Skip to main content
Log in

Personal identity and cosmopolitan philosophy

  • Published:
Philosophical Studies Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Jonardon Ganeri’s The Self: Naturalism, Consciousness, and the First-Person Stance is a trailblazing study in cross-cultural philosophy of mind. Its liberal conception of naturalism makes room for a rich analytic taxonomy of conceptions of personal identity that go well beyond the standard models of Cartesianism, Physicalism, and Reductionism. But this naturalistically respectable model of the self must contend with the fact that the findings of the cognitive sciences are also compatible with ontological antirealism about the self. And while the book opens new avenues for systematic reflection that thoroughly engages the historical material (specifically, the views of influential first millennium Indian and Buddhist philosophers), its solutions to the problem of personal identity and the problem of self-knowledge often shortcut descriptive accounts that take agency and self-awareness to be constituted by their proprietary phenomenology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The literature on cross-cultural philosophy of mind has been growing steadily in recent years. Jonardon’s book, along with such edited collections as Self, No-Self: Perspectives from Analytical, Phenomenological, and Indian Traditions (Siderits et al. 2011), showcase the state of the art in the exploration of issues about consciousness, subjectivity, and selfhood from across different philosophical traditions.

  2. As Smith (2012) noted recently on the opinion pages of the New York Times, this exclusionary attitude is compounded by the fact that many if not most philosophers today reject the idea that “what they do is essentially bound to the discipline’s past.” Having reconceived philosophy on the model of the sciences, which are free to reject past theories that were disproven long ago, most practitioners of the genre consider it perfectly reasonable to ignore not just the philosophical traditions of ancient India and China, but those of early modern Europe as well.

  3. There is perhaps no more flagrant an expression of this bias than Anthony Flew’s now classic sweeping remark, in his An Introduction to Western Philosophy: ‘…philosophy, as the word is understood here, is concerned first, last and all the time with argument. It is, incidentally, because most of what is labeled Eastern Philosophy is not so concerned––rather than any reason of European parochialism––that this book draws no materials from any source east of Suez’ (Flew 1971: 36).

  4. In my first book, I argue that insofar as they are rooted in different aspects of their conscious experience rather than, say, doctrinal considerations, the argumentative strategies of first millennium Indian and Buddhist philosophers “are better showcased when made continuous with contemporary philosophical concerns” (Coseru 2012). I make a stronger case for the cosmopolitan approach in Coseru (2017).

  5. Bhushan and Garfield (2011: xiii) quote the following statement from Daya Krishna: “Anybody who is writing in English is not an Indian philosopher…What the British produced was a strange species…The strangeness of the species is that their terms of reference are the West…They put [philosophical problems] in a Western way.”

  6. Granoff's (1979) work on Śrī Harṣa, Phillips' (1995) work on Gaṅgeśa, and Taber’s (2005) work on Kumārila are among the best classical examples of this latter approach that explicitly resists the attribution of contemporary positions to classical thinkers.

  7. Much of what I have to say in Sects. 3 and 4 is a revised and expanded version of my review essay of the book (Coseru 2015).

References

  • Angle, S. C. (2007). “中 國 哲 學 家 與 全 求 哲 學 [Chinese Philosophers and Global Philosophy],” 中 國 哲 學 與 文 化 [Chinese Philosophy and Culture] 1(1), 239–256.

  • Bermudez, J. (1998). The paradox of self-consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez, J. (2011). Bodily awareness and self-consciousness. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The oxford handbook of the self (pp. 157–179). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhushan, N., & Garfield, J. L. (Eds.). (2011). Indian philosophy in english. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (1997). Self and world. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassam, Q. (2011). The embodied self. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 139–156). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2000). A theory of sentience. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Connolly, T. (2015). Doing philosophy comparatively. New York: Bloomsbury Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coseru, C. (2012). Perceiving reality: Consciousness, intentionality, and cognition in Buddhist philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Coseru, C. (2015). Selves: Subpersonal, immersed, and participating. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14(4), 1083–1088.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Coseru, C. (2017). Interpretations and interventions: Indian philosophy and the cosmopolitan approach. In P. Bilimoria (Ed.), History of Indian philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, O. (2011). The Bodhisattva’s brain: Buddhism naturalized. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flew, A. (1971). Introduction to Western philosophy: Ideas and arguments from Plato to Sartre. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, Jerry A. (2003). Hume variations. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franco, E. (1997). Dharmakīrti on compassion and rebirth. Wien: Universität Wien.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ganeri, J. (2012). The self: Naturalism, consciousness, and the first-person stance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ganeri, J. (2015). Blueprint: An institute for cosmopolitan philosophy in a culturally polycentric world (academia.edu).

  • Ganeri, J. (2017). Attention, not self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Granoff, P. (1979). Philosophy and Argument in Late Vedānta. Śrī Harṣa’s Khaṇḍanakhaṇḍakhādya. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hales, S. D. (2008). Review of Hans-Johann Glock, What is Analytic Philosophy?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews.

  • Kim, J. (1988). Supervenience for multiple domains. Philosophical Topics, 16, 129–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lærke, M., Smith, J. E. H., & Schliesser, E. (2013). Introduction. In M. Lærke, J. E. H. Smith, & E. Schliesser (Eds.), Philosophy and its history: Aims and methods in the study of early modern philosophy (pp. 1–6). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Legrand, D. (2007). Subjectivity and the body: Introducing basic forms of self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 16(3), 577–582.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Legrand, D. (2011). Phenomenological dimensions of bodily self-consciousness. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 204–227). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. C. (1984). The relationship of philosophy to its past. In R. Rorty, J. B. Schneewind, & Q. Skinner (Eds.), Philosophy in history: Essays on the historiography of philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matilal, B. K. (1989). Perception: An essay on classical Indian theories of knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mou, B. (2010). On constructive-engagement strategy of comparative philosophy: A journal theme introduction. Comparative Philosophy, 1(1), 1–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oberding, A. (2015). It’s not them, it’s you: A case study concerning the exclusion of Non-Western Philosophy. Comparative Philosophy, 6(2), 14–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, S. (1995). Classical Indian metaphysics: Refutations of realism and the emergence of “New Logic”. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shukla, B. (1984). Nyāya-śastrīya-vicāra-paddhatyā dehātmavādasya sambhābhana, Sarasvatī Suṣamā 38: 121–124. Translated as “Dehātmavāda or the Body as Soul: The Exploration of a Possibility within Nyāya Thought.” Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1991, 1–17.

  • Siderits, M., Thompson, E., & Zahavi, D. (Eds.). (2011). Self, no-self perspectives from analytical, phenomenological, and Indian traditions. Oxford University Press: Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. E. H. (2012). “Philosophy’s Western Bias”. The New York Times, The Stone, June 3.

  • Smith, J. E. H. (2015). Tradition, culture, and the problem of inclusion in philosophy. Comparative Philosophy, 6(2), 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1966). The bounds of sense: An essay on Kant’s ‘critique of pure reason’. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2009). Selves: An essay in revisionary metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Taber, J. (2005). A Hindu critique of Buddhist epistemology. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (2002). Truth and truthfulness: An essay in genealogy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (2014). Essays and reviews 1959–2002. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahavi, D. (2014). Self and other: Exploring subjectivity, empathy, and shame. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Coseru.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Coseru, C. Personal identity and cosmopolitan philosophy. Philos Stud 174, 1749–1760 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0829-6

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0829-6

Keywords

Navigation