness; (2) equality before the law; and (3) institutional protection of rights (Dicey 1959, p. 201–203).

The main concern surrounding the rule of law may be phrased in many different ways: securing individual autonomy, guaranteeing respect for human dignity, providing for accountability of governmental agencies, limiting arbitrariness in execution of power, etc. But overall these ideas can be reduced to the principle that there must exist certain limits for the use of law, or as framed by Joseph Raz, the rule of law defends against threats coming from the law itself (Raz 2009, p. 224). Law is one of the ways political power is exercised, and thus the rule of law is a virtue of a certain legal order. The main theoretical concern about the rule of law is how broad this virtue is in terms of the scope of its particular requirements. Though Dicey’s threefold approach is a common starting point for rule of law discussions, it does not exhaust the varieties of conceptions—broad and narrow—of this idea. Therefore, the critical point of theoretical disagreements about the rule of law is whether it accounts only for what is known as formal legality or also encompasses requirements regarding the content of rules.

On the one hand, it is often claimed that the rule of law is only a virtue of a legal system, and there are other virtues a legal system may or may not possess, or may possess to a lesser or higher degree. Hence, in this conception the rule of law only relates to the principles which represent the idea of formal legality, i.e. a set of requirements as to how laws should function. To say that a legal system conforms to the rule of law implies, from this perspective, that its laws are clear enough, known in advance, and relatively stable; that they do not prescribe the impossible and do not apply retrospectively; that their making is guided by clear, known, and stable rules; that all these rules are equally and consistently applied; that they are general and do not select particular individuals or make irrelevant distinctions between people; that courts are accessible and allowed to review governmental directives, etc.Footnote 6 This view embodies in ‘thin’ or formal conceptions of the rule of law.Footnote 7 The main claim of these theories is that the rule of law only relates to formal features of laws composing a given legal system and does not impose requirements regarding their content.Footnote 8 In such a way, ‘thin’ theories strictly separate the rule of law as a virtue of a legal system from other virtues, such as goodness or justness of its laws. The rule of law, in other words, does not by definition mean the rule of good law.

On the other hand, the rule of law is often taken as a much broader ideal. It is thus framed not merely a virtue of a legal system, but the moral and political ideal that embraces principles and values which form an image of a better society. From this perspective, it is not enough to secure a specific way or method in which law operates, and for this reason the rule of law must mean more than just formal legality. The rule of law, it is therefore submitted, must be furthered not only for the motives of legal certainty and predictability but also for the motives of higher values, such as human dignity, democracy, equality, justice, liberty, etc.Footnote 9 Ronald Dworkin famously claimed that

the rule of law on this conception is the ideal of rule by an accurate public conception of individual rights. It does not distinguish … between the rule of law and substantive justice; on the contrary it requires, as part of the ideal of law, that the rules … capture and enforce moral rights (Dworkin 1985, p. 11–12).

Taken in such a broad, or ‘thick’, meaning, the rule of law is no longer just a quality of a legal system. It becomes a complex and multidimensional ideology, ‘too important to be left to lawyers’ (Krygier 2012, p. 30).Footnote 10 In this all-inclusive manifestation the rule of law appears as an element of a theory of justice, and not just as a set of formal requirements for laws, and for this reason conceptions of the rule of law that share this perspective are often labelled as ‘thick’ or ‘substantive’.

The ‘thin’ and the ‘thick’ versions of the rule of law are sometimes seen as complementary standards,Footnote 11 and sometimes as contradictory or at least conceptually incompatible.Footnote 12 But what is more important is that regardless how the ‘thin’ and ‘thick’ visions of the rule of law correlate with each other, they are products of domestic legal experience and practice. The whole logic of describing the rule of law in between these two traditions results from contemplating the rule of law as a political and legal doctrine of protecting citizens against governmental abuses. The only principal difference is that the ‘thin’ theories do this through establishing safeguards as to how laws should be given a proper functionality, and the ‘thick’ theories through ensuring that laws substantively reflect the values and principles underlying individual rights. Is it possible to transplant this logic to international law, or should the international version of the rule of law be approached differently? The critical issue of the concept of the international rule of law is what it means for the rule of law to be (truly) international? Is it the same rule of law? Can we appropriately attach the same meaning to it as we do to the rule of law known domestically?Footnote 13

One of the leading approaches to the concept of the international rule of law suggests that one can grasp its meaning and function in the international community by applying the template designed on the basis of, and applied to, the rule of law known domestically. It is thus often assumed that applying the logic of the rule of law to international law entails matching it to one of the lists of criteria offered by Dicey, Fuller, Raz, or other scholars, and then either try to stretch them to account for peculiarities of international law (Beaulac 2007; Crawford 2003; Sampford 2014) or reject the international rule of law altogether as unsound (Hurd 2015b).Footnote 14 International law is in principle unable to satisfy some of these criteria, which either means the rule of law does not apply here, or that international law is simply deficient (Hurd 2015a). It is therefore claimed that international law is too underdeveloped and primitive, and for this reason ‘there is presently no such thing as the international rule of law, or at least that international law has yet to achieve a certain normative or institutional threshold to justify use of the term’ (Chesterman 2008, p. 358). Some authors even go further and observe that ‘talk of a rule of law for the international realm cannot target law in the usual sense of the term’ (Pavel 2019, p. 3).

In such a way, the most conceptual problems related to the international rule of law are connected to theorising its meaning, content, and functions through the use of the domestic analogy. This domestic analogy, however, does not seem to be justified, if only because the rule of law—domestic or international—must be taken as a product of certain legal histories.Footnote 15 As nicely put by Jutta Brunnée and Stephen Toope,

the problem with the domestic law analogy is not necessarily the analogy as such, but the assumptions that commonly shape it. When we assume that the defining features of domestic law—and by extension of all law—are formal enactment by a superior authority, application by courts, and centralized enforcement, we are bound to see international law as a poor cousin. Most importantly, we risk misjudging how law operates in international society, obscuring its potential power, and misdirecting even the best intentioned efforts to improve it (Brunnée and Toope 2010, p. 6).

And indeed, it is essential to appreciate that domestic and international versions of the rule of law were shaped as responses to quite different challenges. The relevance of the rule of law as a legal ideology for domestic setup was forged in civil wars, revolutions, bills of rights, and oppositions to the powers of kings, princes, and nobles—something that international law has never known. It seems that the only way of taking the international rule of law seriously is by rejecting the transplantation of legal histories and the political ideologies from the domestic to the international realm. Though histories of domestic law and histories of international law overlap, it does not mean that they are shared. The histories of international law comprise tales of preventing and reducing suffering in wars, guaranteeing the autonomy of states, securing their coexistence and cooperation, achieving solidarity and furthering common goals, but also of fighting for sovereign equality and liberation.Footnote 16 Hence though some motives in the historical narratives of domestic and international law may somehow echo one another,Footnote 17 their general structures and story-lines differ quite significantly. As Paul Burgees convincingly argues, even though evolutions of domestic and international rule of law seem to suggest similar solutions, this does not mean they grew from similar problems (Burgees 2019, p. 78–79).Footnote 18

Domestic and international law, in such a way, exist and develop like two ‘pocket universes’. This term relates to a hypothesis shared by some astrophysicists that our reality is not continuously uniform, and that it rather looks like a ‘patchwork quilt’ with each part having somewhat different fundamental parameters (Guth 2000). Thus one ‘pocket universe’ may differ from another in some basic prerequisites, which results in further diversification as they develop. They still belong to the same fabric of reality, and may even share many characteristics, but the way things appear in them features dissimilarities. This idea describes quite accurately the relations between domestic and international jurisprudence. They both belong to the same reality, but at the same time form two distinct ‘pocket universes’, which affects the meaning and functions of many shared concepts and ideas. This is primarily because domestic and international jurisprudence have dissimilar agendas dictated not only by well-known structural and functional differences between the two types of legal orders,Footnote 19 but also by divergent challenges faced by domestic and international law. The convergence of these challenges in recent decades, though, is a reason why the rule of law has been more actively articulated as applicable to international affairs.

The conceptual problem of the rule of law as a product of particular legal histories becomes visible when assessed against this idea of ‘pocket universes’. The two share many concepts and ideas, yet in most cases each jurisprudential universe has its own conventional way of using and applying them. This can be said, for instance, about concepts of ‘custom’, ‘bindingness’, ‘obligation’, ‘validity’, and many more. Though featuring in both universes, they are accompanied by somewhat dissimilar techniques of instrumentalisation; they, if we continue our astrophysics metaphor, ‘vibrate’ on different ‘frequencies’. The same can also be said about the rule of law. As stated by Arthur Watts,

for at least two reasons these national notions of the rule of law cannot be directly transposed to the international level. First, the purposes which the rule of law serves at the national level—usually involving the protection of the rights of the individual as against an otherwise all-powerful governing authority—are quite different from those which it might be called upon to serve internationally; and second, the more specific requirements of the rule of law often reflect a State’s particular historical and constitutional evolution, and differ from State to State. The international rule of law cannot be identified with any one national meaning of the concept… (Watts 1993, p. 16).

And indeed, the histories of the domestic rule of law relate to the ideas that individuals must have normative and institutional safeguards that defend them against governmental abuses, which in itself assumes a hierarchical relation between the ruled and the ruler. Whom does the international rule of law defend then, and against whose abuses? Certainly, it can be said that in the case of the international rule of law, just like with it domestic sibling, its ultimate beneficiaries are individuals; that states mediate between international law and people replicating in such a way the hierarchical scheme of government (Waldron 2011).Footnote 20 It is a solid perspective, which, however, only takes one of the possible dimensions of the international rule of law. Even though international law and international institutions have been increasingly addressing natural persons, which naturally creates the rule of law related concerns,Footnote 21 it seems too far-fetching to boil down all possible manifestations of the international rule of law only to this kind of relations. It may be too early to reject the paradigm that states are the primary subjects of international law and hence beneficiaries of the international rule of law, which makes the hierarchical perception of this doctrine far less relevant. Since there is no government states require protection from, there is seemingly little point in framing the international rule of law concerns in such a way.Footnote 22 Yet it does not mean that these concerns are no longer relevant. As convincingly argued by Martin Krygier, the main goal of the rule of law is to limit arbitrariness in execution of power (Krygier 2018, p. 149–152)—a concern which is as valid in international law as it is in domestic legal systems. States obviously may use their powers to abuse other states, without being formally superior to them. This makes the horizontal dimension of the international rule of law as relevant as canonical vertical ones. And yet there seems to be little understanding of how horizontal and vertical manifestations of the international rule of law can be reconciled within one conceptual paradigm.

Does this mean that the international rule of law is merely an empty political slogan, which has in fact no meaning? Or perhaps international law is way too special and therefore any attempt to conceive it through the prism of the rule of law will fall victim of unacceptable distortions? These questions are tough ones because they address the very problem of extended applicability of a certain normative ideal beyond its native domain. The next section will address these questions by reconstructing the core meaning of the rule of law common to its domestic and international manifestations.

3 Attempting Reverse Engineering: the Rule of Law and Normative Authority

The conceptual challenge posed by the international rule of law is of a complex nature. First of all, it impeaches the underlying assumptions most classical doctrines of the rule of law rely on (such as that the rule of law is addressed to officials and thus implies a formal hierarchy, or that it entails separation of governmental functions, or that it primarily safeguards individual autonomy). Further, the international iteration of the rule of law presupposes the universal validity of this concept, yet as was shown, the direct transplantation of its domestic vision to the international law does not seem a promising strategy. In such a way, to admit that the rule of law may apply internationally implies to abandon the traditional images of this idea and to try to discover its core, common for all its possible manifestations.

In order to contemplate the international rule of law we need to abstract from its domestic model and attempt its reconstruction or ‘reverse engineering’. What reverse engineering requires is a deconstruction of the conceptual layers of the rule of law that came as a consequence of domestic contestation of this ideal. Deconstructing the core meaning of the rule of law without linking it directly or indirectly to the domestic rule of law theories and practices chiefly implies abstracting from its moral and political justifications.Footnote 23 Being stripped down of these justifications, however, the rule of law has a seemingly trivial content. Joseph Raz offers, probably, the most straightforward formulation of the truism that underlies the rule of law when he submits that ‘“the rule of the law” means literally what it says: the rule of the law. Taken in its broadest sense this means that people should obey the law and be ruled by it’ (Raz 2009, p. 212). This implies that the rule of law, taken domestically or internationally, does not have any direct moral message, as is sometimes assumed.Footnote 24

This core formula of the rule of law may seem way too simplistic. For if the rule of law only means recognition of the normative force of the law and obedience to it, then even the formal legality requirements appear as a redundant set of principles. Yet importantly, saying that the law ought to be obeyed and people should be guided by it is also assuming many other things which are often taken exactly as the requirements of the rule of law. For the people to obey the law, it must be capable of being obeyed.Footnote 25 They must at least know what it is, how to identify it, and how to extract its normative meaning. No-one can obey norms he is not aware of, or norms that prescribe the impossible, or norms presented in a language its subjects cannot understand. This does not mean that such norms cannot exist or cannot be enforced upon their subjects.Footnote 26 However, a legal order consisting only of such norms would probably not last for long even if coercively imposed.Footnote 27 In other words, for a subject of law to obey norms, these norms must have qualities that create practical opportunities for obedience.

In this way, the rule of law is a merit of a legal order that enables its subjects to comply with it.Footnote 28 This merit, however, may be implemented in more than just one way. Depending on how a legal order operates, what normative claim it has, to whom it is addressed, and so on, its content and structure changes. The rule of law, from this point of view, should be perceived as coalescing two perspectives: one is the perspective of the subjects (bottom-up) and the other is the perspective of legal order as such (top-down). The function and the value of the rule of law, therefore, is that it serves a bridge between law’s claim of authority over its subjects, and actual materialisation of this claim in their conduct. Thus, if we accept that the rule of law relates to the ability of a legal order to generate an acceptable and realisable claim of authority, the theory of the rule of law becomes part and parcel of the theory of authority of law. This entails that our attempted deconstruction of the rule of law must also include ascertainment of what this claim actually is and how it may be realised.

International law, like any other legal order, claims to have an authority in a sense that it provides its subjects with reasons for actions they ought to comply with. Yet what does that claim of authority comprise? Why is it relevant to ensure that this claim is actually convertible into compliance?

Authority is a special kind of relation between the law and its addressees.Footnote 29 What is special about this relation is that authority affects the practical reasoning of its subjects. To say that A has an authority over B means to say that A may address to B directives which B ought to obey.Footnote 30 There are many examples of such relations: authority of parents over their children, authority of officers over soldiers, authority of superiors over inferiors in a company, and, of course, authority of government over people. In all these instances, those in a position of authority may provide those subjected to it with special reasons for actions.

Reasons,Footnote 31 in turn, are facts that count for performance of a certain action, or to put in more sophisticated words, ‘a reason for an action is a consideration that renders its choice intelligible, and counts in its favor’ (Raz 2006, p. 1006). Reasons may be simple (‘I am hungry, and this is a reason for me to eat’), or complex and intertwined with other considerations or conceptions (‘a low entrepreneurship activity is a reason for the government to lower the taxation burden’). Reasons reflect what ought to be done. They may have different weight; some reasons can outweigh others, and usually it is expected that an actor behaves accordingly to the optimal balance of reasons, i.e. according to what ought to be done all things considered.

An important feature of practical reasoning is that reasons exist on two levels, and thus there are first-order reasons and second-order reasons. Second-order reasons do not directly compete with first-order reasons, and if a conflict between a first- and a second-order reason happens, a first-order reason must be disregarded altogether and not weighed on its merits (Raz 1999, p. 39–45). An example for such a second-order reason is a promise. One ought to keep one’s promises, no matter what. In such a way, if I gave a promise to help my friend, I must help him even if this is not what I ought to do according to the optimal balance of reasons (I might have other urgent things or I do not feel like helping him anymore, etc.). Second-order reasons of this kind are exclusionary in a sense that even if I have other reasons that compete with my promise, they must be excluded from my considerations, i.e. I must not act on them.

NormsFootnote 32 are another example of second-order reasons. Subjects ought to do as norms prescribe even if they have first-order reasons for non-compliance. Such competing first-order reasons are excluded and must not be taken into account, no matter how weighty they are. Norms, in this way, are protected reasons in a sense that they are reasons for action they prescribe, and at the same time they may not be appropriately defeated by excluded first-order reasons. For example, to say that the prohibition of the threat or use of force against territorial integrity or political independence of any state is a normFootnote 33 is to say that states consider it both as a reason for action (a reason for not treating or using the force against another state) and a reason for not acting for other competing reasons (for example, for reasons of gaining new territories or expanding political influence). First-order reasons that compete with the prohibition of the threat or use of force shall, therefore, be disregarded and must gain no weight in states’ considerations as to what ought to be done. This example also clarifies another feature of norms as exclusionary reasons; they never exclude all the competing reasons (i.e., norms are never absolute reasons).Footnote 34 Thus, states may use force for the reasons of self-defence and authorisation by the UN Security Council. The exclusionary function of norms is a matter of social practices, and as practices evolve so do the norms; for instance, the discussions regarding the legality of humanitarian intervention can be said to rotate around the issue of whether certain moral reasons (solidarity, considerations of humanity, etc.) are altogether excluded by the general prohibition of the use of force.Footnote 35

Unlike other types of authority, the authority of law is therefore normative, because it claims to provide its subjects with a special kind of protected reasons—norms.Footnote 36 Hence, we have come full circle. To say that the law ought to be obeyed is to say that the reasons it provides its subjects with are perceived by them as protected reasons. To put it in Raz’s words, ‘law is authoritative if its existence is a reason for conforming action and for excluding conflicting considerations’ (Raz 2009, p. 29). This reinforces our initial claim that explanation of the rule of law depends on the theory of authority being used. For if we accept that law’s existence makes a practical difference for those to whom it is addressed, there is a reasonable expectation that law’s claims are to be met and perceived in such a way. According to this scheme, the rule of law is what actually enables the perception of the reasons the law offers as protected reasons, i.e. as norms. The rule of law bridges the gap between law’s claim of normative authority and its acceptance as such by the subjects of law. What is peculiar, however, is that different types of legal orders claim and secure normative authority in dissimilar ways. This becomes especially visible when the normative authority of domestic law is compared to the normative authority of international law. These two kinds of the normative authority need a closer look.

The manner in which the claim of normative authority is addressed to the subjects affects the conditions under which this claim is accepted, i.e. the construction and the content of the rule of law. My hypothesis is that law’s claim of authority may have two main forms: mediated and unmediated, which differ in the way the claim of authority is addressed to the subjects.Footnote 37

The authority of law within the domestic context is often a euphemism for the authority of state since state government usually is the only legitimate power that has a universal claim of authority over all relations within society.Footnote 38 Therefore, a normal way of describing the authority of domestic law is by identifying it with the system of officials and corresponding system of public institutions (‘authorities’). This type of authority strongly relates to the idea of ‘authorship’ in a sense that in domestic legal systems law is typically identified through the institutions empowered of making and applying laws. Within a domestic legal system, accepting the law’s claim of the normative authority means accepting the authority of officials who make, interpret, apply, and enforce the law. In such a way, law’s authority in domestic legal orders is by and large performed through institutions and officials.Footnote 39 For this reason, I will refer to it as ‘mediated authority’.

In the international realm, however, law’s claim of authority is not typically backed by an institutional structure similar to the government in states—one of the most widespread arguments against the international rule of law.Footnote 40 International law does not always embody or represent a consolidated or even articulated political power (though it can). Certainly, many parts of international law do rely on the institutional structures, such as international organisations, but these do not exhaust the entirety of norms of international law. Customary international law, and also significant number of international treaties, claim the normative authority without being identified, in one way or another, with some public institutions which issue or enforce them. According to Mario Prost, 70–75% of all international treaties are bilateral treaties (Prost 2012, p. 36), which typically do not provide for any sort of institutional mediation. Even though the last couple of decades evidenced the boom of international organisations, the larger part of international law claims authority without mediation by officials or formal institutions.Footnote 41 For this reason, I will call the authority of international law ‘unmediated authority’.

Both types of authority—mediated and unmediated—represent normative authority. International law’s authority, just like the authority of domestic law, is based on its claims that it accumulates and provides its subjects with protected reasons for action—norms. The difference between the two types, though, is that the authority of domestic law is far more mediated by officials and public institutions, whereas the authority of international law is generally not.Footnote 42 Hence, international law’s normativity is typically directly created by, and addressed to its subjects,Footnote 43 while domestic law’s authority and normativity are mainly communicated through officials.Footnote 44 Terry Nardin also observes that to speak about the international rule of law means to accept that authority of international law may be accounted for with no reference to officials:

we must assume… that law can be effective without legislation, adjudication, and centralised enforcement—that laws can be created, their meanings in particular cases authoritatively determined, and observance secured in other ways (Nardin 2008, p. 398).

That the normative authority of international law is by and large unmediated and its claim is addressed directly to its subjects, implies that the conditions under which this claim is acceptable and realisable differs from those which are germane to the mediated structure of authority. Our attempt of reverse engineering, therefore, brought us to the image of the rule of law as a set of conditions under which reasons addressed by law to its subjects are taken as protected ones. These conditions are not universal and depend on the structure of authority the law claims to have. Now we must investigate how this influences the concept of the rule of law as applied to international law.

4 The International Rule of Law and Features of the Normative Authority

In the previous two sections, I attempted to address some concerns about the concept of the international rule of law. In doing so, I suggested that the domestic and the international versions of this idea should not be deduced from one another, but instead must be treated as rooting in the common core which is the law’s normative authority. From this, the rule of law—domestic, international, or any other—is a meta-normative ideal that reflects the merits of a legal order as functioning in a way which enables its subjects to effectively comply with it and use it as a guidance for actions.Footnote 45 This merit may be achieved and secured in a variety of ways, which also explains the existence of distinct yet functionally overlapping concepts and doctrines.Footnote 46 I shall now illustrate how and in what respect the international rule of law differs from its domestic images regarding the ways of achieving and securing its normative authority.

A critical outcome of excluding officials and public institutions from the equation of the international rule of law, which, as was shown in the previous section, is of primary importance, is that the strict separation between its ‘thin’ and ‘thick’ versions is no longer relevant; at least, this is so according to the image of the rule of law known domestically. The logic of the ‘thin’ and the ‘thick’ rule of law, as Pauline Westerman accurately observes, implies that in order to get thick, one must first be thin (Westerman 2018, p. 141). The rule of law cannot, therefore, be built from its thicker end.Footnote 47 Because domestic law is issued, interpreted, applied, enforced, etc. dominantly through a system of officials, it is of paramount importance from the rule of law perspective that their practices are known, consistent through time, and conducted within reasonable frames of discretion, etc., otherwise its addressees may be unable to comply with it and guide their behaviour by it. These requirements also enable a justification of institutional authority of the state according to one or another moral standard. Yet the rule of law does not require democracy or a liberal political setup, and hence such practices, even when conforming to these requirements, do not necessarily serve a morally justified goal.Footnote 48 For this reason, the rule of law does not guarantee liberty, diversity, democracy, or equality. Its ideal is to enable law’s claim for normative authority to be fulfilled.

Therefore, the thickening of the rule of law as a political doctrine only becomes possible when legal accountability of officials is socially secured, and when their directives meet the requirements of formal legality. Such social conditions usually enable (more or less) effective mechanisms of communicating the values and goals to the officials and transforming them first into policies and later into legal norms. This is one of the reasons why, for instance, populism as a political platform is a threat to the rule of law,Footnote 49 as it values the achievement of certain goals far more than the way in which to achieve such goals. ‘Doing the right thing’ gets much more weight than ‘doing things right’, which may cause non-conformity with the basic formal requirements of the rule of law. In other words, the domestic logic of thickening of the rule of law entails that furthering morally justifiable goals and values does not in itself signifies the conformity to the rule of law, since such goals and values may as well be furthered through a deeply wicked institutional structure. At the same time, non-furthering of such goals and values does not mean non-conformity to the rule of law.

In international law, the situation differs, although the starting point remains the same. As stressed by Mattias Kumm, the international rule of law primarily entails

that nations, in their relationships to one another, are to be ruled by law. The addressees of international law, states in particular, should obey the law. They should treat it as authoritative and let it guide and constrain their actions (Kumm 2003, p. 22).Footnote 50

Here again, the central message of the international rule of law is articulated through international law’s claim for authority. Kumm’s statement, however, lacks an important detail significant for reconstructing the international rule of law through authority, namely, that not only states should treat international law as authoritative or let it guide their actions, but also that international law as such must meet conditions for such a treatment. Authority is always a two-way relation between a legal order and its subjects. What changes during our shift from mediated authority of domestic law to unmediated authority of international law, however, is the perception of typical devices used to justify norms as protected reasons.

As suggested above, the authority of international law does not generally feature mediators in the form of officials. This primarily entails that norms of international law are not commonly justified by reference to institutions though this is also possible in some regimes. This also results in ways legal obligations get generated and what conditions their acceptance. When authority is mediated, the justification of obligation pertains to the delegation of judgment, when public institutions are supposed to weigh all the relevant reasons for action and balance them in legally valid norms (Raz 1999, p. 74). Importantly, such a delegation assumes that the end result of institutions’ practical deliberations must be accepted as a content-independent reason for action, that is, ‘the fact that an authority requires performance of an action is a reason for its performance which is not to be added to all other relevant reasons when assessing what to do, but should exclude and take the place of some of them’ (Raz 1986, p. 46). Mediated structure of legal authority necessarily implies content-independence of its directives,Footnote 51 i.e. the addressees of this directives must accept them without judging them on the merits. This is why traditional domestic doctrines of the rule of law make such an emphasis on formal legality, for it allows to secure that authorities, in their practical deliberations, account for at least some relevant reasons (not necessarily substantive ones).Footnote 52

Norms of international law, especially norms of customary international law, are more often justified as devices enabling and securing coordination, as well as time- and labour-saving or error-eliminating devices.Footnote 53 An important feature of these justificatory devices is that they usually relate to norms deliberated by their subjects directly.Footnote 54 This in itself changes the scheme of normative authority. The authority of a norm of international law does not solely depend on its source or even on the many formal qualities which are of crucial importance for the domestic setup. Since states determine the content of the norms they abide by because they directly participate in their creation (either through conventional law-making or through customary practices), the authority of these norms equally depends on their formal and substantive merits, and often the lack or deficiency of the former is compensated by unanimity regarding the latter. If in domestic law, individuals cannot dis-obligate themselves from compliance with laws they dislike or disagree with (apart from the special cases like civil disobedience), nor can they cherry-pick laws to be bound by. In international law states can do this far more freely.Footnote 55 Besides, since states do not delegate practical deliberations, but instead perform them directly, it affects the ways in which reasons (both first- and second order) are assessed. Unmediated authority generates legal obligation that are not necessarily content-independent, or at least when they are, states are entitled to penetrate through the pre-emptive veil freely.Footnote 56

Because the authority of international law is of unmediated kind, the international rule of law does not require the logic of thickening and hence there is often a small gap between formal and substantive requirements of the international rule of law. The value-driven requirements of the international rule of law matter as much as requirements of formal legality.Footnote 57 Since international law-making and, to a large extent, international law-enforcement are not delegated to formal institutions, the formal and substantive merits of international law converge and intertwine when it claims the authority. From this perspective, what Ian Hurd considers as a vice of international law regarding the rule of law, namely that states are free to choose the legal obligations they see reasonable to be bound by, at least in terms of treaty law (Hurd 2014, p. 41–42), can in fact be its virtue. States are entitled to assess norms of international law both by their formal qualities and by their substance when forming a pull of legal obligations applied to them.

To recapitulate, that the authority of domestic law is mediated by officials makes its formal conditions more relevant, because subjects of law are committed to accept in advance specific types of official utterances as norms even if they are imperfect or even wrong on the balance of reasons. The authority of international law, however, is only in small part mediated by officials, which implies that, in principle, there is no general commitment to accept in advance any norm that meets certain formal criteria.Footnote 58 Even when such commitment is expressed through consent, however, this is seldom general and much more often ad hoc. As a consequence, the body of legal obligations under international treaties is unique for every state, and the content of customary international law is by and large approved through practice. What this difference between the structures of authority entails is that in international law there is a small gap between reasons that apply to states and norms that reinforce these reasons and bolster coordination by providing shortcuts in practical reasoning.Footnote 59 The normative system of international law, in such a way, is closer to the reasons that apply to states, and states are more flexible in articulating groups of interlocked reasons and the balance they have as norms.

Going back to the international rule of law, the described features of the normative authority affect the structure and the content of the rule of law applied internationally. Formal and substantive merits of laws, which in the domestic setup are stored in different baskets, so to speak, get mixed together as pieces of Lego, and different areas or regimes of international law rely more on one pieces, whereas other regimes rely more on other pieces.Footnote 60 The fundamental core of the rule of law—that the subjects of law must obey the law and be guided by it—is therefore enabled by both formal and substantive merits.Footnote 61 States as the central subjects of international law recognise its authority by subjecting themselves (and to a significant degree each other) to the body of rules of conduct that represent a certain balance of reasons that apply to them. These rules generate authority and are complied with because they provide for a formally and procedurally reliable normative framework of conduct or dispute settlement, but they may as well generate it because they express values and principles shared by states, even when the formal qualities of such expressions are dubious.

5 Conclusions

In this article, I attempted a reconstruction of the concept of the rule of law in a way that allows one to account for its main manifestations—domestic and international. I submitted that the rule of law should be considered as part and parcel of a conception of normative authority, and that what is traditionally approached as requirements or principles of the rule of law are in fact conditions under which a claim for authority of a certain normative order is realisable. What does this entail, and how does it change our perception of the international rule of law?

My central conclusion is that an image of the rule of law, its content and function depend on how a certain legal order generates the obligation to obey its norms and use them as guidance for action. The rule of law is therefore a collage of qualities of norms that enable or contribute to their status as authoritative. In the case of the international rule of law, this collage combines both formal and substantive merits of norms, securing in such a way status of states as both agents and addressees of international law. The international rule of law should be considered independently from the domestic rule of law, since the latter depends on dissimilar tools and techniques of justification of norms, and hence the structure of domestic law’s authority differs quite significantly from the one of international law. Still, both versions of the rule of law enable furthering of certain values and principles, since they both protect subjects of law from the threats of the law itself. If conditions under which a legal order’s claim for authority is realisable (and these conditions differ depending on the type of legal order), this allows for securing liberty and autonomy of its subjects and for conforming to principles legitimising this legal order.

That authority of law can be justified, secured, and made realisable by different means and under different conditions allows to break the vicious circle of domestic analogy, when the international rule of law inherits conceptual features of the rule of law known domestically, which leads to distortions or limitations. Both domestic and international rule of law represent the idea that legal orders, by claiming practical authority, must meet conditions under which this claim is justified and realisable. Since authority of law may be more or less mediated by formal institutions, this also affect what these conditions are and how they can be met.