Skip to main content
Log in

Seeking Speaker Meaning in the Archaeological Record

  • Thematic Issue Article: Symbols, Signals and the Archaeological Record II
  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Communication in archaeological artifacts is usually understood in terms of signs or signals, fleshed out under many guises. The notions of signs or signals that archaeologists employ often draw from Saussurean or Peircean semiotic theories from philosophy and linguistics. In this article I consider the consequences of whether we understand archaeological signals in terms of the Saussurean or Peircean framework, and highlight the fact that archaeologists have not always been precise in their use of relevant philosophical machinery. I will argue further that interpretation of archaeological artifacts should be supplemented by a notion of meaning that goes beyond signals and leads us to understand meaning in terms of a specific creator’s communicative intention—which may deviate from how some signal was ordinarily used. This is what I call speaker meaning, drawing from philosophy of language. I then present specific examples from Egypt circa 1300 BC and 3500 BC and from France circa 12,000 BC that I argue are best treated with the proposed notion of speaker meaning. In the course of this discussion I consider questions that arise for current accounts of signals and metaphor in archaeology. Finally, I conclude by considering how my proposal relates to our understanding of decoration and style, humor, the advent of spoken language, and the nature of art.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. At the same time, there are, of course, creations that are the result of the intentions of a number of individuals working together. Peter Hiscock (2004) discusses a case of stone knapping that involves one man knapping the stone and another man making the choice of which of the resulting flakes are suitable as knives, with much communication between the two along the way. Group intentions have received a great deal of attention in philosophy (Gilbert 1990; Searle 1990), especially in discussions of legislation in philosophy of law (Marmor 2011), where the output of some act of creation is almost always a result of a number of agents working together. Although the creators will not share all goals, in such endeavors they work along the areas of agreement, and we can look for a coherent group intention from those areas of overlap.

  2. Such use of the theory of semiology in often called “structuralism” in archaeology, which Margaret Conkey describes as “a body of ideas about how human culture and the human mind work” with “explicit origins in linguistics and the study of language” according to which theorists assume imagery encountered “was generated from a set of underlying cultural premises that are structured like language” (Conkey 2001, p. 274).

  3. I am speaking very generally; there are many pragmatic theories and traditions but their nuances and differences are not relevant for this discussion.

  4. There is much active debate today about which features of Grice’s original theory ought to be maintained (Sperber and Wilson 1986, 2015; Schiffer 1989; Neale 1992; Neale forthcoming). However, for our purposes here I will make use of just a few features of Grice’s original theory and will remain agnostic with respect to the details.

  5. Further, drawing on work defending a Gricean line (Donnellan 1968; Neale 1992, forthcoming), I will note that contra certain objectors (Searle 1969; Saul 2002) tying meaning to intentions does not lead to the conclusion that some speaker meaning can be tied to any word meaning. The formation of some particular meaning-intention is constrained: you cannot form an intention to mean p by uttering r if you know there is no chance your hearer will take you to thereby mean p.

  6. This point is even stronger when considering certain types of archaeological artifacts, such as hieroglyphs and Egyptian art, where the line between the linguistic and non-linguistic is even harder to draw (Wilkinson 1994).

  7. This is a looser notion than Grice’s spelling out of meaning intentions, which for Grice requires that the recognition of this intention provides at least part of the reason for the hearer to come to believe that p. A number of theorists working in the Gricean tradition advocate for this looser treatment of Grice even in the linguistic cases (Neale 1992; Sperber and Wilson 1986).

  8. Some of the earliest available sources of spells and literature show evidence of speaker meaning in the form of metaphor and hyperbole. In the Egyptian Book of the Dead there is a spell to protect the dead from being harmed by crocodiles in the afterlife that includes a crocodile saying, “My teeth are a knife, my tusks are Viper Mountain” (Taylor 2010, p. 184; see also Goldwasser 2005 for metaphor in hieroglyphs). The Iliad, perhaps the earliest source of what we might today call literature (Ross 2005) is rife with speaker meaning in the form of metaphor and hyperbole. In the first few pages of the Iliad, Agamemnon is described rising in anger: “His heart was black with rage and his eyes flashed fire as he scowled on Calchas” (Homer [1925]1999, p. 3). In some of our earliest written records we see uses of speaker meaning. Moving back from the time of the Book of the Dead and the Iliad, we can consider how far back we find this sort of speaker meaning.

  9. Of a similar painting from the time of King Amenhotep III, Gay Robins writes, “…the king’s footstool is decorated with images of prostrate foreigners, a visual rendering of the common royal phrase: ‘all foreign lands are under your sandals’” (Robins 1997, p. 137). This seems to support Carter’s interpretation.

  10. More details on implicature and the search for speaker meaning can be found in Grice (1989); Neale (1992, Forthcoming); and Johnson (2016).

  11. For example, Ian Hodder (1991) goes through such a case when he discusses having heard what he thought was the phrase “indoor pain.” It was, in fact, the American pronunciation of “endure pain.”

References

  • Adajian T (2016) “The definition of art”. In: Zalta E (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/art-definition/. Accessed 31 Jan 2017

  • Allen G (2003) Roland Barthes. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bach K (1997) The semantics-pragmatics distinction: what it is and why it matters. In: Rolf E (ed) Pragmatik: implicaturen und sprechakte. VS Verlag für Sozialwissenschaften, Wiesbaden, pp 33–50

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bahn P (2012) Cave art: a guide to the decorated ice age caves of Europe. Frances Lincoln, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Bandi HG (1988) Mise bas et non défécation. Nouvelle interprétation de trois propulseurs magdaléniens sur des bases zoologiques, éthologiques et symboliques. Espacio, Tiempo y Forma, Serie I, Prehistoria, t. I, pp 133–147

  • Baron-Cohen S (1995) Mindblindness. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Barthes R (2006) The language of fashion. Translated from French by Stafford A. Stafford A, Carter M (eds) Bloomsbury Academic, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauer A (2013) Objects the theory glassy essence: semiotics of self in the early bronze age black sea. Signs Soc 1(No.1):1–31

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bezuidenhout A (2001) Metaphor and what is said: a defense of a direct expression view of metaphor. Midwest Stud Philos 25:156–186

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bruck J (2004) Comment on round barrows and dykes as landscape metaphors. Camb Archaeol J 14(2):185–203

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll N (2014) Humour: a very short introduction. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carston R (2008) Linguistic communication and the semantics/pragmatics distinction. Synthese 165(3):321–345

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carter H ([1923]1977) Discovery of the tomb of Tutankhamen. Dover, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Chandler D (2007) Semiotics: the basics. 2nd edn. Routledge, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Conkey M (2001) Structural and semiotic approaches. In: Whitley D (ed) Handbook of rock art research. Altamira Press, London, pp 273–310

    Google Scholar 

  • Coward F, Gamble C (2010) Metaphor and materiality in earliest prehistory. In: Malafouris L, Renfrew C (eds) The cognitive life of things: recasting the boundaries of the mind. McDonald Institute for Archaeological Research, Cambridge, pp 47–58

    Google Scholar 

  • Crossland Z (2014) Ancestral encounters in highland Madagascar: material signs and traces of the dead. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Currie G (2003) The capacities that enable us to produce and consume art. In: Kieran M, Lopes D (eds) Imagination, philosophy, and the arts. Routledge, New York, pp 293–304

    Google Scholar 

  • Curtis G (2007) The cave painters: probing the mysteries of the world’s first artists. Anchor, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan K (1966) Reference and definite descriptions. Philos Rev 75:281–304

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donnellan K (1968) Putting Humpty Dumpty together again. Philos Rev 77(2):203–215

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DuBreuil B, Henshilwood CS (2013) Material culture and language. Stud Lang Companion Series. 144:147–170

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garrod D (1955) Palaeolithic Spear-throwers. Proc Prehist Soc 3:21–34

    Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert M (1990) Walking together: a paradigmatic social phenomena. Midwest Stud Philos 15:1–14

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldwasser O (2005) Where is metaphor?: conceptual metaphor and alternative classification in the hierglyphic script. Metaphor Symb 20(2):95–113

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice P (1989) Studies in the way of words. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayes WC (2013) The scepter of Egypt: a background for the study of the Egyptian antiquities in the metropolitan museum of art from the earliest times to the end of the middle kingdom. Metropolitan Museum of Art, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Hiscock P (2004) Slippery and Billy: intention, selection, and equifinality in lithic artefacts. Camb Archaeol J 14:71–77

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hiscock P (2014) Learning in lithic landscapes: a reconsideration of the hominid "toolmaking" niche. Biol Theory 9:27–41

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hodder I (1991) Interpretive archaeology and its role. Am Antiquity 56(1):7–18

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Homer ([1925]1999) The Iliad. Translated by Butler S Dover Publications, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson M (2016) Cooperation with multiple audiences. Croat J Philos 16(2):203–227

    Google Scholar 

  • Knecht H (1997) Projectile technology. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke S (1977) Speaker’s reference and semantic reference. Midwest Stud Philos 2:255–276

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff G (1987) The death of dead metaphor. Metaphor Symb Act 2(2):143–147

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leroi-Gourhan A (1968) The art of prehistoric man in Western Europe. Thames & Hudson, London

  • Lewis-Williams D (2002) The mind in the cave. Thames & Hudson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor A (2011) Can the law imply more than it says? On some pragmatic aspects of strategic speech. In: Marmor A, Soames S (eds) Philosophical foundations of language in the law. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 83–104

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Neale S (1992) Paul Grice and the philosophy of language. Linguist Philos 15:509–559

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neale S (Forthcoming) Linguistic pragmatism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

  • Pawelec A (2006) The death of metaphor. Stud Linguist 123:117–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettitt P et al (2014) New views on old hands: the context of stencils in El Castillo and La Garma caves (Cantabria, Spain). Antiquity 88:47–63

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Planer RJ (2017) Talking about tools: did early Pleistocene hominins have a protolanguage? Biol Theory. doi:10.1007/s13752-017-0279-1

    Google Scholar 

  • Power R, Tristant Y (2016) From refuse to rebirth: repositioning the pot burial in the Egyptian archaeological record. Antiquity 90(354):1474–1488

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Preucel RW (2010) Archaeological semiotics. Wiley-Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Renfrew C, Bahn P (2012) Archeology: theory, methods, and practice, 6th edn. Thames & Hudson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Robins G (1997) The art of ancient Egypt. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross S (2005) Barbarophonos: language and panhellenism in the Illiad. Class Philol 100(4):299–316

    Google Scholar 

  • Rossano M (2010) Making friends, making tools, and making symbols. Curr Anthropol 51(S1):S89–S98

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rudgley R (2000) The lost civilizations of the stone age. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sackett JR (1985) Style and ethnicity in the Kalahari: a reply to Wiessner. Am Antiquity 50:154–159

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Saul J (2002) What is said and psychological reality: Grice’s project and relevance theorist’s criticisms. Linguist Philos 25(3):347–372

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer S (1989) Remnants of meaning. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1969) Speech acts. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1990) Collective intentions and actions. In: Cohen, Morgan, Pollack (eds) Intentions in communication. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 401–415

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidelle A (1991) The answering machine paradox. Can J Philos 21:525–539

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber D, Wilson D (1986) Relevance: communication and cognition. Blackwell, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber D, Wilson D (2015) Beyond speaker’s meaning. Croat J Philos 15(44):117–149

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiner M (2014) Finding a common bandwidth: causes of convergence and diversity in paleolithic beads. Biol Theory 9:51–64

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taylor JH (2010) Ancient Egyptian book of the dead: journey through the afterlife. British Museum Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Tilley C (2000) Metaphor and material culture. Wiley-Blackwell, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Tilley C (2004) Round barrows and dykes as landscape metaphors. Camb Archaeol J 14(2):185–203

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (2010) Origins of human communication. Bradford, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Trigger B (2006) A history of archaeological thought, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wiessner P (1983) Style and social information in Kalahari San projectile points. Soc Am Archaeol 48(2):253–276

    Google Scholar 

  • Whittaker J (2010) Weapon trials: the atlatl and experiments in hunting technology. In: Ferguson J (ed) Designing experimental research in archaeology: examining technology through production and use. University Press of Colorado, Boulder, pp 195–224

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilkinson R (1994) Reading Egyptian art: a hieroglyphic guide to ancient Egyptian painting and sculpture. Thames & Hudson, London

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank all the participants of the 2015 “Symbols and Communicative Behaviour in Pleistocene Hominins (Symbols II)” workshop at the University of Sydney and especially Jesse Prinz, Noel Carroll, Ronald Planer, Graham Priest, Mary Stiner, and Katherine Eaton for their feedback on and support of the paper. I would like to thank Peter Godfrey-Smith for his continued support of the project and Peter Hiscock and Kim Sterelny for their organizing work and helpful comments on the article. Travel support was provided by the Tom Austen Brown Endowment at the University of Sydney; completion of the paper was supported by fellowships from the City University of New York Graduate Center Committee for Interdisciplinary Science Studies and the American Society for Aesthetics. I am very grateful to these organizations and the people behind them. Lastly, I should note that any views, findings, conclusions, or recommendations expressed in this publication do not necessarily reflect those of the American Society for Aesthetics.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marilynn Johnson.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Johnson, M. Seeking Speaker Meaning in the Archaeological Record. Biol Theory 12, 262–274 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-017-0285-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-017-0285-3

Keywords

Navigation