Skip to main content
Log in

Regret theory and risk attitudes

  • Published:
Journal of Risk and Uncertainty Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

We examine risk attitudes under regret theory and derive analytical expressions for two components—the resolution and regret premiums—of the risk premium under regret theory. We posit that regret-averse decision makers are risk seeking (resp., risk averse) for low (resp., high) probabilities of gains and that feedback concerning the foregone option reinforces risk attitudes. We test these hypotheses experimentally and estimate empirically both the resolution premium and the regret premium. Our results confirm the predominance of regret aversion but not the risk attitudes predicted by regret theory; they also clarify how feedback affects attitudes toward both risk and regret.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The role of regret in the psychology of decision making has been extensively investigated (Larrick 1993; Larrick and Boles 1995; Zeelenberg 1999; Connolly and Zeelenberg 2002; Connolly and Butler 2006).

  2. 2Loomes and Sugden (1982) refer to u as a “choiceless utility function”.

  3. If instead the DM does want to hear about (resp., is indifferent to) the foregone prospect’s payoffs, then the resolution premium is negative (resp., zero).

  4. In our set-up, note that the resolution premium is computed independently from the regret premium. So our set-up allows a regret-averse DM to be resolution seeking.

  5. The full list of questions is given in Appendix B (the instructions are available at goo.gl/jKOT3R and goo.gl/3ftKzu).

  6. A subject with a concave or convex utility function might prefer the RA prospect despite not being regret averse. For instance, consider a choice between prospects a = (E1, 20; E2, 70; E3, 30) and b = (E1, 45; E2, 25; E3, 50) when all three events are equally likely. Prospect a is a RA prospect because if Q is convex and u is linear then Q(45) > Q(25) + Q(20), in which case ab. If instead u is convex and Q is linear, we still have ab. Similar cases occur also when u is concave and Q is linear. To avoid classifying such subjects as regret averse, we included eight questions in which the RA prospect’s EV was lower than that of the RS prospect.

  7. If more than 50% of choices are consistent with H1, we classify the subject and question as “consistent with H1.” In case of indifference, we choose one of the options with equal probability.

  8. The estimated regret functions of regret-seeking subjects are identical under conditions F and N: Q F (α) = Q N (α) = α0.9. However, feedback increases the number of regret-seeking subjects. In particular, the number (14) of regret-seeking subjects in condition F is significantly larger than the number (3) of regret-seeking subjects in condition N. Feedback therefore decreases the entire subject pool’s regret aversion. The extremely few regret-seeking subjects under condition N precludes any meaningful comparison with their counterparts under condition F.

  9. If the certainty effect influenced our result, then the subjects would have been more consistent with respect to H1 for the second set of questions (since both prospects are risky). However, our evidence points in the opposite direction.

  10. When subjects whose responses in Section II were inconsistent with regret theory are removed and the Q-function is then recomputed, we still find that feedback polarizes regret attitudes.

References

  • Abdellaoui, M. (2000). Parameter-free elicitation of utility and probability weighting functions. Management Science, 46(11), 1497–1512.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Abdellaoui, M., L’Haridon, O., & Paraschiv, C. (2011). Experienced vs. described uncertainty: Do we need two prospect theory specifications? Management Science, 57(10), 1879–1895.

  • Anand, P. (1985). Testing regret. Management Science, 31(1), 114–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baillon, A., Bleichrodt, H., & Cillo, A. (2015). A tailor-made test of intransitive choice. Operations Research, 63(1), 198–211.

  • Barberis, N., Ming, H., & Thaler, R. (2006). Individual preferences, monetary gambles, and stock market participation: A case for narrow framing. The American Economic Review, 96(4), 1069–1090.

  • Barron, G., & Erev, I. (2003). Small feedback-based decisions and their limited correspondence to description-based decisions. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 16(3), 215–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, D. E. (1982). Regret in decision making under uncertainty. Operations Research, 30(5), 961–981.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, D. E. (1983). Risk premiums for decision regret. Management Science, 29(10), 1156–1166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bleichrodt, H., Cillo, A., & Diecidue, E. (2010). A quantitative measurement of regret theory. Management Science, 56(1), 161–175.

  • Bleichrodt, H., & Wakker, P. P. (2015). Regret theory: A bold alternative to the alternatives. The Economic Journal, 125(583), 493–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, M., & Jaffray, J. -Y. (1988). Certainty effect versus probability distortion: An experimental analysis of decision making under risk. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 14(4), 554.

    Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, T., & Butler, D. (2006). Regret in economic and psychological theories of choice. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 19(2), 139–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, T., & Zeelenberg, M. (2002). Regret in decision making. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 11(6), 212–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diecidue, E., Rudi, N., & Tang, W. (2012). Dynamic purchase decisions under regret: Price and availability. Decision Analysis, 9(1), 22–30.

  • Engelbrecht-Wiggans, R., & Katok, E. (2008). Regret and feedback information in first-price sealed-bid auctions. Management Science, 54(4), 808–819.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Erev, I., Ert, E., Plonsky, O., Cohen, D., & & Cohen, O. (2017). From anomalies to forecasts: Toward a descriptive model of decisions under risk, under ambiguity, and from experience. Psychological Review, 124(4), 327.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Filiz-Ozbay, E., & Ozbay, E. Y. (2007). Auctions with anticipated regret: Theory and experiment. The American Economic Review, 97(4), 1407–1418.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, C. R., Rogers, B. A., & Tversky, A. (1996). Options traders exhibit subadditive decision weights. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 13(1), 5–17.

  • Gollier, C., & Salanié, B. (2006). Individual decisions under risk, risk sharing and asset prices with regret. Working paper.

  • Gonzalez, R., & Wu, G. (1999). On the shape of the probability weighting function. Cognitive Psychology, 38(1), 129–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig, R., Barron, G., Weber, E. U., & & Erev, I. (2004). Decisions from experience and the effect of rare events in risky choice. Psychological Science, 15(8), 534–539.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Josephs, R. A., Larrick, R. P., Steele, C. M., & & Nisbett, R. E. (1992). Protecting the self from the negative consequences of risky decisions. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 62(1), 26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 47(2), 263–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larrick, R. P. (1993). Motivational factors in decision theories: The role of self-protection. Psychological Bulletin, 113, 440–450.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larrick, R. P., & Boles, T. L. (1995). Avoiding regret in decisions with feedback: A negotiation example. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 63 (1), 87–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G. (2010). Modeling choice and valuation in decision experiments. Psychological Review, 117(3), 902.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1982). Regret theory: An alternative theory of rational choice under uncertainty. The Economic Journal, 92(368), 805–824.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1987). Some implications of a more general form of regret theory. Journal of Economic Theory, 41(2), 270–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lopes, L. L., & Oden, G. C. (1999). The role of aspiration level in risky choice: A comparison of cumulative prospect theory and SP/A theory. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 43(2), 286–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michenaud, S., & Solnik, B. (2008). Applying regret theory to investment choices: Currency hedging decisions. Journal of International Money and Finance, 27(5), 677–694.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muermann, A., & Volkman, J. (2006). Regret, pride, and the disposition effect. Working paper.

  • Nasiry, J., & Popescu, I. (2012). Advance selling when consumers regret. Management Science, 58(6), 1160–1177.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perakis, G., & Roels, G. (2008). Regret in the newsvendor model with partial information. Operations Research, 56(1), 188–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Qin, J. (2015). A model of regret, investor behavior, and market turbulence. Journal of Economic Theory, 160, 150–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ritov, I. (1996). Probability of regret: Anticipation of uncertainty resolution in choice. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 66(2), 228–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ritov, I., & Baron, J. (1995). Outcome knowledge, regret, and omission bias. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 64(2), 119–127.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, C. (2000). Developments in non-expected utility theory: The hunt for a descriptive theory of choice under risk. Journal of Economic Literature, 38(2), 332–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. (1993). Testing for juxtaposition and event-splitting effects. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 6(3), 235–254.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5(4), 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Wakker, P. (1995). Risk attitudes and decision weights. Econometrica, 63(6), 1255–1280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van de Kuilen, G. (2009). Subjective probability weighting and the discovered preference hypothesis. Theory and Decision, 67(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viefers, P., & Strack, P. (2014). Too proud to stop: Regret in dynamic decisions. Working paper.

  • von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1947). Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakker, P. (2010). Prospect theory for risk and ambiguity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zeelenberg, M. (1999). Anticipated regret, expected feedback and behavioral decision making. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 12(2), 93–106.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zeelenberg, M., & Beattie, J. (1997). Consequences of regret aversion 2: Additional evidence for effects of feedback on decision making. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 72(1), 63–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zeelenberg, M., Beattie, J., Van der Pligt, J., & & de Vries, N. K. (1996). Consequences of regret aversion: Effect of expected feedback on risky decision making. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 65, 148–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We thank Aurélien Baillon, Han Bleichrodt, Luc Wathieu, Klaus Wertenbroch, Horst Zank, the editor, and an anonymous referee for their helpful comments. We also gratefully acknowledge support from the People Program (Marie Curie Actions) of the European Union’s Seventh Framework Program FP7/2007–2013/ under REA grant agreement 290255.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Enrico Diecidue.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

(PDF 534 KB)

Appendices

Appendix A

1.1 Example of experimental stimuli for Sections I and II

Fig. 3
figure 3

Screenshot of Section I stimuli

Fig. 4
figure 4

Screenshot of Section II stimulii

Fig. 5
figure 5

Screenshot of feedback

Appendix B

1.1 Questions used in Sections I and II of the lab experiment

Table 16 Questions used in Section I of the lab experiment
Table 17 Questions used in Section II of the lab experiment to identify attitudes toward risk

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Somasundaram, J., Diecidue, E. Regret theory and risk attitudes. J Risk Uncertain 55, 147–175 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-017-9268-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11166-017-9268-9

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation