Skip to main content
Log in

A second-generation disappointment aversion theory of decision making under risk

  • Published:
Theory and Decision Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper presents a new decision theory for modelling choice under risk. The new theory is a two-parameter generalization of expected utility theory. The proposed theory assumes that a decision maker: (1) behaves as if maximizing expected utility; but (2) may experience disappointment (elation) when the utility of a lottery’s outcome falls short of (exceeds) the expected utility of the lottery; and (3) may have a preference for gambling (attraction/aversion to positively/negatively skewed lotteries). The proposed theory can rationalize the fourfold pattern of risk attitudes; the common ratio effect and the reverse thereof (in certain types of decision problems); the Allais paradox in classical common consequence problems and the reverse Allais paradox—in common consequence problems with an even split of a probability mass; violations of the betweenness axiom; switching behavior in the Samuelson’s example; violations of ordinal, upper and lower cumulative independence (which falsify rank-dependent utility and cumulative prospect theory); and preference reversals between valuations and choice. In application to insurance, the theory can rationalize full insurance with an actuarially unfair premium and aversion to probabilistic insurance. In application to optimal portfolio investment, the theory can rationalize the equity premium puzzle.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In particular, the models proposed by Bell (1985), Loomes and Sugden (1986) and Jia et al. (2001) cf. Sect. 6 below.

  2. I.e. risk aversion for probable gains or improbable losses and risk seeking for improbable gains or probable losses.

  3. Quiggin (1981) rank-dependent utility or Tversky and Kahneman (1992) cumulative prospect theory with a popular probability weighting function \(w( p )=p^{\gamma }/({p^{\gamma }+({1-p})^{\gamma }})^{1/\gamma }\) shares the same limitation.

  4. A simultaneous combination of quasi-concave and quasi-convex preferences (Bernasconi 1994).

  5. In other words, cumulative probability \(1-0.01x\) is uniformly distributed over interval [x, 100].

  6. Markowitz (1952, p. 90) noted that the third moment “may be connected with a propensity to gamble”.

  7. This cubic probability weighting function \(w( p )=p-\rho \cdot p( {1-p} )+\tau \cdot p( {1-p} )( {1-2p} )\) is analyzed in Blavatskyy (2016).

  8. Many studies find that decision making under risk is a probabilistic rather than a deterministic process. For example, Camerer (1989, p. 81), Hey and Orme (1994, p. 1296) as well as Ballinger and Wilcox (1997, p. 1100) found that 31.6, 25 and 20.8% of subjects respectively reverse their choice when presented with the same decision problem within a short period of time.

  9. Restriction to four outcomes is a common approach in experimental economics to facilitate a non-parametric estimation of a Bernoulli utility function (e.g., Hey and Orme 1994; Hey 2001).

  10. The rule of thumb is the following: (1) choose a lottery with the lowest probability of the worst possible outcome; (2) if both lotteries yield the same probability of the worst possible outcome then choose the lottery with the highest probability of the best possible outcome.

  11. E.g. when comparing expected utility theory and the maximization of expected value.

  12. If two or more theories are not significantly different in terms of goodness of fit, then only a theory with fewer subjective parameters is shown on Fig. 5.

References

  • Allais, Maurice. (1953). Le Comportement de l’Homme Rationnel devant le Risque: Critique des Postulates et Axiomes de l’Ecole Américaine. Econometrica, 21, 503–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Astebro, T., Mata, J., & Santos-Pinto, L. (2015). Skewness seeking: Risk loving, optimism or overweighting of small probabilities? Theory and Decision, 78, 189–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ballinger, Parker, & Wilcox, Nathaniel. (1997). Decisions, error and heterogeneity. Economic Journal, 107, 1090–1105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, Gordon M., DeGroot, Morris H., & Marschak, Jacob. (1964). Measuring utility by a single-response sequential method. Behavioral Science, 9, 226–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, David. (1985). Disappointment in decision making under uncertainty. Operations Research, 33, 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernasconi, Michele. (1994). Nonlinear preference and two-stage lotteries: Theories and evidence. Economic Journal, 104, 54–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernoulli, D. (1738). Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis. Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae. [Translated in Bernoulli, D. (1954). Exposition of a new theory on the measurement of risk. Econometrica, 22, 23–36].

  • Birnbaum, Michael. (2004). Tests of rank-dependent utility and cumulative prospect theory in gambles represented by natural frequencies: Effects of format, event framing, and branch splitting. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 95, 40–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, Michael. (2005). Three new tests of independence that differentiate models of risky decision making. Management Science, 51(9), 1346–1358.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, Michael, & Gutierrez, R. (2007). Testing for intransitivity of preferences predicted by a lexicographic semi-order. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 104, 96–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, Michael, & Navarrete, Juan. (1998). Testing descriptive utility theories: Violations of stochastic dominance and cumulative independence. Journal of Risk Uncertainty, 17, 49–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, Michael, Patton, Jamie, & Lott, Melissa. (1999). Evidence against rank-dependent utility theories: Violations of cumulative independence, interval independence, stochastic, dominance, and transitivity. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 77, 44–83.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum, Michael, & Schmidt, Ulrich. (2010). Testing transitivity in choice under risk. Theory and Decision, 69, 599–614.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, Pavlo. (2010a). Reverse common ratio effect. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 40, 219–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, Pavlo. (2010b). Modifying the mean-variance approach to avoid violations of stochastic dominance. Management Science, 56(11), 2050–2057.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, Pavlo. (2013a). Which decision theory? Economics Letters, 120(1), 40–44.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, Pavlo. (2013b). Reverse Allais paradox. Economics Letters, 119(1), 60–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, Pavlo. (2014). Stronger utility. Theory and Decision, 76(2), 265–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, Pavlo. (2016). Probability weighting and L-moments. European Journal of Operational Research, 255(1), 103–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P., & Pogrebna, G. (2010). Models of stochastic choice and decision theories: Why both are important for analyzing decisions. Journal of Applied Econometrics, 25(6), 963–986.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borch, K. (1969). A note on uncertainty and indifference curves. The Review of Economic Studies, 36(1), 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, Colin. (1989). An experimental test of several generalized utility theories. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 2, 61–104.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Camerer, Colin, & Ho, T. (1994). Violations of the betweenness axiom and nonlinearity in probability. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 8, 167–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carbone, Enrica, & Hey, John. (1995). A comparison of the estimates of EU and non-EU preference functionals using data from pairwise choice and complete ranking experiments. Geneva Papers on Risk and Insurance Theory, 20, 111–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cerreia-Vioglio, S., Dillenberger, D., & Ortoleva, P. (2015). Cautious expected utility and the certainty effect. Econometrica, 83(2), 693–728.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chew, S. (1983). A generalization of the quasilinear mean with applications to the measurement of income inequality and decision theory resolving the Allais paradox. Econometrica, 51, 1065–1092.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chew, S., Epstein, L., & Segal, U. (1991). Mixture symmetry and quadratic utility. Econometrica, 59, 139–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cillo, A., & Delquié, P. (2014). Mean-risk analysis with enhanced behavioral content. European Journal of Operational Research, 239(3), 764–775.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conlisk, John. (1989). Three variants on the Allais example. American Economic Review, 79(3), 392–407.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conlisk, John. (1993). The utility of gambling. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 6, 255–275.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Day, Brett, & Loomes, Graham. (2010). Conflicting violations of transitivity and where they may lead us. Theory and Decision, 68, 233–242.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G. (1954). Decision processes. In R. M. Thrall, C. H. Coombs, & R. L. Davis (Eds.), Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function (pp. 159–165). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delquié, Philippe, & Cillo, Alessandra. (2006). Disappointment without prior expectation: A unifying perspective on decision under risk. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 33, 197–215.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ebert, S. (2015). On skewed risks in economic models and experiments. Journal of Economics Behavior and Organization, 112, 85–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ebert, S., & Wiesen, D. (2011). Testing for prudence and skewness seeking. Management Science, 57(7), 1334–1349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M., & Savage, L. (1948). The utility analysis of choices involving risk. Journal of Political Economy, 56, 279–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gini, Corrado. (1912). Variabilità e Mutabilità, contributo allo studio delle distribuzioni e delle relazione statistiche. Studi economici-giuridici dela Regia Università di Cagliari, 3, 3–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grether, David, & Plott, Charles. (1979). Economic theory of choice and the preference reversal phenomenon. American Economic Review, 69(4), 623–638.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gul, Faruk. (1991). A theory of disappointment aversion. Econometrica, 59, 667–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harless, D., & Camerer, C. (1994). The predictive utility of generalized expected utility theories. Econometrica, 62, 1251–1289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hey, John. (2001). Does repetition improve consistency? Experimental Economics, 4, 5–54.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hey, John, & Orme, Chris. (1994). Investigating generalisations of expected utility theory using experimental data. Econometrica, 62, 1291–1326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hosking, J. R. M. (1990). L-moments: Analysis and estimation of distributions using linear combinations of order statistics. Journal of the Royal Statistical Society, Series B, 52, 105–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphrey, Steven, & Verschoor, Arjan. (2004). The probability weighting function: Experimental evidence from Uganda, India and Ethiopia. Economics Letters, 84, 419–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huygens, Christiaan. (1657). Exercitationum mathematicarum. In Frans van Schooten (Ed.), De Ratiociniis in Ludo Aleae. Leiden: Elzevir.

  • Jia, Jianmin, Dyer, James S., & Butler, John C. (2001). Generalized disappointment models. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 22(1), 59–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jouini, E., Karehnke, P., & Napp, C. (2014). On portfolio choice with savoring and disappointment. Management Science, 60(3), 796–804.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, Daniel, & Tversky, Amos. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, XLVII, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karni, Edi, & Safra, Zvi. (1987). “Preference reversal” and the observability of preferences by experimental methods. Econometrica, 55(3), 675–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, Graham, Starmer, Chris, & Sugden, Robert. (1989). Preference reversal: Information-processing effect or rational non-transitive choice? Economic Journal, 99, 140–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, Graham, & Sugden, Robert. (1982). Regret theory: An alternative theory of rational choice under uncertainty. Economic Journal, 92, 805–824.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, Graham, & Sugden, Robert. (1986). Disappointment and dynamic consistency in choice under uncertainty. Review of Economic Studies, 53, 271–282.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, Graham, & Sugden, Robert. (1998). Testing different stochastic specifications of risky choice. Economica, 65, 581–598.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, Graham, & Sugden, Robert. (1991). Observing violations of transitivity by experimental methods. Econometrica, 59, 425–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, Graham, Moffatt, Peter, & Sugden, Robert. (2002). A microeconomic test of alternative stochastic theories of risky choice. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 24, 103–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markowitz, Harry M. (1952). Portfolio selection. The Journal of Finance, 7(1), 77–91.

    Google Scholar 

  • Masatlioglu, Y., & Raymond, C. (2016). A behavioral analysis of stochastic reference dependence. The American Economic Review, 106(9), 2760–2782.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mehra, R., & Prescott, E. (1985). The equity premium: A puzzle. Journal of Monetary Economics, 15(2), 341–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prelec, D. (1990). A ‘pseudo-endowment’ effect, and its implications for some recent nonexpected utility models. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 3, 247–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, John. (1981). Risk perception and risk aversion among Australian farmers. Australian Journal of Agricultural Recourse Economics, 25, 160–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, Ariel. (1988). Similarity and decision making under risk: Is there a utility theory resolution to the Allais paradox? Journal of Economic Theory, 46, 145–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, Paul. (1963). Risk and uncertainty: A fallacy of large numbers. Scientia, 98, 108–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sopher, Barry, & Gigliotti, Gary. (1993). Intransitive cycles: Rational choice or random errors? An answer based on estimation of error rates with experimental data. Theory and Decision, 35, 311–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, Chris. (1992). Testing new theories of choice under uncertainty using the common consequence effect. Review of Economic Studies, 59, 813–830.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, Chris. (2000). Developments in non-expected utility theory: The hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk. Journal of Economic Literature, 38, 332–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, Chris, & Sugden, Robert. (1991). Does the random-lottery incentive system elicit true preferences? An experimental investigation. American Economic Review, 81, 971–978.

    Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, Chris, & Sugden, Robert. (1998). Testing alternative explanations of cyclical choices. Economica, 65, 347–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos. (1969). Intransitivity of preferences. Psychological Review, 76, 31–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos, & Kahneman, Daniel. (1986). Rational choice and the framing of decisions. Journal of Business, 59(4), 251–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, Amos, & Kahneman, Daniel. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viscusi, Kip. (1989). Prospective reference theory: Toward an explanation of the paradoxes. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 2, 235–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • von Neumann, John, & Morgenstern, Oscar. (1947). Theory of games and economic behavior (2nd ed.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vuong, Quang. (1989). Likelihood ratio tests for model selection and non-nested hypotheses. Econometrica, 57, 307–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, George. (1994). An empirical test of ordinal independence. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 9, 39–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yaari, Menahem. (1987). The dual theory of choice under risk. Econometrica, 55, 95–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pavlo Blavatskyy.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary material 1 (docx 81 KB)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Blavatskyy, P. A second-generation disappointment aversion theory of decision making under risk. Theory Decis 84, 29–60 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-017-9629-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11238-017-9629-5

Keywords

Navigation