Skip to main content
Log in

New problems for defining animal communication in informational terms

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Exactly what makes an interaction between two organisms a case of communication is contentious. Historically, debate has taken place between definitions of communication invoking information transmission vs definitions invoking causal influence. More recently, there has been some convergence on a hybrid definition: invoking (co-adapted) causal influence mediated via the transmission of information. After proposing an understanding of what it means to say that a receiver is causally influenced by the transmission of information, I argue that an information-mediated influence definition overextends to include most, indeed maybe all, co-adapted interactions. This is because the transmission of correlational information is actually a feature of most, if not all, co-adapted interactions. I end by considering whether adding an arbitrariness criterion to an information-mediated influence definition helps. After giving an account of what arbitrariness amounts to, I argue that it swings things too far in the opposite direction: we go from a definition of communication that is too liberal to one that is too restrictive. This is because many signal kinds are not arbitrary. It turns out to be extremely difficult to capture what makes communication unique.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. ‘Informing’ is meant in a loose sense here: as causing a response in a receiver that is adaptive for the receiver, given the state of the world.

  2. Of course, behaviours that are adapted for advertising or accentuating one’s size might be signals. But here we are not dealing with such adaptations: only size as such.

  3. Carazo and Font (2010) also argue for a hybrid definition of communication invoking both (co-adapted) influence and information transmission. However, their reasons are mostly different to those of Scarantino.

  4. It is more or less the same as the notion of correlational information advanced by Shea (2007) and Skyrms (2010). Scarantino (2015) gives a richer and more detailed analysis of this kind of information.

  5. See Stegmann 2013 for an overview.

  6. There is then the further foundational question of what facts make it the case that an utterance has this or that truth-condition. One influential view comes from Grice (1957), and takes the content of utterances to be grounded by the content of mental states. Roughly speaking, my utterance means what it does because of my particular goal in using it; and you understand my utterance by (accurately) inferring my goal in using it.

  7. If leopard alarms did not correlate with the presence of a leopard over the learning period, receivers wouldn’t respond to them by climbing trees.

  8. I hope that elucidating the causal-explanatory role of predictive information in this way might also render the notion of information more palatable for those sceptical of the utility of informational notions in explaining animal communication (e.g. Owren et al. 2010; Rendall et al. 2009).

  9. This is not to say that vervet alarm calls are completely arbitrary, in the sense I am beginning to outline. As Owren et al. (2010) rightly note, the physical form of alarm calls is constrained to some degree. They must allow for detection and localization. Also, they must prime listeners by engaging low-level attention and arousal mechanisms. However, there seems to be no necessary connection between the physical form of a leopard call, on the one hand, and behavioural responses that are adaptive in the presence of leopards as opposed to eagles or snakes, on the other. In other words, there is nothing special about the physical form of leopard calls, qua signals designating leopards, as opposed to that of eagle or snake calls.

  10. This includes the nervous systems of senders and receivers.

  11. In work currently underway with Ron Planer we intend to analyse a counterfactual notion of arbitrariness in considerable detail, separating it from the notion of iconicity (more precisely, a lack thereof). We plan to argue that iconicity is only one way out of a number of different ways arbitrariness can be constrained.

  12. Including an information-mediated influence definition that includes an arbitrariness feature.

  13. I thank an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out to me.

  14. As Carazo and Font (2010, p. 663) highlight, “the function... and information content of a signal are not the same thing, as evinced by the fact that the same effect (e.g. to intimidate a rival) can be achieved by a signal with different informative content (e.g. size, social or residential status).”

References

  • Blackburn, P. L. (2007). The code model of language: A powerful metaphor in linguistic metatheory. Dallas: SIL International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carazo, P., & Font, E. (2010). Putting information back into biological communication. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 23(4), 661–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, N. B., & Halliday, T. R. (1978). Deep croaks and fighting assessment in toads, Bufo Bufo. Nature, 274, 683–685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R., & Krebs, J. R. (1978). Animal signals: Information or manipulation? In J. R. Krebs & N. B. Davies (Eds.), Behavioural ecology: An evolutionary approach (pp. 282–309). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1994). The explanatory role of information. Philosophical transactions: Physical sciences and Engineering, 349(1689), 59–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Darwinian populations and natural selection. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2014). Signs and symbolic behaviour. Biological Theory, 9(1), 78–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, P. (1957). Meaning. The Philosophical Review, 66(3), 377–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harms, W. (2004). Primitive content, translation, and the emergence of meaning in animal communication. In D. K. Oller & U. Griebel (Eds.), Evolution of communication systems: A comparative approach (pp. 31–48). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. (1986). On human nature. In PSA: Proceedings of the biannual meetings of the philosophy of science association (Vol. 2, pp. 3–13).

  • Lewis, S. M., & Cratsley, C. K. (2008). Flash signal evolution, mate choice, and predation in fireflies. Annual Review of Entomology, 53, 293–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, E., & Laurence, S. (1999). Concepts: Core readings. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard-Smith, J., & Harper, D. (1995). Animal signals: Models and terminology. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 177(3), 305–311.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard-Smith, J., & Harper, D. (2003). Animal signals. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1988). Towards a new philosophy of biology: Observations of an evolutionist. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. (2004). Varieties of meaning. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Moller, A., & de Lope, F. (1994). Differential costs of a secondary sexual character: An experimental test of the handicap principle. Evolution, 48(5), 1676–1683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nolan, D. (2005). David Lewis. Chesham: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Owren, M., Rendall, D., & Ryan, M. (2010). Redefining animal signals: Influence versus information in communication. Biology and Philosophy, 25(5), 755–780.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reddy, M. (1979). The conduit metaphor: A case of frame conflict in our language about language. In A. Ortony (Ed.), Metaphor and thought (pp. 284–324). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rendall, D., Owren, M., & Ryan, M. (2009). What do animal signals mean? Animal Behaviour, 78(2), 233–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino, A. (2010). Animal communication between information and influence. Animal Behaviour, 79(6), e1–e5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino, A. (2013). Animal communication as influence-mediated influence. In U. Stegmann (Ed.), Animal communication theory: Information and influence (pp. 63–87). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino, A. (2015). Information as a probabilistic difference maker. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93(3), 419–443.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott-Phillips, T. (2008). Defining biological communication. Journal of Evolutionary Biology, 21(2), 287–395.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth, R., Cheney, D., & Marler, P. (1980). Vervet monkey alarm calls: Semantic communication in a free-ranging primate. Animal Behaviour, 28(4), 1070–1094.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea, N. (2007). Consumers need information: Supplementing teleosemantics with an input condition. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 75(2), 404–435.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms, B. (2010). Signals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann, U. (2013). Animal communication theory: Information and influence. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (2008). Origins of human communication. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Frisch, K. (1967). The dance language and orientation of bees. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Ron Planner, Kim Sterelny, audience members at the 2016 Sydney-ANU philosophy of biology workshop, and two anonymous reviewers for useful feedback. This research is supported by an Australian Government Research Training Program (RTP) Scholarship

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Kalkman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kalkman, D. New problems for defining animal communication in informational terms. Synthese 196, 3319–3336 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1598-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1598-2

Keywords

Navigation