Skip to main content
Log in

Information, influence, and the causal-explanatory role of content in understanding receiver responses

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Sceptics of informational terminology argue that by attributing content to signals, we fail to address nonhuman animal communication on its own terms. Primarily, we ignore that communication is sender driven: i.e. driven by the intrinsic physical properties of signals, themselves the result of selection pressures acting on signals to influence receivers in ways beneficial for senders. In contrast, information proponents argue that this ignores the degree to which communication is, in fact, receiver driven. The latter argue that an exclusive focus on the intrinsic mechanical properties of signals cannot explain why receivers respond as they do. This is because receivers are not prisoners of sender influence. They possess response flexibility, and so we can only explain why receivers respond to signals as they do by positing that receivers ‘derive information’ from signals. I argue that, while basically true, this response flexibility can take one of two forms depending on the causal-explanatory role of information in understanding the response of the receiver: diachronic, on the one hand; and synchronic, on the other. In species with diachronic response flexibility only, information is derived by receivers from signals in a minimal sense. In such cases, information is an ultimate explanatory construct: one underpinned by historical facts at the population level. Alternatively, in species with synchronic response flexibility, information is derived by receivers from signals in a richer sense. Here, information is a proximate explanatory construct: one underpinned by cognitive-mechanistic facts at the level of the individual organism. Without recognising the different ways information can be derived from signals, and the different causal-explanatory roles (ultimate vs proximate) information can play in understanding alternate kinds of receiver flexibility (diachronic vs synchronic), proponents of information leave themselves open to the charge of anthropomorphising some signalling systems.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Particularly when fitness interests of senders and receivers diverge.

  2. The ingenious study tested endurance capacity by encouraging lizards to run around specially engineered racetracks.

  3. It must be noted that Shea (2007) employs his notion of correlational information within a teleosemantic view of content.

  4. Although, in reality, it is likely to carry significantly more information.

  5. Another kind is ‘input-oriented’ teleosemantics (Neander 2013). Shea’s (2007) teleosemantic theory is output-based, but it includes the novel requirement that a signal must correlate with its content.

  6. Dretske (1994) calls this type of explanation a ‘structuring’ explanation.

  7. Indeed, when it comes to lizard push-ups, signal honesty is enforced by the target receiver, as opposed to being ensured by cost paid up-front. As a result, we should expect some amount of dishonest ‘bluffing’ to occur (Bruner et al. 2017).

  8. Although here conventional coordination is not the result of rational processes, as opposed to the law of effect.

  9. In the opinion of this author, the issue of arbitrariness is extremely murky. Future work, currently in progress with Ron Planer, will put forward a general account of arbitrariness along the lines suggested here, and identify a class of recurring reasons why arbitrariness is commonly constrained across different kinds of communication systems.

  10. Although Wheeler and Fischer (2012, pp. 196–197) note “the idea that functional referential signals require greater cognitive complexity and provide a clearer link to human language than do other types of animal signals remains pervasive in the animal communication literature”.

  11. Although see Scarantino (2013) for an alternative proposal.

  12. There is an important caveat. Even if the receiver’s cognitive mechanism for learning the signal-world correlation is more sophisticated it would still not follow that the signal would be anything like a word. If, for example, the receiver learns what the signal correlates with via a form of social learning, such as by observing the responses of other animals, this would not make the signal word-like. This is because what is being learned, however cleverly or not, is just a very specific signal-world association. And, as Deacon (1997) pointed out, word meaning is more complicated than a large list of signal-world associations.

  13. For debate about the continuing importance of the functional reference paradigm, see Wheeler and Fischer (2012) and the subsequent exchange between Scarantino and Clay (2015) and Wheeler and Fischer (2015).

  14. Vervet infants initially give alarm calls to warthogs and pigeons that pose no danger to them. But such mistakes are not random: infants ‘over-extend’ leopard alarm calls to terrestrial mammals and eagle alarms to birds. From birth then, vervets divide predators from non-predators, and within the predator category they divide terrestrial carnivores from aerial predators (Seyfarth and Cheney 2010).

  15. This is not to say that signal production in old-world monkeys is inflexible and insensitive to context. Senders do not have to learn the circumstances under which a signal is to be produced, but nevertheless they often must take into account contextual features of the situation to determine whether or not to signal, at any particular time. Audience effects are a good example: senders are sensitive to conspecifics, and adjust when they produce signals based on their presence or absence (Seyfarth and Cheney 2010; Fitch and Zuberbuhler 2013).

  16. It was argued previously that the idea of functional reference is a red herring when it comes to the psychological sophistication of animal communication. This was because the context-specific nature of signals thought to ‘refer’ in fact rules out the likelihood that response mechanisms are sophisticated or language-like. The view being considered now is that vervet communication, for example, is of interest because signals correlate reliably with distal states. This seems like a contradiction. However, note that the mechanisms which are sensitive to the tight signal-world relation in the case of vervets are ontogenetic (on the consumption side of communication), while the functional reference paradigm would characterise hard-wired response mechanisms as possessing some interesting kind of sophistication. The implication is that if Pavlovian conditioning in some animals is representational, as will soon be discussed, then functional reference might be significant for the issue of human-nonhuman communicative continuity if it restricts itself to context-specific signals that are learnt, as opposed to context-specific signals that are developmentally canalized.

  17. All are influenced by Grice’s (1957) analysis of non-natural meaning. Tomasello and especially Scott-Phillips also take inspiration from Sperber and Wilsons (1986) ‘Post-Gricean’ explanation of human communication which stresses the necessity of high-level recursive mindreading.

  18. As noted in the introduction, information proponents take the existence of communication as evidence for signals being honest, unlike information sceptics who emphasise sensory manipulation.

References

  • Allen C, Hauser M (1991) Concept attribution in nonhuman animals: theoretical and methodological problems in ascribing complex mental processes. Philos Sci 58:221–240

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Artiga M (2014) Signalling without cooperation. Biol Philos 29:357–378

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bermudez J (2003) Thinking without words. OUP, New York

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bruner J, Brusse C, Kalkman D (2017) Cost, expenditure and vulnerability. Biol Philos 31:357–375

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheney D, Seyfarth R (1988) Assessment of meaning and the detection of unreliable signals by vervet monkeys. Anim Behav 36:477–486

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R, Krebs JR (1978) Animal signals: information or manipulation? In: Krebs JR, Davies NB (eds) Behavioural ecology: an evolutionary approach. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 282–309

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon T (1997) The symbolic species: the coevolution of language and the brain. W.W. Norton and Co, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1981) Knowledge and the flow of information. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (1994) The explanatory role of information. Philoso Trans Phys Sci Eng 349:59–70

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans C, Evans L, Marler P (1993) On the meaning of alarm-calls: functional reference in an avian vocal system. Anim Behav 46:23–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fitch WT (2010) The evolution of language. CUP, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fitch WT, Hauser M (2003) Unpacking honesty: vertebrate vocal production and the evolution of acoustic signals. In: Simmons A, Fay R, Popper A (eds) Animal communication. Springer, New York, pp 65–137

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitch WT, Zuberbuhler K (2013) Primate precursors to human language: beyond discontinuity. In: Alternmuller E, Schmidt S, Zimmermann E (eds) The evolution of emotional communication: from sounds in nonhuman mammals to speech and music in man. OUP, Oxford, pp 26–48

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J (1975) The language of thought. HUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Gallistel CR (2003) Conditioning from an information processing perspective. Behav Process 62:89–101

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grafen A (1999) Biological signals as handicaps. J Theor Biol 144:517–546

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice P (1957) Meaning. Philos Rev 66:377–388

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hauser M (1996) The evolution of communication. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Holland P (2008) Cognitive versus stimulus-response theories of learning. Learn Behav 6:227–241

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leal M (1999) Honest signalling during prey–predator interactions in the lizard Anolis cristatellus. Anim Behav 58:521–526

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manser M (2013) Semantic communication in vervet monkeys and other animals. Anim Behav 86:491–496

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maynard-Smith J, Harper D (2003) Animal signals. OUP, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (1989) Biosemantics. J Philos 66:281–297

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (2007) An input condition for teleosemantics? Reply to Shea (and Godfrey-Smith). Philos Phenomenol Res 75:436–454

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore R (2017) Gricean communication and cognitive development. Philos Q 67:303–326

    Google Scholar 

  • Neander K (2013) Toward an informational teleosemantics. In: Ryder D, Kingsbury J, Williford K (eds) Millikan and her critics. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 21–40

    Google Scholar 

  • Owren M, Rendall D (1997) An affect-conditioning model of nonhuman primate vocal signaling. In: Owings D, Beecheer M, Thomson N (eds) Perspectives in ethology: volume 12 communication. Plenum, New York, pp 359–390

    Google Scholar 

  • Owren M, Rendall D, Ryan M (2010) Redefining animal signal: influence versus information in communication. Biol Philos 25:755–780

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pereira M, Macedonia J (1991) Ringtailed lemur anti-predator calls denote predator class, not response urgency. Anim Behav 41:543–544

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rendall D, Owren M (2013) Communication without meaning or information: abandoning language-based and informational constructs in animal communication theory. In: Stegmann U (ed) Animal communication theory: information and influence. CUP, Cambridge, pp 151–188

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Resocrla R (1988) Pavlovian conditioning: it’s not what you think it is. Am Psychol 43:151–160

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino A (2013) Rethinking functional reference. Philos Sci 80:1006–1018

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino A (2015) Information as a probabilistic difference maker. Australas J Philos 93:419–443

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scarantino A, Clay Z (2015) Contextually variable signals can be functionally referential. Anim Behav 100:e1–e8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott-Phillips T (2015) Speaking our minds: why human communication is different, and how language evolved to make it special. Pelgrave Macmillan, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searcy W, Nowicki S (2005) The evolution of animal communication: reliability and deception in signaling systems. PUP, New Jersey

    Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth R, Cheney D (2003) Signalers and receivers in animal communication. Annu Rev Psychol 54:145–173

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth R, Cheney D (2010) Production, usage, and comprehension in animal vocalizations. Brain Lang 115:92–100

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth R, Cheney D (2017) The origin of meaning in animal signals. Anim Behav 128:339–346

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth R, Cheney D, Marler P (1980) Vervet monkey alarm calls: semantic communication in a free-ranging primate. Anim Behav 28:1070–1094

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth R, Cheney D, Bergman T, Fischer J, Zuberbuhler K, Hammerschmidt K (2010) The central importance of information in studies of animal communication. Anim Behav 80:3–8

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shannon C (1948) A mathematical theory of communication. Bell Systems Tech J 27:379–423

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2007) Consumers need information: supplementing teleosemantics with an input condition. Philos Phenomenol Res 75:404–435

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shettleworth S (2010) Cognition, evolution and behavior. OUP, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Skyrms B (2010) Signals. OUP, Oxford

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber D, Wilson D (1986) Relevance: communication and cognition. HUP, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann U (2009) A consumer-based teleosemantics for animal signals. Philos Sci 76:864–875

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann U (2013) Animal communication theory: information and influence. CUP, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stegmann U (2014) Prospects for probabilistic theories of natural information. Erkenn 80:869–893

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2003) Thought in a hostile world: the evolution of human cognition. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (2008) Origins of human communication. MIT, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (2014) A natural history of human thinking. HUP, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler B, Fischer J (2012) Functionally referential signals: a promising paradigm whose time has passed. Evolut Anthropol 21:195–205

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler B, Fischer J (2015) The blurred boundaries of functional reference: a response to Scarantino & Clay. Anim Behav 100:e9–e13

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson EO (1971) The insect societies. Belknap Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Zuberbuhler K (2005) The phylogenetic roots of language: evidence from primate communication and cognition. Curr Dir Psychol Sci 14:126–130

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zuberbuhler K, Cheney D, Seyfarth R (1999) Conceptual semantics in a nonhuman primate. J Comp Psychol 113:33–42

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to Ron Planer, Kim Sterelny, Stephen Mann, and two anonymous reviewers. This research is supported by an Australian Government Research Training Program (RTP) Scholarship.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Kalkman.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kalkman, D. Information, influence, and the causal-explanatory role of content in understanding receiver responses. Biol Philos 32, 1127–1150 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-017-9596-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-017-9596-9

Keywords

Navigation