Skip to main content
Log in

Distinguishing Natural Selection from Other Evolutionary Processes in the Evolution of Altruism

  • Orginal Article
  • Published:
Biological Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Altruism is one of the most studied topics in theoretical evolutionary biology. The debate surrounding the evolution of altruism has generally focused on the conditions under which altruism can evolve and whether it is better explained by kin selection or multilevel selection. This debate has occupied the forefront of the stage and left behind a number of equally important questions. One of them, which is the subject of this article, is whether the word “selection” in “kin selection” and “multilevel selection” necessarily refers to “evolution by natural selection.” I show, using a simple individual-centered model, that once clear conditions for natural selection and altruism are specified, one can distinguish two kinds of evolution of altruism, only one of which corresponds to the evolution of altruism by natural selection, the other resulting from other evolutionary processes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For a recent discussion on the relation between multilevel selection and kin selection see Okasha (2015).

  2. I borrow the term “selective environment” from Brandon (1990). As recognized by Brandon (2014) this concept of natural selection faces several possible objections. One of them is that any case in which the individuals of a population significantly interact with each other (altruism is only one case in which this kind of interaction occurs) will prevent these individuals from being in the same environment. I will regard this problem as non-fatal to this formulation and leave its resolution for further work.

  3. Brandon, in his original definition, refers to the environment as only external factors to the organism. For reasons that cannot be developed here, to be consistent, it should be defined in reference to a phenotype, be it expressed within or beyond the physical boundaries of the organism. See Haig (2012) for a similar notion of the environment in relation to what he calls the “strategic gene.”

  4. I leave for further work to determine which evolutionary force(s) each kind of difference should be attributed to.

  5. This is inspired from Sober and Wilson (1998, pp. 19–21)

  6. This is also a point made in the literature on reciprocal altruism (Trivers 1971; Axelrod 1984).

  7. By “causal factors” I mean “difference makers” following Woodward’s (2003) interventionist account of causation.

  8. Note that β, in the general case, could be inferior to 1 (but superior or equal to 0), in which case altruistic individuals would “avoid” interacting with other altruistic individuals. I consider here only the case in which altruistic individuals “seek” other altruistic individuals, hence why I assume β ≥ 1.

References

  • Abrams M (2009) The unity of fitness. Philos Sci 76:750–761

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Axelrod R (1984) The evolution of cooperation. Basic Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bouchard F (2008) Causal processes, fitness, and the differential persistence of lineages. Philos Sci 75:560–570

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bouchard F, Rosenberg A (2004) Fitness, probability and the principles of natural selection. Br J Philos Sci 55:693–712

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourke AF (2011) Principles of social evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat P (2014) Reconceptualising evolution by natural selection. Dissertation, University of Sydney

  • Bourrat P (2015a) Levels of selection are artefacts of different fitness temporal measures. Ratio 28:40–50. doi:10.1111/rati.12053

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourrat P (2015b) Levels, time and fitness in evolutionary transitions in individuality. Philos Theory Biol. doi:10.3998/ptb.6959004.0007.001

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon RN (1990) Adaptation and environment. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon RN (2014) Natural selection. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/natural-selection/. Accessed Jan 2015

  • Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1979) Twelve misunderstandings of kin selection. Z für Tierpsychol 51:184–200

    Google Scholar 

  • Dugatkin LA, Reeve HK (1994) Behavioral ecology and levels of selection: dissolving the group selection controversy. Adv Study Behav 23:101–133

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher JA, Doebeli M (2009) A simple and general explanation for the evolution of altruism. Proc R Soc B 276:13–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner A, Foster KR (2008) The evolution and ecology of cooperation–history and concepts. In: Korb J, Heinze J (eds) Ecology of social evolution. Springer, Heidelberg, pp 1–36

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gardner A, West SA (2010) Greenbeards. Evolution 64:25–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (1984) Natural selection, kin selection and group selection. In: Krebs JR, Davies NB (eds) Behavioural ecology: an evolutionary approach. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 62–84

    Google Scholar 

  • Haig D (2012) The strategic gene. Biol Philos 27:461–479

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1963) The evolution of altruistic behavior. Am Nat 97:354–356

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1964a) The genetical evolution of social behaviour. I. J Theor Biol 7:1–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1964b) The genetical evolution of social behaviour. II. J Theor Biol 7:17–52

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamilton WD (1975) Innate social aptitudes of man: an approach from evolutionary genetics. In: Fox R (ed) Biosocial anthropology. Malaby Press, London, pp 133–153

    Google Scholar 

  • Keller L, Ross KG (1998) Selfish genes: a green beard in the red fire ant. Nature 394:573–575

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kerr B, Godfrey-Smith P (2002) Individualist and multi-level perspectives on selection in structured populations. Biol Philos 17:477–517

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kerr B, Godfrey-Smith P, Feldman MW (2004) What is altruism? Trends Ecol Evol 19:135–140

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mills SK, Beatty JH (1979) The propensity interpretation of fitness. Philos Sci 46:263–286

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nunney L (1985) Group selection, altruism, and structured-deme models. Am Nat 126:212–230

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2006) Evolution and the levels of selection. Oxford University Press, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Okasha S (2015) The relation between kin and multilevel selection: an approach using causal graphs. Br J Philos Sci. doi:10.1093/bjps/axu047

    Google Scholar 

  • Pocheville A (2010) What niche construction is (not). La niche écologique: concepts, modèles, applications. Ecole Normale Supérieure, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Queller DC (1985) Kinship, reciprocity and synergism in the evolution of social behaviour. Nature 318:366–367

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosas A (2010) Beyond inclusive fitness? On a simple and general explanation for the evolution of altruism. Philos Theory Biol. doi:10.3998/ptb.6959004.0002.0004

    Google Scholar 

  • Rousset F (2004) Genetic structure and selection in subdivided populations (MPB-40). Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E (1984) The nature of selection. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober E, Wilson DS (1998) Unto others: the evolution and psychology of unselfish behavior. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (1996) The return of the group. Philos Sci 63:562–584

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K, Griffiths PE (1999) Sex and death: an introduction to philosophy of biology. University of Chicago press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor PD, Frank SA (1996) How to make a kin selection model. J Theor Biol 180:27–37

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trivers RL (1971) The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Q Rev Biol 46:35–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Baalen M, Rand DA (1998) The unit of selection in viscous populations and the evolution of altruism. J Theor Biol 193:631–648

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wenseleers T, Gardner A, Foster KR (2010) Social evolution theory: a review of methods and approaches. In: Szekely T, Moore AJ, Komdeur J (eds) Social behaviour: genes, ecology and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 132–158

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • West SA, Griffin AS, Gardner A (2007) Social semantics: altruism, cooperation, mutualism, strong reciprocity and group selection. J Evol Biol 20:415–432

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West SA, Griffin AS, Gardner A (2008) Social semantics: how useful has group selection been? J Evol Biol 21:374–385

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson DS (1980) The natural selection of populations and communities. Benjamin/Cummings, Menlo Park

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson DS, Wilson EO (2007) Rethinking the theoretical foundation of sociobiology. Q Rev Biol 82:327–348

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward J (2003) Making things happen: a theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am thankful to Patrick Forber, Arnaud Pocheville, and two anonymous reviewers for their comments on earlier versions of this paper. I am particularly thankful to Arnaud Pocheville for his extensive help on the most technical parts of the paper and for his thorough proofreading. This research was supported under Australian Research Council’s Discovery Projects funding scheme (Projects DP0878650 and DP150102875).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pierrick Bourrat.

Appendix

Appendix

Let us start from (15):

$$\beta (bN_{A} (N_{T} - N_{A} ) - cN_{T} N_{A} ) > bN_{A} (N_{T} - N_{A} ) + cN_{T} \left( {N_{T} - N_{A} } \right)$$

To be meaningful, we assume β ≥ 0. Let us call the term in brackets on the left-hand side of (15) \(P = bN_{A} (N_{T} - N_{A} ) - cN_{T} N_{A}\). Let’s call Q the right hand side.

If P > 0 we have:

$$\beta > Q / P$$

We know that\(cN_{T} (N_{T} - N_{A} ) > 0 > - cN_{T} N_{A}\), thus Q > P which means that β > 1.

If P = 0 then 0 > Q, which is impossible.

If P < 0 then either 0 > Q, which is impossible, or β < 0, which is impossible.

Thus, if (15) holds, β > 1.

Then P > 0 implies N A  > 0 and \(b > c\frac{{N_{T} }}{{N_{T} - N_{A} }}\), in the case where \(N_{T} \ne N_{A}\). This is an interesting constraint bearing on b which is consistent with the hypotheses classically made in models on the evolution of altruism, namely that the benefit received by the focal altruistic individual is larger than the cost it pays.

Thus if (15) holds, β > 1 (which satisfies the intuition), N A  > 0 (which is expected), and \(b > c\frac{{N_{T} }}{{N_{T} - N_{A} }}\), if \(N_{T} \ne N_{A}\).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bourrat, P. Distinguishing Natural Selection from Other Evolutionary Processes in the Evolution of Altruism. Biol Theory 10, 311–321 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-015-0210-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13752-015-0210-6

Keywords

Navigation