Skip to main content

How to Vindicate (Fictional) Creationism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Abstract Objects

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 422))

Abstract

In this paper, I want to show that Moderate Creationism (MC), a variant among realist doctrines concerning fictional entities (ficta), is the only form of Fictional Creationism that may rescue it from both the ontological and the metaphysical criticisms that have been recently raised against this position in general. According to MC, what is distinctively required in order for a fictum to come into existence qua abstract mind-dependent entity is that a certain reflexive stance applies to the non- ontologically committal make-believe practice that there is a certain (nonactual yet typically concrete) individual. In this stance, the practice is taken as involving a certain set of properties, the properties the storyteller mobilises in the relevant bit of her narration. So taken, the practice amounts to the fact that that very set of properties is make-believedly identical with a certain (nonactual yet typically concrete) individual. In particular, I appeal to a strong version of MC, according to which, once it is so taken, the practice counts as a certain fictum, in virtue of a constitutive rule for its generation. For this version may account for the special sense in which ficta may be created entities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    Thesis b) is mostly explicitly defended in Thomasson (1999), but it traces back to the seminal work of Ingarden (1973) as well as to van Inwagen (1977) and Kripke (2013). For other defenders of the thesis cf. Searle (1979), Salmon (1998), Schiffer (1996, 2003), Predelli (2002), Goodman (2004), Braun (2005).

  2. 2.

    As to (Neo)Meinongians, cf. e.g. Castañeda (1989), Parsons (1980), Zalta (1983). As to (Im)possibliists, cf. Lewis (1983), Priest (2016)2, Berto (2013). Berto’s and Priest’s theories are also a variant of (Neo)Meinongianism, i.e., Modal Meinongianism.

  3. 3.

    Voltolini (2006, 2015b). One normally believes that Kripke (2011, 2013) is a defender of RC. Yet there are reasons to call this belief into question. First, Kripke says that the make-believe practice in which one pretends that there is an individual that does such and such things is not ontologically committed to ficta (2013: 81, 148); ficta rather come into existence in virtue of certain human activities. Kripke gives, as examples of such activities, telling stories, writing plays, writing novels (2011:63–4), (2013: 73, 76). Second, he says that fictional works are sufficient conditions for ficta (2013: 71–2). Thus, one may suspect that within such activities there also is the sort of reflection that is manifested in what he labels a derivative or extended use of language that is committed to ficta (ibid.: 81, 103, 148–50). Schiffer (1996, 2003) called this use the hypostatising use, which is for Kripke the condition for further ascribing ficta also story-relative properties (2011: 65), (2013: 74–5, 83). All this suggests that Kripke is rather a forerunner of MC.

  4. 4.

    For Sainsbury (2010: 61–3, 82–5), who is an antirealist, Creationism is the only realist doctrine that manages to face the socalled selection problem: how is it that an author manages to select one rather than another fictum candidate among countless candidates? For Zvolenszky (2015a), who is a realist, Creationism is the only realist doctrine that manages to face the epistemological problem Kripke (1980) raised consisting in finding both a historical connection and a suitable mode of introduction for a name to refer to a fictum.

  5. 5.

    Voltolini (2006). For a more radical critique on this concern see Everett (2013:131–2), who holds instead (wrongly, I think: cf. fn.28) that our notion of a fictum involves that such an entity does not exist, thus supporting an antirealist intuition on these matters.

  6. 6.

    Cf. Yagisawa (2001).

  7. 7.

    Curiously enough, Meinong himself seemingly was of this idea in the first 1902 edition of his (1983). At the time of the second 1910 edition, however, he had probably changed his mind, by holding a supervenience claim that makes an assuming (or make-believe) practice to be ontologically generative. Cf. Kroon (1992).

  8. 8.

    Cf. Van Inwagen (1977). See also his (2000, 2003).

  9. 9.

    For an attempt at going in this direction, cf. Zvolenszky (2015b: 182).

  10. 10.

    For a similar move aimed at blocking the inference from Fictional Creationism to Mythical Creationism, the theory according to which in the overall ontological domain there also are mythological entities often not recognised as such even by their creators, cf. Goodman (2014).

  11. 11.

    Certainly, on this respect things might change. We would then have an oneiric entity. If we had something like oneiric works, just as we have fictional works, this would be a sign that a public reflexive stance in favour of oneiric entities has occurred.

  12. 12.

    As a result, even if one managed to independently show (as I incidentally believe it is hard to do: Voltolini 2018) that VA’s (a) is false (as many people nowadays hold: Azzouni (2010), Crane (2013), Everett (2013), Sainsbury and Tye (2012)), this would be of no help for the anticreationist.

  13. 13.

    Notoriously, the easiest way for a realist to solve the problem of indeterminate ficta, namely, appealing to groups as fictional characters such that according to the relevant fiction it is indeterminate how many individuals they comprise (cf. Parsons 1980:191), does not work. For suppose that the following sentence (7) continued by saying “…yet just some of such dwarves appear in many other battles LOTR focuses on”. It is unclear how appealing to groups would enable a realist to deal with this continuation. For it is unclear whether it would involve the same subgroup or different ones. Analogous problems may be raised by a creationist appeal to similar plural entities like pluralities or sets.

  14. 14.

    This specification helps Kroon in ruling out a possible creationist reply (that may however be affected by the problem raised in fn. 13) that the relevant existentially quantified sentences are ontologically committal, since they concern either pluralities or sets to which properties are predicated collectively.

  15. 15.

    In this case, which for some involves a mere semantic indeterminacy (the description of the make-believe world is conceptually indeterminate) the make-believe practice undetermines the creation of different indeterminate ficta (one and the same set of properties may not be make-believedly identical with just one individual). In other perhaps more radical cases, which involve a metaphysical indeterminacy (the make-believe world is indeterminate as to whether one individual is the same as another individual) the practice has not even a start, for in the make-believe world there is no (typically concrete) individual the set may be makebelievedly identical with. Cf. a version of Robert Stevenson’s tale according to which it were indeterminate whether Dr. Jekyll is identical with Mr. Hyde.

  16. 16.

    Cf. Kroon (2015: 166).

  17. 17.

    For similar cardinality problems affecting ficta, cf. Everett (2013), Nolan and Sandgren (2014).

  18. 18.

    Cf. Everett (2013: 226). To my mind (Voltolini 2015a), the problems other similar bridge principles Everett appeals to arise for ficta can be dealt with in a similar way.

  19. 19.

    Either in a semantic or in a metaphysical sense. Cf. fn.15.

  20. 20.

    For examples of such those arguments cf. e.g. Thomasson (1999), Voltolini (2006).

  21. 21.

    For this idea cf. Voltolini 2006.

  22. 22.

    Cf. Kroon (2015: 170fn.29).

  23. 23.

    Pace Everett (2005, 2013) and Howell (2011). Cf. Kroon (2015: 165–6).

  24. 24.

    As Zalta (1988: 4, 127–8) suggested.

  25. 25.

    Cf. Frege (1997: 370–3).

  26. 26.

    Cf. Brock et al. (2013).

  27. 27.

    Clearly enough, this conceptual truth must not be transparent to people involved with make-believe practices. But this is not particularly astonishing. As Wittgenstein (2009)4 stressed, grammatical propositions, i.e., what fix the rule of use of certain expressions hence their meanings viz. the concepts they express, are to be shown to the community members that abide by them.

  28. 28.

    Pace Everett (2013: 131–2), that our notion of a fictum involves the fact that a fictum does not exist is clearly accountable by creationists as meaning that a fictum is not spatiotemporal.

  29. 29.

    In this respect, my account bears some similarities with Manning’s approach, which claims that “we must correlate fictional objects with the specific features through which their native works represent them” (2014: 21). Yet Manning frames this claim within traditional creationist accounts of ficta generation, which, as he admits, explain our realist intuitions about ficta that however occur independently of whether a realist or antirealist theory about ficta is correct (2014: 21–2).

  30. 30.

    For Fara Graff (2011), this amounts to the difference between being called N and being called ‘N’.

  31. 31.

    Cf. Deutsch (1991: 222–3). Deutsch appeals to the socalled principle of poetic license (ibid.: 211) that reminds of the Meinongian object-abstraction principle Meinong (1983) labeled the principle of the Freedom of Assumption.

  32. 32.

    Cf. Brock (2010: 355–62). I have deliberately changed Brock’s examples in order not to get into the controversy involving the number of immigrant ficta, as Brock instead does. For that controversy may be accounted for differently according to one’s theory on crossfictional identity. For a rejection of Brock’s use of his own examples cf. Friedell (2016).

  33. 33.

    Cf. again Brock (2010: 355–62). On the last point see also Zvolenszky (2015b: 181–3) and Brock himself (2018); for a moderate view that distinguishes between intentional creation and nonintentional production of a fictum. cf. Cray (2017). Again, I have changed Brock’s example, for it implausibly appeals to a storyteller antirealist philosophical beliefs, which may be inert as regards a nonphilosophical practice of storytelling.

  34. 34.

    This is not to deny that a general fictum may encompass certain particular ficta. Cf. Voltolini (2006, 2012).

  35. 35.

    Cf. Brock et al. (2013: 72).

  36. 36.

    As Brock (2010: 343) holds contra Deutsch (1991).

  37. 37.

    This paper has been presented at the conferences The Roots of Fiction, University of Macau, December 5–6 2015, Macau; BSA Conference on Fictional Characters, University of Southampton, December 15–16, 2015 Southampton; Political Communities. Normativity and the Metaphysics of politics July 2–3, 2019, University of Udine, Udine. I thank all the participants for their useful remarks. I also thank Catherine Abell, Fred Kroon and Elisa Paganini for their insightful comments to previous version of the paper.

References

  • Azzouni, J. (2010). Talking about nothing: Numbers, hallucinations, and fictions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Berto, F. (2013). Existence as a real property. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Braun, D. (2005). Empty names, fictional names, mythical names. Noûs, 39, 596–631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brock, S. (2010). The creationist fiction: The case against creationism about fictional characters. Philosophical Review, 119, 337–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brock, S. (2018). A recalcitrant problem for abstract creationism. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 76, 93–98.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brock, S., Maslen, C., & Ngai, J. (2013). A puzzle about fictional characters. In C. Barbero et al. (Eds.), From fictionalism to realism: Fictional and other social entities (pp. 63–86). Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castañeda, H.-N. (1989). Thinking, language, and experience. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2013). The objects of thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cray, W. (2017). Abstract generationism: A response to Friedell. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 75, 289–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deutsch, H. (1991). The creation problem. Topoi, 10, 209–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, G. (1982). The varieties of reference. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Everett, A. (2005). Against fictional realism. Journal of Philosophy, 102, 624–649.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Everett, A. (2013). The nonexistent. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fara Graff, D. (2011). You can call me ‘stupid’, ... just don’t call me stupid. Analysis, 71, 492–501.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1997). The thought. In M. Beaney (Ed.), The Frege reader (pp. 325–345). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedell, D. (2016). Abstract creationism and authorial intention. Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 74, 129–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, J. (2004). A defense of creationism in fiction. Grazer Philosophische Studien, 67, 131–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, J. (2014). Creatures of fiction, objects of myth. Analysis, 74, 35–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Howell, R. (2011). Fictional realism and its discontents. In F. Lihoreau (Ed.), Truth in fiction (pp. 153–202). Frankfurt: Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingarden, R. (1973). The literary work of art. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (2011). Vacuous names and fictional entities. In Philosophical troubles: Collected papers (Vol. 1, pp. 52–74). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (2013). Reference and existence. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kroon, F. (1992). Was Meinong only pretending? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, 499–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kroon, F. (2011). The fiction of creationism. In F. Lihoreau (Ed.), Truth in fiction (pp. 203–222). Ontos: Frankfurt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kroon, F. (2013). The social character of fictional entities. In C. Barbero et al. (Eds.), From fictionalism to realism: Fictional and other social entities (pp. 87–110). Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kroon, F. (2015). Creationism and the problem of indiscernible fictional objects. In S. Brock & A. Everett (Eds.), Fictional objects (pp. 139–171). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1983). Truth in fiction. In Philosophical papers I. (pp. 261–280). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manning, L. (2014). Real representation of fictional objects. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism, 72, 13–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meinong, A. (1983). On assumptions. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nolan, D., & Sandgren, A. (2014). Creationism and cardinality. Analysis, 74, 615–622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parsons, T. (1980). Nonexistent objects. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Predelli, S. (2002). ‘Holmes’ and Holmes. A millian analysis of names from fiction. Dialectica, 56, 261–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Priest, G. (2016)2. Towards non-being: The logic and metaphysics of intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sainsbury, M. R. (2010). Fiction and fictionalism. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sainsbury, M. R., & Tye, M. (2012). Seven puzzles of thought and how to solve them. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (1987). Existence. Philosophical Perspectives, 1, 49–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, N. (1998). Nonexistence. Noûs, 32, 277–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (1996). Language-created language-independent entities. Philosophical Topics, 24, 149–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer, S. (2003). The things we mean. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1969). Speech acts. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1979). The logical status of fictional discourse. In P. A. French et al. (Eds.), Contemporary perspectives in the philosophy of language (pp. 233–243). Minneapolis: University of Minneapolis Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1995). The construction of social reality. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. L. (1999). Fiction and metaphysics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. L. (2003a). Fictional characters and literary practices. British Journal of Aesthetics, 43, 138–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. L. (2003b). Speaking of fictional characters. Dialectica, 57, 205–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1977). Creatures of fiction. American Philosophical Quarterly, 14, 299–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (2000). Quantification and fictional discourse. In A. Everett & T. Hofweber (Eds.), Empty names, fiction and the puzzles of non-existence (pp. 235–247). Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (2003). Existence, ontological commitment, and fictional entities. In M. J. Loux & D. W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 131–157). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltolini, A. (2006). How Ficta follow fiction. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Voltolini, A. (2009). The seven consequences of creationism. Metaphysica, 10, 27–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Voltolini, A. (2012). Crossworks ‘identity’ and intrawork∗ identity of a fictional character. Revue internationale de philosophie, 66, 561–576.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltolini, A. (2015a). Anthony Everett, The nonexistent. Dialectica, 69, 611–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Voltolini, A. (2015b). A suitable metaphysics for fictional entities. In S. Brock & A. Everett (Eds.), Fictional characters (pp. 129–146). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltolini, A. (2018). Can one refer to and quantify over nonexistent objects of hallucination? In P. Stalmaszczyk (Ed.), Objects of inquiry in philosophy of language and linguistics (pp. 97–115). Berlin: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, K. L. (1990). Mimesis as make-believe. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (2009)4. Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yagisawa, T. (2001). Against creationism in fiction. Philosophical Perspectives, 15, 153–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. N. (1983). Abstract objects. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. N. (1988). Intensional logic and the metaphysics of intentionality. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zvolenszky, Z. (2015a). An argument for authorial creation. Organon F, 22, 461–487.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zvolenszky, Z. (2015b). Inadvertent creation and fictional characters. Organon F, 22(Suppl), 169–184.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This paper has been presented at the conferences The Roots of Fiction, University of Macau, December 5–6 2015, Macau; BSA Conference on Fictional Characters, University of Southampton, December 15–16, 2015 Southampton; Political Communities. Normativity and the Metaphysics of politics July 2–3, 2019, University of Udine, Udine. I thank all the participants for their useful remarks. I also thank Catherine Abell, Fred Kroon and Elisa Paganini for their insightful comments to previous version of the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alberto Voltolini .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Voltolini, A. (2020). How to Vindicate (Fictional) Creationism. In: Falguera, J.L., Martínez-Vidal, C. (eds) Abstract Objects. Synthese Library, vol 422. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-38242-1_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics