Skip to main content
Log in

The possessive morphosyntactic strategy of gradable predication in Taiwanese Southern Min and the measure function

  • Published:
Journal of East Asian Linguistics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The TSM u N construction adopts the possessive morphosyntactic strategy of gradable predication to construct a gradable predicate headed by the possessive verb u ‘have’. The possessive verb u ‘have’ inside, in addition to retaining its possessive meaning, introduces a functional projection (i.e., MeasP) headed by Meas, which denotes a measure function measuring the denotation of the N component along the dimension of cardinality or quantity. Depending on whether the N component is an abstract noun or a non-abstract noun, the measure scale associated with the gradable u N predicate can be an interval one or a ratio one. This study has the following implications. First, many languages might use the possessive or existential verb to construct a gradable possessive verbal predicate; however, they might differ from each other in the semantic function the possessive or existential verb plays. Second, a TSM PC nominal does not denote a scale resulting from the total preorder ≤. Third, a TSM gradable adjective is lexically specified with a scale.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Abbreviations used in this paper include: CL: classifier, E: marker for modifying phrases, MC: Mandarin Chinese, PRT: particle, SFP: sentence final particle and TSM: Taiwanese Southern Min. Also, nasalization of TSM vowels is signaled by –nn, and will be left unspecified if it is predictable.

  2. The ideas of Li (2017) are all incorporated into her (2019) book chapter. So, in Sect. 5, I will remark on Li (2019) instead. Besides, Liu (2020), which focuses on the TSM u V construction, presents his ideas about the TSM u N construction in an appendix-like section, and the ideas there are mainly based on Liu (2019). So, it is Liu (2019) that is remarked.

  3. The predicate modification relation here is subject to the principle of predicate modification revised from Heim and Kratzer (1998: 65), as (i) shows.

    (i)

    Predicate Modification

     

    If α is a branching node, {β, ∃γ} is the set of α’s daughters, and ⟦β⟧ and ⟦γ⟧ are

     

    both in D<e, t>, then ⟦α⟧ = λxDe.⟦β⟧(x) = ⟦γ⟧(x) =1.

    Assuming that the covert Pro is the syntactic object of the transitive verb tsia ‘eat’, in (22b), Predicate Modification works in a way, as (iia–c) illustrate.

    (ii)

    a.

    λx.∃y[tsia(x, y)]

     

    b.

    λx.pa(x)

     

    c.

    λx.∃y[tsia(x, y) & pa(x)]

  4. One anonymous reviewer asks whether examples like (23a–b) count as serial verb constructions. According to Li and Thompson (1981: 594), a Mandarin Chinese serial verb construction has the “[…] (NP) V (NP) (NP) V (NP)” form and always “refers to events or states of affairs which are understood to be related as parts of one overall event or state”. As Paul (2008: 369–370) further argues, a Mandarin Chinese serial verb construction always “contains two or more verb phrases or clauses juxtaposed without any marker indicating what their relationship is between them”. So, examples like (23a–b) can be considered a type of serial verb construction, and it is the predicate modification relation that connects the verb phrases or clauses involved. Since the verb phrases (or clauses) involved might form a coordinated structure together, it is hard to clearly identify which verb phrase or clause is the main one. So, I do not have any intention of saying that, in (23a–b), the ‘u N’ part of the TSM u N construction is the main predicate; therefore, the English translation I provide for (23a) is the intended meaning which does not reflect its syntactic structure.

  5. The occurrence of the covert object Pro behind the verb be ‘sell’ in (23a) implies that be ‘sell’ is a transitive verb.

  6. Given this, I will use the TSM u N construction to represent the TSM u N construction and the TSM bo N construction in the rest of this study. The term ‘the TSM bo N construction’ will not be used unless it is necessary.

  7. As Wellwood (2015: 74) points out, her semantics of much (i.e., (36)) is similar to the semantics of the covert expression Meas suggested by Solt (2015).

  8. Wellwood (2015: 75) uses Hilbert’s є operator to represent the silent indefinite determiner which combines with pear.

  9. One anonymous reviewer wonders whether there is any further motivation for the assumption that the TSM morpheme u has as part of its inherent meaning a measure function. Indeed, Taiwanese Southern Min per se provides one further motivation for this assumption. In the TSM u V construction, the morpheme u, which forms a gradable predicate with a non-gradable verb like tshing ‘wear’, has lost the meaning of ‘have’.

    (i)

    Tsit-khuan

    sann

    tsin

    u-tshing.

     

    This-CL

    clothing

    very

    have-wear

     

    ‘For anyone to wear it, this kind of clothing is very durable/lasts quite long.’

    Namely, in (i), the TSM morpheme u, which cannot take a morpheme with the meaning of ‘have’ in other languages as its translational equivalent, simply functions to introduce a measure function with which the event denoted by the verb tshing ‘wear’ is measured. So, I suggest that the inherent core meaning of the TSM morpheme u is ‘the measure function’, and the meaning of ‘have’, depending on whether it occurs in the TSM u N construction or the TSM u V construction, might be optional. Given this, it does not matter to my assumption whether the morpheme with the meaning of ‘have’ in other languages has ‘the measure function’ as part of its inherent meaning. Relevantly here, my teasing the ‘measure function’ meaning apart from the ‘have’ meaning of the morpheme u of the TSM u N construction has a bonus; that is, my analysis of the morpheme u of the TSM u N construction can accommodate the morpheme u of the TSM u V construction.

  10. Although I assume that a TSM PC nominal is not lexically specified with a scale resulting by the preorder ≤, this does not exclude the possibility of assigning a TSM PC nominal the type of <p, t> because PC nominals do not denote entities as non-PC nominals do. As I have pointed out, the TSM possessive verb u ‘have’ can form a gradable possessive predicate with a PC nominal or a non-PC nominal. Thus, instead of assuming that the argument P in (41) can be of type <e, t> or <p, t>, for ease of exposition, I will use <e, t> to represent the semantic type of TSM PC nominals, especially those occurring in the TSM u N construction, because doing so does not have any significant impact on my analysis. Hence, I leave it open whether a TSM PC nominal is of type <p, t> or <e, t>. Please see Sect. 5.1 for further discussion.

  11. For reader-friendliness, I use English as the metalanguage to represent the Taiwanese Southern Min words in (43b).

  12. As one anonymous reviewer reminds me, in Taiwanese Southern Min, there are two potential ways in which non-abstract nouns can be modified by degree modifiers like kha ‘more’ and tsin ‘very’, namely in combination with tse ‘many’ or u ‘have’, as illustrated by (ia-b), respectively.

    (i)

    a.

    Yi

    kin

    ni

    u

    kha

    tse

    hasing.

      

    s/he

    this

    year

    have

    more

    many

    student

      

    ‘This year, s/he has more students.’

     

    b.

    Yi

    kin

    ni

    kha

    u

    hasing.

     
      

    s/he

    this

    year

    more

    have

    student

     
      

    ‘This year, s/he has more students.’

     

    As s/he further points out to me, relevant to (ia–b) are the following two questions. First, what are the properties of tse ‘many’? For example, as it is translated as many, does it also introduce a measure function as the English quantity adjective many/much does? Second, how does tse ‘many’ interact with u ‘have’?

    For the first question, along the line of Wellwood (2015) and Solt (2015), I suggest that, in (ia), the TSM morpheme tse ‘many’ is a quantity adjective and functions to introduce a measure function that measures the denotation of the noun modified by it along some dimension. Given this, I further assume that, in (ia), the morpheme u is the ‘pure’ possessive verb ‘have’ that cannot form a gradable predicate with the predicate right after it (i.e., u kha tse hasing ‘have more many student’), as the ungrammaticality of (ii) attests.

    (ii)

    *Yi

    kin

    ni

    kha

    u

    kha

    tse

    hasing.

     

    s/he

    this

    year

    more

    have

    more

    many

    student

    As for the question of how tse ‘many’ interacts with the TSM morpheme u ‘have’, as I have argued, in the TSM u N construction (e.g., (ib)), the morpheme u, in addition to retaining the meaning of ‘have’, functions to introduce a functional phrase (i.e., MeasP) headed by Meas that denotes a measure function. The ungrammaticality of (ii) further leads me to assume that two measure function introducers cannot share the same ‘modifyee’. This assumption is verified by the grammaticality of (iii) because (iii) differs from (ii) in that, in (iii), the measure function introducer tse ‘many’ ‘modifies’ the noun sann ‘clothing’ but the measure function introducer u ‘modifies’ the verb tshing ‘wear’ (Liu 2020).

    (iii)

    Tsimma,

    tsin

    tse

    sann

    long

    tsiok

    u

    tshing

    e.

     

    Nowadays

    very

    many

    clothing

    all

    very

    have

    wear

    SFP

     

    ‘Nowadays, many kinds of clothing are all very durable/last quite long.’

    Furthermore, the presence of tse ‘many’ in between u ‘have’ and the non-abstract noun, as (ia) shows, does not imply that tse ‘many’ is the spell-out of the head Meas in (iva) because (ivb) is ungrammatical.

    (iv)

    a.

    Yi

    [kha [VP

    [V u]

    [MeasP Meas [NP hasing]]]].

     
      

    s/he

    more

    have

    student

     
      

    ‘S/He has more students.’

     
     

    b.

    *Yi

    kha

    u

    tse

    hasing.

      

    s/he

    more

    have

    many

    student

  13. Here (49a–f) are not used in a context with the contrastive focus.

  14. Example (i) pointed out to me by one anonymous reviewer cannot be a counterexample to my analysis here because the grammaticality of (i) is expected under my analysis.

    (i)

    John is 100 times richer than you.

    Namely, one’s property, for example being worth one billion dollars, can be measured by a conventional objective measure scale but one’s self-cultivation cannot.

  15. According to Francez and Kootz-Garboden (2015: 548), (62b) can be described as follows: with P being a variable over (abstract) substance and being a possessive relation, D, being a variable over sets of portions, provides a domain restriction for the existential quantifier such that the value of z is restricted to portions that count as ‘big enough’ in context.

  16. This language-specific feature shown by the TSM u N construction is only about the TSM gradable u N possessive verbal predicate. So, it does not imply that concrete (mass) nouns cannot occur as complement of the possessive verb in other languages especially when the possessive verbal predicate is non-gradable, as (i–iii) illustrate.

    (i)

    Zhāngsān

    yŏu

    chē.

     

    Zhangsan

    have

    car

     

    ‘Zhangsan

    has

    cars.’

    (ii)

    John has cars.

    (iii)

    Yi

    (*kha)

    u

    tsit-tai

    tshia.

     

    s/he

    more

    have

    one-CL

    car

     

    ‘S/he (*more) has a car.’

  17. For reader-friendliness, I use English as the metalanguage to represent the Taiwanese Southern Min words in (78b).

  18. Liu (2019) uses HOLD to represent the possessive relation between the individual y and the property about self-cultivation.

  19. The N component of a gradable hěn N predicate, in fact, can be a concrete noun, as (i) shows.

    (i)

    Zhè

    jiāhuŏ

    hěn

    jīchē.

     

    This

    guy

    very

    motorcycle

     

    ‘Intended: This guy is a real pain in the butt.’

  20. The following two empirical facts provide further evidence in support of this argument. First, although the TSM u N construction allows the N component to be a concrete noun, the meaning conveyed by the first half of a TSM sentence like (i), in which the N component of the u N predicate is the concrete noun tshitiunn ‘market’, differs from the (84a)-like meaning which the anonymous reviewer might want to attribute to it (i.e., the city is more popular for the market) by conveying that there are more markets in the city’.

    (i)

    Tootshi

    kha

    u

    tshitiunn,

    be

    mihkiann

    kha

    hongpen.

     

    city

    more

    have

    market

    buy

    thing

    more

    convenient

     

    ‘There are more markets in the city; it is more convenient to buy things in the

     

    city.’

    Second, as the interpretation of (i) implies, if Mandarin Chinese allows the concrete noun shìchăng ‘market’ to occur as the N component of the gradable yŏu N construction, then example (ii) is expected to be acceptable, contrary to fact.

    (ii)

    *Dūshì

    gèng

    yŏu

    shìchăng,

    măi

    dōngxī

    gèng

    fāngbiàn.

     

    city

    even-more

    have

    market

    buy

    thing

    even-more

    convenient

     

    ‘Intended: There are more markets in the city; it is more convenient to buy

     

    things in the city.’

    So, the meaning conveyed by the noun shìchăng in (88) provided by one anonymous reviewer should not be the concrete meaning of ‘market’.

References

  • Castroviejo Miró, Elena. 2008. Deconstructing exclamations. Catalan Journal of Linguistics 7: 41–90.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chernilovskaya, Anna, and Rick Nouwen. 2012. “On wh-exclamatives and noteworthiness.” In Proceedings of the Amsterdam Colloquium 2011. Dordrecht: Springer.

  • Francez, Itamar, and Andrew Koontz-Garboden. 2015. Semantic variation and the grammar of property concepts. Language 91(3): 533–563.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Francez, Itamar, and Andrew Koontz-Garboden. 2017. Semantics and Morphosyntactic Variation: Qualities and the Grammar of Property Concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, Irene, and Angelika Kratzer. 1998. Semantics in Generative Grammar. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huang, Cheng-Teh James. 1988. Wó păo dé kuài and Chinese phrase structure. Language 64(2): 274–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, Christopher. 2007. Vagueness and grammar: The semantics of relative and absolute gradable predicates. Linguistics and Philosophy 30(1): 1–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, Christopher, and Louise McNally. 2005. Scale structure, degree modification and the semantic typology of gradable predicates. Language 81(2): 345–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koontz-Garboden, Andrew, and Itamar Francez. 2010. Possessed properties in Ulwa. Natural Language Semantics 18(2): 197–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lasersohn, Peter. 2005. Context dependence, disagreement, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy 28(4): 643–686.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Li, Charles N., and Sandra A. Thompson. 1981. Mandarin Chinese: A Functional Reference Grammar. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Li, Xiao. 2017. Subjectivity and gradability: On the semantics of the possessive property concept construction in Mandarin Chinese. Paper presented at the 53rd Annual Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society. http://qcpages.qc.cuny.edu/~xli/Research/Subjectivity_Gradability.pdf

  • Li, Xiao. 2019. “Measure scales and gradability: On the semantics of the possessive property concept construction in Mandarin Chinese.” In The Semantics of Plurals, Focus, Degrees, and Times: Essays in Honor of Roger Schwarzschild, edited by Daniel Altshuler and Jessica Rett, 239–256. Springer. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-04438-1_12

  • Liu, Chen-Sheng Luther. 2010. The positive morpheme in Chinese and the adjectival structure. Lingua 120(4): 1010–1056.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Chen-Sheng Luther. 2018. Projecting adjectives in Chinese. Journal of East Asian Linguistics 27(1): 67–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Chen-Sheng Luther. 2019. The possessive morphosyntactic strategy for predicating gradable properties in Taiwanese Southern Min. Paper presented at the Seventh Symposium on Recent Advances in Chinese Syntax and Semantics, Guangdong University of Foreign Studies, Guangzhou, China, November 08–10, 2019.

  • Liu, Chen-Sheng Luther. 2020. A morpheme introducing degrees and its impact on argument structure: The Taiwanese Southern Min U. Glossa: A Journal of General Linguistics 5(1): 37.1-40. https://doi.org/10.5334/gjgl.1021.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, Zhilang. 2020. Děngjíxìng ‘yŏu + míngcí’ jiégòu de yǔyì yánjiù [On the semantics of gradable ‘yŏu + N’ constructions]. Master thesis, Nanjing University.

  • Paul, Waltraud. 2008. The serial verb construction in Chinese: A tenacious myth and a Gordian knot. The Linguistic Review 25(3/4): 367–411.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rett, Jessica. 2011. Exclamatives, degrees and speech acts. Linguistics and Philosophy 34(5): 411–442.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, Roger. 2002. “The grammar of measurement.” In Proceedings of SALT XII, edited by Brendan Jackson, 225–245. Ithaca, NY: CLC Publications.

  • Schwarzschild, Roger. 2006. The role of dimensions in the syntax of noun phrase. Syntax 9(1): 67–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Solt, Stephanie. 2015. Q-adjectives and the semantics of quantity. Journal of Semantics 32(2): 221–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spencer, Andrew. 2005. Word-formation and syntax. In Handbook of Word-Formation, edited by Pavol Štekauer and Rochelle Lieber, 73–97. Amsterdam: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stephenson, Tamina. 2007. Judge dependence, epistemic modals, and predicates of personal taste. Linguistics and Philosophy 30(4): 487–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stevens, Stanley Smith. 1946. On the theory of scales of measurement. Science 103: 677–680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stevens, Stanley Smith. 1957. On the psychophysical law. Psychological Review 64(3): 153–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tovena, Lucia. 2001. “Between mass and count.” In Proceedings of the 20th West Coast Conference on Formal Linguistics, edited by Karine Megerdoomian and Leora Anne Bar-el, 565–578. Somerville, MA: Cascadilla Proceedings Project.

  • Van de Velde, Danièle. 1996. Le Spectre nominal. Des noms de matières aux noms d’abstractions. Louvain: Peeters.

  • Wellwood, Alexis. 2015. On the semantics of comparison across categories. Linguistics and Philosophy 38(1): 67–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhu, Dexi. 1982. Yúfă Jiăngyì [Lectures on Chinese Syntax]. Běijīng: Shāngwù Yìnshūguăn.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Various versions of this article have been presented at the 7th Symposium on Recent Advances in Chinese Syntax and Semantics held by Guangdong University of Foreign Studies on November 08–10, 2019 and the 13th Workshop on Formal Syntax and Semantics held by Academia Sinica (Taiwan) on October 16–17, 2020. I am grateful for the feedback from the audiences there, especially from Roger Wěi-Wén Liào, Jò-Wàng Lín, Hóngyŏng Liú, Hăihuá Pān, Dìngxǔ Shí, Sze-Wing Tang, Yù-Yún Wáng, Yáng Yáng and Qìngwén Zhāng. I would also like to express my immense gratitude to Yì-Hsūn Chén for his timely and stimulating comments as well as constructive suggestions on various parts/versions of this article. The keen and rigorous comments as well as constructive suggestions from the anonymous reviewers and editors, especially Jim Huang, also improved the content and presentation of this work considerably. Added to these, I am indebted to Chīn-Fā Lién, Chúng-Háo Kū and Tíng-Chì Wèi for crosschecking the data used in this study for grammaticality judgments. Needless to say, any errors or inconsistencies that have persisted are my responsibility. This study is partially funded by the research Grant MOST108-2410-H-009-004 from the Ministry of Science of Technology, Taiwan, to which I am very grateful.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Chen-Sheng Luther Liu.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Liu, CS.L. The possessive morphosyntactic strategy of gradable predication in Taiwanese Southern Min and the measure function. J East Asian Linguist 31, 179–220 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10831-022-09238-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10831-022-09238-2

Keywords

Navigation