Philosophical Studies

, Volume 174, Issue 7, pp 1749–1760 | Cite as

Personal identity and cosmopolitan philosophy

Article
  • 429 Downloads

Abstract

Jonardon Ganeri’s The Self: Naturalism, Consciousness, and the First-Person Stance is a trailblazing study in cross-cultural philosophy of mind. Its liberal conception of naturalism makes room for a rich analytic taxonomy of conceptions of personal identity that go well beyond the standard models of Cartesianism, Physicalism, and Reductionism. But this naturalistically respectable model of the self must contend with the fact that the findings of the cognitive sciences are also compatible with ontological antirealism about the self. And while the book opens new avenues for systematic reflection that thoroughly engages the historical material (specifically, the views of influential first millennium Indian and Buddhist philosophers), its solutions to the problem of personal identity and the problem of self-knowledge often shortcut descriptive accounts that take agency and self-awareness to be constituted by their proprietary phenomenology.

Keywords

Agency Reflexive self-consciousness Self Naturalism Physicalism Cosmopolitan philosophy 

References

  1. Angle, S. C. (2007). “中 國 哲 學 家 與 全 求 哲 學 [Chinese Philosophers and Global Philosophy],” 中 國 哲 學 與 文 化 [Chinese Philosophy and Culture] 1(1), 239–256.Google Scholar
  2. Bermudez, J. (1998). The paradox of self-consciousness. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bermudez, J. (2011). Bodily awareness and self-consciousness. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The oxford handbook of the self (pp. 157–179). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Bhushan, N., & Garfield, J. L. (Eds.). (2011). Indian philosophy in english. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Cassam, Q. (1997). Self and world. Oxford: Clarendon.Google Scholar
  6. Cassam, Q. (2011). The embodied self. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 139–156). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Clark, A. (2000). A theory of sentience. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Connolly, T. (2015). Doing philosophy comparatively. New York: Bloomsbury Publishing.Google Scholar
  9. Coseru, C. (2012). Perceiving reality: Consciousness, intentionality, and cognition in Buddhist philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Coseru, C. (2015). Selves: Subpersonal, immersed, and participating. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 14(4), 1083–1088.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Coseru, C. (2017). Interpretations and interventions: Indian philosophy and the cosmopolitan approach. In P. Bilimoria (Ed.), History of Indian philosophy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  12. Flanagan, O. (2011). The Bodhisattva’s brain: Buddhism naturalized. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  13. Flew, A. (1971). Introduction to Western philosophy: Ideas and arguments from Plato to Sartre. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.Google Scholar
  14. Fodor, Jerry A. (2003). Hume variations. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Franco, E. (1997). Dharmakīrti on compassion and rebirth. Wien: Universität Wien.Google Scholar
  16. Ganeri, J. (2012). The self: Naturalism, consciousness, and the first-person stance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Ganeri, J. (2015). Blueprint: An institute for cosmopolitan philosophy in a culturally polycentric world (academia.edu).Google Scholar
  18. Ganeri, J. (2017). Attention, not self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Granoff, P. (1979). Philosophy and Argument in Late Vedānta. Śrī Harṣa’s Khaṇḍanakhaṇḍakhādya. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Co.Google Scholar
  20. Hales, S. D. (2008). Review of Hans-Johann Glock, What is Analytic Philosophy?. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews. Google Scholar
  21. Kim, J. (1988). Supervenience for multiple domains. Philosophical Topics, 16, 129–150.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Lærke, M., Smith, J. E. H., & Schliesser, E. (2013). Introduction. In M. Lærke, J. E. H. Smith, & E. Schliesser (Eds.), Philosophy and its history: Aims and methods in the study of early modern philosophy (pp. 1–6). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Legrand, D. (2007). Subjectivity and the body: Introducing basic forms of self-consciousness. Consciousness and Cognition, 16(3), 577–582.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Legrand, D. (2011). Phenomenological dimensions of bodily self-consciousness. In S. Gallagher (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of the self (pp. 204–227). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  25. MacIntyre, A. C. (1984). The relationship of philosophy to its past. In R. Rorty, J. B. Schneewind, & Q. Skinner (Eds.), Philosophy in history: Essays on the historiography of philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  26. Matilal, B. K. (1989). Perception: An essay on classical Indian theories of knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Mou, B. (2010). On constructive-engagement strategy of comparative philosophy: A journal theme introduction. Comparative Philosophy, 1(1), 1–32.Google Scholar
  28. Oberding, A. (2015). It’s not them, it’s you: A case study concerning the exclusion of Non-Western Philosophy. Comparative Philosophy, 6(2), 14–34.Google Scholar
  29. Phillips, S. (1995). Classical Indian metaphysics: Refutations of realism and the emergence of “New Logic”. Chicago: Open Court.Google Scholar
  30. Shukla, B. (1984). Nyāya-śastrīya-vicāra-paddhatyā dehātmavādasya sambhābhana, Sarasvatī Suṣamā 38: 121–124. Translated as “Dehātmavāda or the Body as Soul: The Exploration of a Possibility within Nyāya Thought.” Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 1991, 1–17.Google Scholar
  31. Siderits, M., Thompson, E., & Zahavi, D. (Eds.). (2011). Self, no-self perspectives from analytical, phenomenological, and Indian traditions. Oxford University Press: Oxford.Google Scholar
  32. Smith, J. E. H. (2012). “Philosophy’s Western Bias”. The New York Times, The Stone, June 3.Google Scholar
  33. Smith, J. E. H. (2015). Tradition, culture, and the problem of inclusion in philosophy. Comparative Philosophy, 6(2), 1–13.Google Scholar
  34. Strawson, P. F. (1966). The bounds of sense: An essay on Kant’s ‘critique of pure reason’. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
  35. Strawson, G. (2009). Selves: An essay in revisionary metaphysics. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Taber, J. (2005). A Hindu critique of Buddhist epistemology. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  37. Williams, B. (2002). Truth and truthfulness: An essay in genealogy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  38. Williams, B. (2014). Essays and reviews 1959–2002. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  39. Zahavi, D. (2014). Self and other: Exploring subjectivity, empathy, and shame. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyCollege of CharlestonCharlestonUSA

Personalised recommendations