Skip to main content

Statistical Inference

Handbook of Cliometrics
  • 171 Accesses

Abstract

Statistical and, subsequently, econometric inferences have not undergone a cumulative, progressive process. We have seen instead the emergence of a number of different views, which have often been confused with each other in textbook literature on the subject. It therefore makes sense to approach the issue from a historical-scientific angle rather than a systematic one. We intend, using the extraordinarily complex development as a basis, to give a historical overview of the emergence of concepts that are of particular importance from the point of view of cliometrics. We shall start by describing the beginnings of modern probability theory, along with its connection with other statistical approaches. The following overview covers the basic principles of the current concepts of inference developed by R. A. Fisher on one hand and by J. Neyman and E. S. Pearson on the other. Neo-Bayesian approaches have meanwhile been developed in parallel, although they were not taken into account during the initial founding phase of econometrics. A “classic” approach was instead adopted in this respect, albeit with an additional difficulty: the taking into account of time. Cliometrics initially followed a Bayesian approach, but this did not finally prevail. Following on from econometrics, a correspondingly classic, inference-based position was adopted. This chapter concludes with a reference to a fundamental critique of the classic position by Rudolf Kalman, which we also find very promising as an inference-related concept for cliometrics. We often quote authors directly, in an effort to portray developments more vividly.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Cf. Birnbaum (1962, 1968, 1977).

  2. 2.

    Original author’s italics.

  3. 3.

    Quoted from DuMouchel (1992, S. 527). The first edition was published in 1954. Cf. Savage (1954).

  4. 4.

    A detailed treatment of the topic of this chapter can be found at Rahlf (1998) and Gigerenzer/Swijtink/Porter/Daston/Beatty/Krüger (1989).

  5. 5.

    Stigler (1986, p. 122).

  6. 6.

    See, for example, Yule (1895, 1896a, b) and Pearson (1898).

  7. 7.

    F. Galton in a letter to K. Pearson of 18 Nov 1893, quoted by Stigler (1986, p. 336). Original author’s italics.

  8. 8.

    Despite criticism, Pearson’s frequency curves soon became part of the standard repertoire of statistics.

  9. 9.

    W. F. R. Weldon in a letter to F. Galton of 27 Jan 1895, quoted by Stigler (1986, p. 337).

  10. 10.

    K. Pearson explicitly rejected the concept of inverse probability, although E. S. Pearson was of the view that he implicitly followed this approach on at least one occasion. Cf. Pearson (1898). “The basic of the approach used here is a little obscure and there seems to be implicit in it the classical concept of inverse probability” (Pearson 1967, p. 347), quoted by Dale (1991, p. 379). Pearson expressed himself most extensively on this issue in his paper The fundamental problem of practical statistics (1920), which has provoked different interpretations up to the present day. While Fisher (1922, p. 311), for example, believed he recognized a proof of Bayes’ theorem in it, Dale (1991, p. 388) considered this as a “totally inaccurate observation.” For further interpretations, cf. ibid., pp. 377–391. According to Stigler (1986, p. 345), Pearson worked on multiple occasions “[…] (implicitly) in a Bayesian framework.”

  11. 11.

    Pearson (1898, p. 1f), quoted by Stigler (1986, p. 304).

  12. 12.

    Cf. ibid., p. 373.

  13. 13.

    Fisher (1922 [1992], p. 13), similar also to Fisher (1959, p. 34). There is in the case of Fisher (1956, p. 9) a (more or less) clear rejection of the Bayesian approach. He emphasized that he was “personally convinced” that “the theory of inverse probability is founded upon an error, and must be wholly rejected.”

  14. 14.

    Fisher (1922 [1992], p. 13). Ambiguities such as these are characteristic of Fisher’s work. According to Geisser (1992, p. 4), Fisher subscribed – until at least 1912 – to approaches based on Bayesian logic. He then (p. 26f) explicitly rejected the validity of Bayes’ theorem. Cf. Barnard (1988) regarding this question.

  15. 15.

    See supporting evidence in Savage (1976, p. 461). In Fisher (1959, p. 32), he emphasized, for example, that no probability of individual events could be established with such a definition.

  16. 16.

    Savage (1976, p. 461) with corresponding supporting evidence. Savage observes in this respect: “Such a notion is hard to formulate mathematically, and indeed Fisher’s concept of probability remained very unclear, which must have contributed to his isolation from many other statistical theorists” (p. 462).

  17. 17.

    Cf. Geisser (1992). Partly ambiguous terms such as “mean,” “standard deviation,” or “correlation coefficient” have remained in use to this day to indicate, in various contexts, either theoretical variables or estimators for these theoretical variables.

  18. 18.

    Cf. Savage (1976, S. 462) with supporting evidence.

  19. 19.

    Ibid., p. 466: “Nobody knows just what they mean […]. In a word, Fisher hopes by means of some process ─ the fiducial argument ─ to arrive at the equivalent of posterior distributions in a Bayesian argument without the introduction of prior distributions […].” We would like to join in with this criticism. As observed by Menges (1972, p. 275): “The fiducial concept considers the results of an observation as indisputable fact in this respect, and as the basis on which to build inference. It can thus do justice, in principle, to the historical character of social phenomena” (original author’s italics), although this also applies to Bayesian logic in our opinion.

  20. 20.

    Such as Pearson’s chi-squared goodness-of-fit test of 1900, Student’s t-test, developed in 1908 and formalized by Fisher, or the F-test applied to the analysis of variance by Fisher.

  21. 21.

    Fisher (1959, p. 41f). Fisher’s failure to include tables of P-values in his famous textbook Statistical Methods for Research Workers (rather than the tables of significance values that he did include) arose from the fact that K. Pearson held the copyright to the former. Cf. Watson (1983, p. 714).

  22. 22.

    Pearson in a paper from 1939 quoted from Lehmann’s comments (1992, p. 68) on Neyman/Pearson (1933) (our italics).

  23. 23.

    Ibid.

  24. 24.

    Lehmann (1992, p. 68). This highly important aspect of the Neyman-Pearson theory is often not taken into account. As Borovcnik (1992, p. 92) rightly points out “[…] a frequency interpretation places too much emphasis on the α-error during testing, while the real trick with this method is to minimise the ß-error.”

  25. 25.

    According to Lehmann (1992, p. 69f).

  26. 26.

    We do not intend to go into the corresponding techniques here but refer instead to textbook literature on the subject.

  27. 27.

    Neyman/Pearson (1933 [1992], p. 74). Kyburg (1985, p. 119) sums up their intention in the observation: “That says nothing about the case before us, but it may make us feel better.”

  28. 28.

    Fisher (1955, S. 71).

  29. 29.

    Cf. Lehmann (1993), for example.

  30. 30.

    Johnstone (1986, p. 6) aptly describes the prevailing approach: “In general, tests of significance in practice follow Neyman formally, but Fisher philosophically. Formally, there is mention of ‘alternative’ hypotheses, errors ‘of the second kind’, and the ‘power’ of the test, which are terms due to Neyman (and his colleague Pearson). But philosophically, the result in a test, e.g. the result that the level of significance P equals 0.049, or that P is less than or equal to 5 %, is interpreted as a measure of evidence, which is the interpretation following Fisher, and denied repeatedly by Neyman.”

  31. 31.

    Ramsey (1931a, b).

  32. 32.

    Keynes (1921, S. 4), quoted by Kyburg/Smokler (1964, p. 9).

  33. 33.

    Cf. de Finetti (1937).

  34. 34.

    De Finetti (1981, p. 657).

  35. 35.

    Jeffreys (1939, p. 8).

  36. 36.

    Ibid., p. 401.

  37. 37.

    Although the hypothesis can still be false in terms of rule 4.

  38. 38.

    Barnard (1947, 1949). For historical development, see Berger/Wolpert (1988, p. 22ff).

  39. 39.

    Birnbaum (1962). Cf. also Bjornstad (1992) on the following. A “standard” work on the subject is that of Berger/Wolpert (1988).

  40. 40.

    Edwards/Lindman/Savage (1963 [1992]). Our intention from here on is to deal only with certain ideas without going into technical detail.

  41. 41.

    Ibid., pp. 534–540.

  42. 42.

    For example, Laplace (1812) and Edgeworth (1884).

  43. 43.

    Ibid., p. 541. This is referred to as “stable estimation.”

  44. 44.

    DuMouchel (1992, p. 521) points out that this approach is closely related to the “reference priors” subsequently proposed by other Bayesians for use in situations where little a priori information is available, which are also acceptable to classical statisticians.

  45. 45.

    Edwards/Lindman/Savage (1963 [1992], p. 546).

  46. 46.

    Bayesian literature does not adopt a uniform position regarding the need for a test theory.

  47. 47.

    DuMouchel (1992, p. 523). Cf. example no. 3 in appendix A3 and also example no. 2 in appendix A4.

  48. 48.

    General reference is made to Hodges (1990) in this respect.

  49. 49.

    The following according to Iversen (1984, p. 31).

  50. 50.

    Ibid.: “This is the way many users of confidence intervals want to interpret a confidence interval, but in classical statistical inference such an interpretation is not possible.”

  51. 51.

    See above, p. 86f.

  52. 52.

    Cf. Stegmüller (1973, p. 32ff, particularly p. 37).

  53. 53.

    Howson (1995, p. 27).

  54. 54.

    See above, p. 99.

  55. 55.

    Lindley (1991, p. 493).

  56. 56.

    Economic theories, from L. Walras to A. Marshall, started out from states of equilibrium, which were adapted, independently of historical context, by the same perpetual motives of human action. The economic laws contained in these theories were timeless.

  57. 57.

    See above, p. 76 f.

  58. 58.

    One of the few exceptions, who assigned independent significance to the trend, was S. Kuznets. See Kuznets (1930a, b) in particular.

  59. 59.

    Even Tinbergen came to recognize that he “did not understand the role of the shocks as well as Frisch did” (Tinbergen in Magnus/Morgan (1987, p. 125)).

  60. 60.

    The separation between the role of the mechanism and that of the shock was of great importance for the development of econometrics, even though Tinbergen regarded it critically in retrospect: “[…] I think that what interested economics most was not the shocks but the mechanism generating endogenous cycles, and it might very well be that we have overestimated the role of the mechanism. Maybe the shocks were really much more important. This problem was never solved, because the War came along and after the War we were not interested in business cycles anymore” (Tinbergen in Magnus/Morgan (1987, p. 125)).

  61. 61.

    Cf. Kuznets (1934).

  62. 62.

    See Epstein (1987, p. 75 note 39), Mirowski (1989, p. 234), and above all Boumans (1993). Even the statistician G. U. Yule, who was particularly involved in research in the field of time series analysis and its potential applications in economics, began his academic career in the study of electrical waves.

  63. 63.

    Quoted from Mirowski (1991, p. 152). Frisch and Koopmans applied matrix calculus, which was being widely disseminated in physics in the mid-1920s, in the context of multiple regression analysis, to the field of econometrics, thereby making it more difficult for economists to comprehend the texts concerned. Cf. Mirowski (1989, p. 231).

  64. 64.

    Research nevertheless still continued to take place in the “old” tradition, as econometrics began to develop. See, for example, Hotelling (1934), Schultz (1934), Greenstein (1935), and Regan (1936). Even the method of moving averages was still being recommended by Sasuly (1936) in this context.

  65. 65.

    Keuzenkamp/Magnus (1995, p. 18).

  66. 66.

    Heckman (1992, p. 881) also poses the question in this context, in criticism addressed to Morgan (1990): “Why was the Neyman-Pearson theory adopted as the paradigm of statistical inference in econometrics, and why were rival theories by Ronald Fisher and Harold Jeffreys less successful?”.

  67. 67.

    Haavelmo (1994, p. 75).

  68. 68.

    Haavelmo (1944, pp. 13, 22f, 24).

  69. 69.

    Heckman (1992, p. 882). He gives reasons for Morgan’s overestimation of Haavelmo’s approach – rightly in our opinion – with the view, which can be traced back to the influence of Hendry, that these problems are generally solvable in the context of the Neyman-Pearson approach. This overestimation is also picked up by Malinvaud (1991, p. 635 need citation) and Zellner (1992, p. 220 need citation. Only Zellner 1971 is listed in references).

  70. 70.

    See, for example, Sims (1980).

  71. 71.

    They were also subject to the same statistical limitations, such as stationarity and linearity.

  72. 72.

    Zellner (1971, p. 11).

  73. 73.

    See references in Rahlf (1998).

  74. 74.

    Leamer (1994, p. ix).

  75. 75.

    Keuzenkamp (1995, p. 243) therefore uses, for Hendry’s approach, the more apposite term “diagnostic checks” rather than “diagnostic tests.”

  76. 76.

    Cf. Usher (1949, p. 148 and p. 155, note 29).

  77. 77.

    Fogel (1995, S. 49): “The leading history journals, even in economic history, initially refused to accept articles with complex tables and even after such articles began to be accepted, equations were absolutely forbidden.”

  78. 78.

    Floud (1991, p. 452.

  79. 79.

    Fogel/Elton (1983, S. 2), quoted by Floud(1991, p. 452.

  80. 80.

    See above, p. 5.

  81. 81.

    See also Fogel (1995, p. 52) on this subject: “By the early 1980s cliometric methods were so firmly established in certain fields of history that no scholar in these fields could afford to neglect them” (our italics).

  82. 82.

    This is supported not least by the fact that cliometrics did emerge as an independent school of thought because an application for admission by a group of the founding fathers of cliometrics had been rejected by the Econometric Society. Cf. Hughes (1965).

  83. 83.

    Conrad/Meyer (1958). The authors were at the time assistant professors of economics at Harvard. The expressions “starting gun” or “watershed” are therefore justified, since econometric methods were for the first time being applied to historical phenomena without any reference to the present.

  84. 84.

    Cf. Conrad/Meyer (1964).

  85. 85.

    Conrad/Meyer (1957).

  86. 86.

    Cf. Conrad/Meyer (1957, p. 527.

  87. 87.

    They refer here to an example given by Simon (1957) regarding the differing possible influences of the variables of weather, wheat harvest yield, and wheat price.

  88. 88.

    Conrad/Meyer (1957, p. 147.

  89. 89.

    They seek support, in this context, in the line of argument of H. Jeffreys.

  90. 90.

    Conrad/Meyer (1957, p. 544). Specific examples can be found in Conrad/Meyer (1964).

  91. 91.

    Bayesian approaches were not to find fertile ground in the field of econometrics until several years later. It must however be emphasized that the line of argument maintained by Conrad and Meyer contained various terms and concepts (they speak of objective tests and significant differences, before returning to probabilities of hypotheses and a “morass of subjectivism”) that cannot always be clearly differentiated from each other.

  92. 92.

    We rely mainly on Kalman (1982a, b) in this respect. We are therefore not concerned with the application of the so-called Kalman filter to econometrics.

  93. 93.

    Kalman (1982a, p. 19f). Original author’s italics.

  94. 94.

    Ibid., p. 20.

  95. 95.

    This sentence, which was supposed to appear in Kalman (1982c), was deleted at editorial request and included instead in Kalman (1982b, p. 194).

  96. 96.

    Kalman (1982a, p. 23). Linearity and finiteness might be reasonable assumptions for such a system.

  97. 97.

    Kalman (1982b, p. 162). Original author’s italics.

  98. 98.

    Ibid., p. 171.

  99. 99.

    Cf. ibid., p. 172.

  100. 100.

    Kalman (1982a, pp. 26, 27). He describes the calculation of a constant parameter (e.g., in the context of the Phillips curve) as a “conceptual absurdity” (ibid.). Kalman consequently also rejects any causal interpretation. Cf. Kalman (1982b, p. 177), for example.

References

  • Barnard G (1947) The meaning of a significance level. Biometrika 34:179–182

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barnard G (1949) Statistical inference (with discussion). J R Stat Soc B 11:115–149

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnard G (1988) R. A. Fisher – a true Bayesian? Int Stat Rev 55:183–189

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berger J, Wolpert R (1988) The likelihood principle, vol 6, 2nd edn, Lecture notes – monograph series. Institute of Mathematical Statistics, Hayward

    Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum A (1962) On the foundations of statistical inference (with discussion). J Am Stat Assoc 57:269–306

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum A (1968) Likelihood. In: Sills D (ed) International encyclopedia of the social sciences. Macmillan, New York, pp 299–301

    Google Scholar 

  • Birnbaum A (1977) The Neyman-Pearson theory as decision theory and as inference theory: with a criticism of the Lindley-Savage argument for Bayesian theory. Synthese 36:19–49

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bjornstad J (1992) Introduction to Birnbaum (1962) on the foundations of statistical inference. In: Kotz S, Johnson N (eds) Breakthroughs in statistics. Bd. I. Foundations and basic theory. Springer, New York, pp 461–477

    Google Scholar 

  • Borovcnik M (1992) Stochastik im Wechselspiel von Intuitionen und Mathematik. Spektrum Akademischer Verlag, Mannheim

    Google Scholar 

  • Boumans M (1993) Paul Ehrenfest and Jan Tinbergen: a case of limited physics transfer. In: de Marchi N (ed) Non-natural social sciences: reflecting on the enterprise of ‘More heat than light’, vol 25, Supplement to history of political economy. Duke University Press, Durham/London, pp 131–156

    Google Scholar 

  • Burns AF, Mitchell WC (1946) Measuring business cycles. National Bureau of Economic Research, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad A, Meyer J (1957) Economic theory, statistical inference, and economic history. J Econ Hist 17:524–544

    Google Scholar 

  • Conrad A, Meyer J (1958) The economics of slavery in the antebellum south. J Political Econ 66:95–130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Conrad A, Meyer J (eds) (1964) The economics of slavery. Studies in econometric history. Aldine, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Dale A (1991) A history of inverse probability. From Thomas Bayes to Karl Pearson, vol 16, Studies in the history of mathematics and physical sciences. Springer, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • de Finetti B (1937) La prévision: Ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectives. Ann V Institut Henri Poincaré 1:1–68

    Google Scholar 

  • de Finetti B (1981) Wahrscheinlichkeitstheorie. Einführende Synthese mit kritischem Anhang. Oldenbourg, Wien/München

    Google Scholar 

  • DuMouchel W (1992) Introduction to Edwards, Lindman, Savage (1963) Bayesian statistical inference for psychological research. In: Kotz S, Johnson N (eds) Breakthroughs in statistics. Bd. 1. Foundations and basic theory. Springer, New York, pp 519–530

    Google Scholar 

  • Edgeworth FY (1884) The philosophy of chance. Mind 9/34:223–235

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edwards W, Lindman H, Savage L (1963) Bayesian statistical inference for psychological research. Psychol Rev 70:193–242. [Reprinted in: Kotz S, Johnson N (1992) (eds) Breakthroughs in statistics. Bd. 1. Foundations and basic theory, New York]

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Epstein RJ (1987) A history of econometrics. North Holland, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Ezekiel M (1928) Statistical analysis and the law’ of price. Q J Econ 42:199–227

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher R (1922 [1992]) On the mathematical foundations of theoretical statistics. Philos Trans R Soc Lond A 222:309–368. [Reprinted in: Kotz S, Johnson N (1992) (eds) Breakthroughs in statistics. Bd. 1. Foundations and basic theory, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher R (1955) Statistical methods and scientific induction. J R Stat Soc B 17:69–78

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher R (1956) Statistische Methoden für die Wissenschaft, 12. Aufl. Oliver and Boyd, Edinburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher R (1959) Statistical methods and scientific inference. Oliver and Boyd (2nd ed.), London

    Google Scholar 

  • Floud R (1991) Cliometrics. In: Eatwell J, Milgate M, Newman P (eds) The new Palgrave. A dictionary of economics. Bd. 1, 2nd edn. Macmillan, London/New York/Tokyo, p 452–454

    Google Scholar 

  • Fogel R (1995) History with numbers: the American experience. In: Etemad B, Batou J, David T (eds) Pour une histoire économique et sociale internationale. Genéve: Ed. Passé Présent. Genf, p 47–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Fogel R, Elton G (1983) Which road to the past? Two views of history. Yale University Press, New Haven/London

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M, Schwartz A (1991) Alternatives approaches to analyzing economic data. Am Econ Rev 81/1:39–49

    Google Scholar 

  • Frisch R (1931) A method of decomposing an empirical series into its cyclical and progressive components. J Am Stat Assoc (Supplement) 26:73–78

    Google Scholar 

  • Frisch R (1933) Propagation problems and impulse problems in dynamic economics. In: Essays in honour of Gustav Cassel. Allen & Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Galton F (1888) Co-relations and their measurement. Proc R Soc Lond Ser 45:135–145

    Google Scholar 

  • Geisser S (1992) Introduction to Fisher (1922) On the mathematical foundations of theoretical statistics. In: Kotz S, Johnson N (eds) Breakthroughs in statistics. Bd. 1. Foundations and basic theory. Springer, New York, pp 1–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer G, Swijtink T, Porter T, Daston L, Beatty J, Krüger L (1989) The Empire of chance: how probability changed science and everyday life. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge/New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gosset WS (1908) The probable error of a mean. Biometrika 6:1–25

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graunt J (1662 [1939]) Natural and political observations made upon the bills of mortality. Edited with an introduction by Walter F. Willcox, John Hopkins University Press, Baltimore

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenstein B (1935) Periodogram analysis with special application to business failure in the U.S. 1867–1932. Econometrica 3:170–198

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haavelmo T (1944) The probability approach in econometrics. Econometrica 12(Supplement):1–115

    Google Scholar 

  • Haavelmo T (1994) Ökonometrie und Wohlfahrtsstaat. Nobel-Lesung vom 7. Dezember 1989. In: Grüske K-D (Hg) Die Nobelpreisträger der ökonomischen Wissenschaft. Bd. 3. 1989–1993. Wirtschaft und Finanzen, Düsseldorf, pp 71–80

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall L (1925) A moving secular trend and moving integration. J Am Stat Assoc 20:13–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halley E (1693) An estimate of the degrees of mortality of mankind drawn from curious tables of the births and funerals at the city of Breslau; with an attempt to ascertain the price of annuities upon lives. Philos Trans R Soc 17:596–610. Electronic reprint: http://www.pierre-marteau.com/editions/1693-mortality.html

  • Heckman J (1992) Haavelmo and the birth of modern econometrics: a review of the history of econometric ideas by Mary Morgan. J Econ Lit 30:876–886

    Google Scholar 

  • Heckscher E (1939) Quantitative measurement in economic history. Q J Econ 53:167–193

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hendry DF (2001) Econometrics: alchemy or science? 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Hodges J (1990) Can/may Bayesians do pure tests of significance? In: Geisser S, Hodges J, Press S, Zellner A (eds) Bayesian and likelihood methods in statistics and econometrics. Essays in honor of George A. Barnard. Studies in Bayesian econometrics and statistics, vol 7. North Holland Publishing, New York, pp 75–90

    Google Scholar 

  • Hotelling H (1934) Analysis and correlation of time series. Econometrica 2:211

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson C (1995) Theories of probability. Br J Philos Sci 46:1–32

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hughes J (1965) A note in defense of Clio. Explor Entrep Hist 3:154

    Google Scholar 

  • Iversen G (1984) Bayesian statistical inference. Sage Publications, Newbury Park

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffreys H (1939) Theory of probability. The Clarendon Press, London/New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnstone D (1986) Tests of significance in theory and practice (with discussion). Statistician 35:491–504

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kalman R (1982a) Dynamic econometric models: a system-theoretic critique. In: Szegö G (ed) New quantitative techniques for economic analysis. Academic, New York, pp 19–28

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalman R (1982b) Identification from real data. In: Hazewinkel M, Rinnooy Kan A (eds) Current developments in the interface: economics, econometrics and mathematics. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 161–196

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalman R (1982c) Identifiability and problems of model selection in econometrics. In: Hildenbrand W (Hg) Advances in econometrics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kempthorne O (1971) Comment on ‘Applications of statistical inference to physics’. In: Godambe V, Sprott D (eds) Foundations of statistical inference. Holt, Rinehart and Winston of Canada, Toronto, pp 286–287

    Google Scholar 

  • Keuzenkamp H (1995) The econometrics of the Holy Grail – a review of Econometrics: alchemy or science? Essays in econometric methodology. J Econ Surv 9:233–248

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keuzenkamp H, Magnus J (1995) On tests and significance in econometrics. J Econ 67:5–24

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keynes J (1921) A treatise on probability. Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Koopmans T (1941) The logic of econometric business-cycle research. J Political Econ 49:157–181

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuznets S (1928a) On moving correlation of time sequences. J Am Stat Assoc 23:121–136

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuznets S (1928b) On the analysis of time series. J Am Stat Assoc 23:398–410

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuznets S (1929) Random events and cyclical oscillations. J Am Stat Assoc 24:258–275

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuznets S (1930a) Secular movements in production and prices. Houghton Mifflin, Boston/New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuznets S (1930b) Wesen und Bedeutung des Trends. Zur Theorie der säkularen Bewegung. Veröffentlichungen der Frankfurter Gesellschaft für Konjunkturforschung. Bonn, Schroeder

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuznets S (1934) Time series. In: Seligman E, Johnson A (eds) Encyclopedia of the social sciences. Bd. 13. Macmillan, New York, pp 629–636

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyburg H (1985) Logic of statistical reasoning. In: Kotz S, Johnson N (eds) Encyclopedia of statistical sciences. Bd. 5. Wiley, New York, pp 117–122

    Google Scholar 

  • Kyburg H, Smokler H (eds) (1964) Studies in subjective probability. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Laplace P-S (1812) Théorie analytique des probabilités. Courcier, Paris. https://archive.org/details/thorieanalytiqu01laplgoog

  • Leamer EE (1994) Introduction. In: Leamer EE (ed) Sturdy econometrics. Elgar, Aldershot, pp ix–xvi

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehmann E (1992) Introduction to Neyman and Pearson (1933) On the problem of the most efficient tests of statistical hypotheses. In: Kotz S, Johnson N (eds) Breakthroughs in statistics. Bd. 1. Foundations and basic theory. Springer, New York, pp 67–72

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lehmann EL (1993) The Fisher, Neyman-Pearson theories of testing hypotheses: one theory or two. J Am Stat Assoc 88:1242–1249

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindley D (1991) Statistical inference. In: Eatwell J, Milgate M, Newman P (eds) The new Palgrave. A dictionary of economics, vol 4, 2. Aufl. Macmillan, London/New York/Tokyo, pp 490–493

    Google Scholar 

  • Malinvaud E (1991) Review of Morgan, Morgan M (1990) The history of econometric ideas, Economic Journal 101:634–636

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus J, Morgan M (1987) The ET interview: Professor J. Tinbergen. Econ Theory 3:117–142

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marshak J (1950) Statistical inference in economics. In: Koopmans T (ed) Statistical inference in dynamic economic models. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Menges G (1972) Grundriß der Statistik. 1. Theorie, 2nd edn. Westdeutscher Verlag, Opladen

    Google Scholar 

  • Mirowski P (1989) The probabilistic counter revolution, or how stochastic concepts came to neoclassical economic theory. Oxf Econ Pap 41:217–235

    Google Scholar 

  • Mirowski P (1991) The when, the how and the why of mathematical expression in the history of economic analysis. J Econ Perspect 5:145–157

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morgan M (1990) The history of econometric ideas. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Neyman J (1937) Outline of a theory of statistical estimation based on the classical theory of probability. Philos Trans R Soc Lond, Ser A, Math Phys Sci 236/767:333–380

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neyman J, Pearson ES (1928a) On the use and interpretation of certain test criteria for purposes of statistical inference. Part I. Biometrika 20A:175–240

    Google Scholar 

  • Neyman J, Pearson ES (1928b) On the use and interpretation of certain test criteria for purposes of statistical inference. Part II”. Biometrika 20A:263–294

    Google Scholar 

  • Neyman J, Pearson ES (1933) On the problem of the most efficient tests of statistical hypotheses. Philos Trans R Soc Lond, Ser A, containing papers of a mathematical or physical character 231:289–337. [Reprinted in: Kotz S, Johnson N (1992) (eds) Breakthroughs in statistics. Bd. 1. Foundations and basic theory, New York]

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearson K (1894) Contributions to the mathematical theory of evolution. Philos Trans R Soc Lond 85:71–110

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearson K (1895) Contributions to the mathematical theory of evolution. II. Skew variation in homogeneous material. Philos Trans R Soc Lond 186:343–414

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearson K (1898) Mathematical contributions to the theory of evolution: on the law of ancestral heredity. Proc R Soc Lond 62:386–412

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearson K (1920) The fundamental problem of practical statistics. Biometrika 13/1:1–16

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pearson ES (1967) Some reflections on continuity in the development of mathematical statistics, 1885-1920, Biometrica 52:3–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper K (1990) A world of propensities. Thoemmes, Bristol

    Google Scholar 

  • Pratt J (1971) Comment on: ‘probability, statistics and knowledge business’ by O. Kempthorne. In: Godambe V, Sprott D (eds) Foundations of statistical inference. Holt, Rinehart and Winston, Toronto

    Google Scholar 

  • Rahlf T (1998) Deskription und Inferenz Methodologische Konzepte in der Statistik und Ökonometrie, vol 9, Historical social research supplement. Zentrum für Historische Sozialforschung, Köln

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey F (1931a) Truth and probability (1926). In: Braithwaite R (ed) The foundations of mathematics and other logical essays by Frank Plumpton Ramsey. International Library of Psychology, Philosophy and Scientific Method, London. [Reprinted in Kyburg, Smokler (1964)]

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey F (1931b) Further considerations (1928). In: Braithwaite R (ed) The foundations of mathematics and other logical essays by Frank Plumpton Ramsey. International Library of Psychology, Philosophy and Scientific Method, London, pp 199–211

    Google Scholar 

  • Regan F (1936) The admissibility of time series. Econometrica 4:189

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins H (1955) An empirical Bayes approach to statistics. In: Neyman J (ed) Proceedings of the 3rd Berkeley symposium on mathematical and statistical probability, University of California. Statistical Laboratory: University of California Press, vol 1, pp 157–163. [Reprinted in Kotz/Johnson (1992)]

    Google Scholar 

  • Sasuly M (1936) A method of smoothing economic time series by moving averages. Econometrica 4:206

    Google Scholar 

  • Savage L (1954) The foundations of statistics. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Savage L (1976) On rereading R. A. Fisher (with discussion). Ann Stat 4:441–500

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schultz H (1934) Discussion of the question ‘Is the theory of harmonic oscillations useful in the study of business cycles?’. Econometrica 2:189

    Google Scholar 

  • Sims C (1980) Macroeconomics and reality. Econometrica 48:1–48

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon H (1957) Models of man. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Slutzky E (1937) The summation of random causes as the source of cyclic processes. Econometrica 5:105–146 [originally published in Russian 1927]

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmüller W (1973) Personelle und Statistische Wahrscheinlichkeit. Erster Halbband: Personelle Wahrscheinlichkeit und Rationale Entscheidung. Zweiter Halbband. Statistisches Schließen, Statistische Begründung, Statistische Analyse. Probleme und Resultate der Wissenschaftstheorie und Analytischen Philosophie IV. Springer, Berlin/Heidelberg/New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Stigler S (1986) The history of statistics: the measurement of uncertainty before 1900. Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Usher A (1949) The significance of modern empiricism for history and economics. J Econ Hist 9:131–155

    Google Scholar 

  • von Mises R (1951) Wahrscheinlichkeit, Statistik und Wahrheit. Springer, Wien

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wald A (1950) Statistical decision functions. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Watson G (1983) Hypothesis testing. In: Kotz S, Johnson N (eds) Encyclopedia of statistical sciences. Bd. 3. Wiley, New York, pp 712–722

    Google Scholar 

  • Yule GY (1895) On the correlation of total pauperism with proportion of out-relief, I: all ages. Econ J 5:603–611

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yule GU (1896a) Notes on the history of pauperism in England and Wales from 1850, treated by the method of frequency-curves; with an introduction on the method. J R Stat Soc 59/2:318–357

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yule GY (1896b) On the correlation of total pauperism with proportion of out-relief, II: males over sixty-five. Econ J 6:613–623

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yule GY (1927) On a method of investigating the periodicities of disturbed series, with special reference to Wolfer’s sunspot numbers. Philos Trans R Soc A 226(1927):267–298

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zellner A (1971) An introduction to Bayesian statistics in econometrics. Wiley, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Zellner A (1992) Review of Morgan, Morgan M (1990) The history of econometric ideas, Journal of Political Economy 100:218–222

    Google Scholar 

Recommended Reading

  • The best starting point is still Gigerenzer et al. (1989). See Cited Literature. Other helpful overviews are:

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen IB (2005) The triumph of numbers: how counting shaped modern life. W. W. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotz S, Johnson NL (1992) (eds) Breakthroughs in statistics, 1. Foundations and basic theory. 2. Methodology and distribution. Springer series in statistics. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenhard J (2006) Models and statistical inference: the controversy between Fisher and Neyman-Pearson. Br J Philos Sci 57:69–91

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Salsburg D (2001) The lady tasting tea: how Statistics Revolutionized Science in the Twentieth Century. Freeman, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprenger J (2014) Bayesianism vs. frequentism in statistical inference. In: Hájek A, Hitchcock C (eds) Handbook of the philosophy of probability. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sprenger J, Hartmann S (2001) Mathematics and statistics in the social sciences. In: Jarvie IC, Bonilla JZ (eds) The SAGE handbook of the philosophy of social sciences. Sage, London, pp 594–612

    Google Scholar 

  • Stigler SM (1999) Statistics on the table: the history of statistical concepts and methods. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Thomas Rahlf .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2014 Springer-Verlag Berlin Heidelberg

About this entry

Cite this entry

Rahlf, T. (2014). Statistical Inference. In: Diebolt, C., Haupert, M. (eds) Handbook of Cliometrics. Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-40458-0_16-1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-40458-0_16-1

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Berlin, Heidelberg

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-642-40458-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Reference Economics and FinanceReference Module Humanities and Social SciencesReference Module Business, Economics and Social Sciences

Publish with us

Policies and ethics

Chapter history

  1. Latest

    Statistical Inference
    Published:
    05 December 2014

    DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-40458-0_16-2

  2. Original

    Statistical Inference
    Published:
    11 April 2014

    DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-642-40458-0_16-1