Skip to main content
Log in

Perceptual presence: an attentional account

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

It is a distinctive mark of normal conscious perception that perceived objects are experienced as actually present in one’s surroundings. The aim of this paper is to offer a phenomenologically accurate and empirically plausible account of the cognitive underpinning of this feature of conscious perception, which I shall call perceptual presence (PP). The paper begins with a preliminary characterization of (PP). I then consider and criticize the seminal account of (PP) proposed by Mohan Matthen. In the remainder of the paper I put forward and defend my own attentional account. I first outline a simple version of the view by focusing on vision and then extend it to audition. After discussing the case of depersonalization, I consider some objections. The last objection, in particular, will motivate a refinement of the attentional account for the visual case. The paper ends with some remarks mainly about the specificity of the visual case vis-à-vis the auditory one.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This term is also employed by Dokic (2012: p. 193), who in the same paper also talks of “feeling of presence”. Elsewhere Dokic uses the term “feeling of reality” (see Dokic and Martin 2012; Dokic 2016). Matthen (2010) talks of “feeling of presence” and Farkas (2013) of “sense of reality”. Here is why I prefer the label “perceptual presence”. First, it is better to avoid terms like “sense” and “feeling”, for they seem to imply, and surely suggest, that the nature of the feature in question is phenomenological. That this is the case, however, is an open question. (See further below in this section for this.) Second, that feature seems better described in terms of “presence” than of “reality”. If I look at a tennis match on the TV, I surely experience the players as real, though I don’t experience them as “really there” in the same sense in which my computer keyboard is “really there”, to stick to Matthen’s example. (Thanks to Enrico Terrone, who made me appreciate this point.) Since theoretically neutral and phenomenologically more accurate, the term “perceptual presence” is thus a better candidate.

  2. The same kind of contrast can be drawn between perception and imagery, which is arguably not identical with imagination (on this point, see Nanay 2016: pp. 66–67). As this difference has no bearing on the arguments presented in this paper, I shall simply ignore it and talk in terms of imagination throughout.

  3. This last notion is admittedly vague. Discussion in Sect. 6 will help to qualify it.

  4. As we saw, imagination is another usual contrast case to perception when it comes to (PP). So why not draw further on this contrast? The reason is that the case of imagination is so intricate that no even remotely satisfying treatment could be aimed at on this occasion. To highlight the complications, let me just name two of them. First, as already noted (see footnote 2), both imagination and imagery can be contrasted with perception. So one would need to clarify the difference between them and, ideally, deal with both. Second, though hallucinations typically display (PP), some have argued that they are just a specific kind of imagination (Allen 2015) or imagery (Nanay 2016). If one of these views is true, it is thus simply false that imagination or imagery is, as such, a contrast case when it comes to (PP). As these are arguably not the only troubles awaiting an appropriate examination of imagination and/or imagery, I shall leave this issue to further work.

  5. Farkas (2013) and Matthen (2010; see also Dokic 2012: pp. 398–399) provide arguments against (i) and (ii), respectively. Matthen (2010), Dokic (2012) and Dokic and Martin (2012) defend (iv).

  6. Husserl (1997 [1907]: §5) already makes this point by appealing to resisted hallucinations.

  7. Matthen’s proposal is similar, see (2010: pp. 114–115).

  8. Matthen’s most detailed treatment of the “feeling of presence” is to be found in his (2010), on which I shall focus. However, see also Matthen (2005, especially: pp. 304–307).

  9. Two things to note here. First, the labels “motion-guiding vision” and “descriptive vision” are not of common use in the literature, as far as I know. Here, I adopt Matthen’s terminology for ease of discussion. Second, Matthen stresses that his argument is committed only to the functional independence of the two visual systems, and not also to their neuroanatomical segregation. Though in my paper I sometimes use the more current labels “ventral” and “dorsal”, which refer to specific regions of the brain, I do not assume that no relevant neuroanatomical connection between the two systems exists, nor that Matthen’s proposal requires this to be the case.

  10. Studies on subjects with normal vision show that “invisible” objects that remain undetected by the ventral stream can elicit responses in the dorsal stream (see Fang and He 2005). As no awareness whatsoever of such objects is reported, activation of the dorsal stream can occur (as in blindsight) in the complete absence of conscious perceptual experience and, a fortiori, of (PP).

  11. For instance, VHs in Parkinson disease correlate with degraded visual input due to reduced contrast and color discrimination (see Diederich et al. 2005).

  12. The notion of “incorrect proto-object” employed by Collerton is somewhat ambiguous. A proto-object may be incorrect because it misrepresents an item in the environment, or because no suitable item is there at all. Given that Collerton’s model is about hallucinations, the second option is here the pertinent one. However, there might as well be visual illusions caused by a malfunction of object-based attention. In such cases, if they exist, the notion should then be read in the first sense. (Thanks to an anonymous referee for raising this issue.)

  13. For more empirical evidence, see also Løberg et al. (2015) and Rayner et al. (2015).

  14. Sometimes this specific feeling of world-directed unreality is described in the literature as the mark of derealization, a condition that is in turn categorized as part of a broader depersonalization/derealization disorder.

  15. Importantly, Guralnik et al. (2000) suggest that the detected short-term memory deficits are “secondary to difficulties focusing, perceiving, and taking in new information” (107). Attention deficits seem thus to be the primary problem here.

  16. Compare the following report: “At times, the most common, familiar objects can seem foreign, as if I am looking at them for the first time. An American flag, for instance. It’s instantly recognizable, and immediately means something to everyone. But if I look at it for more than a moment, I just see colors and shapes on a piece of cloth” (Simeon and Abugel 2006: p. 7).

  17. In their earlier model, Anne Hillstrom and Steven Yantis defend the opposite claim. Their basic contention is that “the appearance of new objects, and little else [i.e. no other features like motion], captures attention” (Hillstrom and Yantis 1994: p. 409). What’s relevant for the purposes of my paper is that their model allows an equally plausible account of “fleeting glimpses”. Accordingly (see Hillstrom and Yantis 1994: p. 410), the visual field is parsed and segmented into potential objects. Some objects are selected by object-based attention and corresponding object-files are created. When a new object abruptly appears, attention is captured towards it and a new object-file is created. If this turns out to be the right picture, my suggestion would then be that a “fleeting glimpse” occurs when the appearance of the new object is too short-lived to allow the relevant object file to be successfully created.

  18. See “Despite the fact that the acuity of attention is increasingly coarser towards the periphery of FA [field of attention], the peripheral attention, however, may play crucial roles in searching objects and in fine adjustment of attention focus”, Yao et al. (2011: p. 4). See also Thorpe et al. (2001), who show that peripheral vision suffices for the detection of animals in natural images.

  19. This may seem to be in tension with a point I made earlier (see Sect. 3). There, I argued that the fact that hallucinated objects occupy the focus of one’s visual field supports the view that they are selected by visual attention. But that claim requires only that visual attention is usually allocated focally, not that it is necessarily focal.

  20. For similar considerations see also Dokic (2012: p. 394).

  21. A report to this effect is quoted above in Sect. 5. The second symptom listed in the Cambridge Depersonalization Scale devised by Sierra and Berrios reads: “What I see looks ‘flat’ or ‘lifeless’, as if I were looking at a picture” (Sierra 2009: p. 161).

  22. In Sect. 5 I argued that the spatial attention deficits found in depersonalization possibly impair the binding and selection of visual objects. Given the present refinement of the account, and assuming that the feeling of unreality typical of depersonalization consists in a lack of (PP), my position requires only that such deficits impair the correct formation of three-dimensional visual objects.

References

  • Adler, J., et al. (2014). Altered orientation of spatial attention in depersonalization disorder. Psychiatry Research, 216, 230–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allen, K. (2015). Hallucination and imagination. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 93(2), 287–302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bentall, R. (1990). The illusion of reality: A review and integration of psychological research on hallucinations. Psychological Bulletin, 107(1), 82–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bregman, A. S. (1993). Auditory scene analysis: Hearing in complex environments. In S. McAdams & E. Bigand (Eds.), Thinking in sound: The cognitive psychology of human audition (pp. 10–36). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chen, Z. (2012). Object-based attention: A tutorial review. Attention, Perception, and Psychophysics, 74(5), 784–802.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collerton, D., Perry, E., & McKeith, I. (2005). Why people see things that are not there: A novel perception and attention deficit model for recurrent complex visual hallucinations. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 28(6), 737–757.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Diederich, N. J., Goetz, C. G., & Stebbins, G. T. (2005). Repeated visual hallucinations in Parkinson’s disease as disturbed external/internal perceptions: Focused review and a new integrative model. Movement Disorders, 20(2), 130–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dokic, J. (2012). Pictures in the flesh: Presence and appearance in pictorial experience. British Journal of Aesthetics, 52(4), 391–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dokic, J. (2016). Toward a unified account of hallucinations. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 23(7–8), 82–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dokic, J., & Martin, J.-R. (2012). Disjunctivism, hallucination and metacognition. WIREs Cognitive Science, 3, 533–543.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Driver, J., et al. (2001). Segmentation, attention and phenomenal objects. Cognition, 80, 61–95.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fang, F., & He, S. (2005). Cortical responses to invisible objects in the human dorsal and ventral pathways. Nature Neuroscience, 8(10), 1380–1385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Farkas, K. (2013). A sense of reality. In F. Macpherson & D. Platchias (Eds.), Hallucination (pp. 399–414). Cambridge MA: MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Franconeri, S., Hollingworth, A., & Simons, D. (2005). Do new object capture attention? Psychological Science, 16, 275–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guralnik, O., Schmeidler, J., & Simeon, D. (2000). Feeling unreal: Cognitive processes in depersonalization. American Journal of Psychiatry, 157, 103–109.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hillstrom, A., & Yantis, S. (1994). Visual motion and attentional capture. Perception and Psychophysics, 55(4), 399–411.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hollingworth, A., Simons, D., & Franconeri, S. (2010). New objects do not capture attention without a sensory transient. Attention, Perception, and Psychophysics, 72, 1298–1310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hugdahl, K., et al. (2013). Failure of attention focus and cognitive control in schizophrenia patients with auditory verbal hallucinations: Evidence from dichotic listening. Schizophrenia Research, 147, 301–309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E., & (1997 [1907]). Thing and space. Lectures of,. (1907). Translated by R. Rojcewicz. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

  • Jaspers, K. (1911). Zur Analyse der Trugwahrnehmungen (Leibhaftigkeit und Realitätsurteil). Zeitschrift für die gesamte Neurologie und Psychiatrie, 6, 460–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koerts, J., et al. (2010). Attentional and perceptual impairments in Parkinson’s disease with visual hallucinations. Parkinsonism and Related Disorders, 16, 270–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kubovy, M., & Van Valkenburg, D. (2001). Auditory and visual objects. Cognition, 80, 97–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Løberg, E.-M., Jørgensen, H. A., Kroken, R. A., & Johnsen, E. (2015). Auditory verbal hallucinations reflect stable auditory attention deficits: A prospective study. Cognitive Neuropsychiatry, 20(1), 81–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Looijestijn, J., et al. (2013). The auditory dorsal stream plays a crucial role in projecting hallucinated voices into external space. Schizophrenia Research, 146(1–3), 314–319.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2005). Seeing, doing, and knowing. A philosophical theory of sense perception. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. (2010). Two visual systems and the feeling of presence. In N. Gangopadhyay, M. Madary, & F. Spicer (Eds.), Perception, action, and consciousness. Sensorimotor dynamics and two visual systems (pp. 107–24). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • McGinn, C. (2004). Mindsight. Image, dream, meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Milner, D., & Goodale, M. (2006). The visual brain in action (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. (2016). Hallucination as mental imagery. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 23(7–8), 65–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Norman, L. J., Heywood, C. A., & Kentridge, R. W. (2013). Object-based attention without awareness. Psychological Science, 24(6), 836–843.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Callaghan, C. (2008). Object perception: Vision and audition. Philosophy Compass, 3(4), 803–829.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2011). Is attention necessary and sufficient for consciousness? In C. Mole, D. Smithies, & W. Wu (Eds.), Attention. Philosophical and psychological essays (pp. 174–203). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Rayner, L., Lee, K.-H., & Woodruff, P. (2015). Reduced attention-driven auditory sensitivity in hallucination-prone individuals. The British Journal of Psychiatry, 207, 414–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rensink, R. (2000). Seeing, sensing, and scrutinizing. Vision Research, 40, 1469–1487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scholl, B. J. (2001). Objects and attention: The state of the art. Cognition, 80, 1–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwitzgebel, E. (2008). The unrealiability of naïve introspection. Philosophical Review, 117(2), 245–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shine, J. M., O’Callaghan, C., Halliday, G. M., & Lewis, S. J. (2014). Tricks of the mind: Visual hallucinations and disorders of attention. Progress in Neurobiology, 116, 58–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shinn-Cunnigham, B. G. (2008). Object-based auditory and visual attention. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12, 182–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shorvon, H. J. (1946). The depersonalization syndrome. Proceedings of the Royal Society of Medicine, 39, 779–792.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sierra, M. (2009). Depersonalization. A new look at a neglected syndrome. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simeon, D., & Abugel, J. (2006). Feeling unreal. Depersonalization disorder and the loss of the self. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thorpe, S. J., Gegenfurtner, K. R., Fabre-Thorpe, M., & Bülthoff, H. H. (2001). Detection of animals in natural images using far peripheral vision. European Journal of Neuroscience, 14, 869–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Varga, S. (2012). Depersonalization and the sense of realness. Philosophy, Psychiatry & Psychology, 19(2), 123–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yao, J.-G., Gao, X., Yan, H.-M., & Li, C.-Y. (2011). Field of attention for instantaneous object recognition. PLoS ONE, 6(1), e16343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I presented versions of this paper at the University of Porto, at London Institute of Philosophy and at the Institute Jean Nicod in Paris. On all occasions I greatly benefitted from discussion with the audience. Special thanks are due to Roberta Locatelli, Hong Yu Wong and, in particular, Jérôme Dokic. I’d also like to thank Enrico Terrone for his very helpful feedback on an earlier draft and the two anonymous referees of this journal for their insightful suggestions and comments. Finally, I’d like to thank BIAL Foundation for supporting this research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mattia Riccardi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Riccardi, M. Perceptual presence: an attentional account. Synthese 196, 2907–2926 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1588-4

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1588-4

Keywords

Navigation