Skip to main content
Log in

Physicalism and the sortalist conception of objects

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Many hold an Aristotelian metaphysic of objects: fundamentally, objects fall under sortals and have persistence conditions befitting their sort. Though sometimes offered as a theory of material objects, I argue this view is in fact incompatible with physicalism. Call a ‘sortal’ a kind of object, a ‘sortal identity’ a particular’s nature specified in sortal terms, and ‘sortal properties’ properties that are determined by an object’s sortal identity, such as its persistence conditions. From here the argument runs as follows. Something is physical only if it is physically fundamental or is determined by what is physically fundamental (P1), but sortal identities and properties are neither physically fundamental (P2) nor determined by the physically fundamental (P3). I defend each premise in turn. P1 falls out of the standard conception of physicalism. Rejecting P2 is tantamount to positing Aristotelian substantial forms and formal causes—which are themselves incompatible with physicalism. I defend P3 by showing that extant solutions to “the grounding problem”—the problem of showing how (nonfundamental) sortal properties are determined by (nonsortal) physical properties—are either physicalistically unacceptable, or else physicalistically acceptable but opposed to the sortalist metaphysic.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The Aristotelian view was revived by Wiggins (1967, 2001), and then defended by Baker (2002), Fine (2003, 2008), Lowe (2006; 2007; inter alia) and Koslicki (2004, 2008), among others.

  2. See Fine (1995), Zalta (2006) and Correia (2012) for discussion of the consequence relation.

  3. Traditionally ‘everything’ is taken to be unrestricted, though some might wish to exclude abstracta. I won’t because, as I explain in §2, my goal in this paper concerns physicalism as it is traditionally understood. Nothing in my argument turns on this point, however, so one may restrict as one wishes.

  4. See especially Ellis (2001, 2002) and Devitt (2008).

  5. Because sortal identities and properties do not satisfy this necessary condition (or so I will argue), sufficiency conditions for physicality are not germane here.

  6. See Hellman and Thompson (1975) for a classic expression of this view, and Kim (1982), Crane (1991), Wilson (1999) and Loewer (2001) for elaboration and defense. For criticism see Montero (1999, 2006).

  7. Many now understand fundamentality in terms of “grounding”, a relation appearing quite similar to what I’ve said about determination: Schaffer (2009), for instance, holds that some x is fundamental iff nothing grounds x, akin to my claim that something is fundamental iff nothing determines it. This may be because ‘grounding’ and ‘determination’ are two names for the same relation (Audi 2012 suggests as much). Others are skeptical, however (e.g. Wilson 2014). Still others have been critical of understanding physicalism in terms of grounding (e.g. Sider 2011, ch.8, though see Dasgupta 2014 for a response). Whether such criticisms also apply to determination is not entirely clear. Nothing here turns on adjudicating these issues, however. If it turns out that grounding and determination are the same relation then of course my determination talk can be substituted with grounding talk. If there are important reasons to distinguish them then grounding should be put aside for the purposes of my discussion.

  8. Because I will argue that sortalism violates this condition, I will not discuss other conditions for being physically fundamental.

  9. Papineau (2001, p. 20) makes a similar though weaker point. According to Papineau the success of the physical sciences through the 1950’s sufficed to show only that no distinctly vital forces exist—not that determination was demonstrated. But the stronger claim is warranted: for in the absence of nonphysical or sui generis forces it is not clear what else could determine chemical and biological properties. And as what was being worked out was how to explain these properties in physical terms, this seems at (at least partially) tantamount to demonstrating determination. Thanks to Andrew Melnyk for discussion on this point.

  10. Of course, a subset of everyone—physicalists—believe this has been or will be shown shortly.

  11. Thanks to an anonymous referee for this journal for raising this concern.

  12. Lowe (2006) defends the substance-kind vs. attribute-kind distinction, which he too attributes to Aristotle’s Categories, and which he claims is generally unrecognized by contemporary metaphysicians.

  13. Armstrong even goes so far as to claim that the Euthyphro dilemma “is in many ways the most useful dilemma in metaphysics,” and that he relies on variations of it “at a number of points” (p. 40).

  14. Thanks to an anonymous referee for this suggestion.

  15. One may think this first option obvious on the grounds that physicists simply define an electron as whatever has a certain mass, charge, and spin, say (thanks to an anonymous referee for this journal for the suggestion). Though I don’t think matters are so simple—see my discussion in §4—this view is of course consistent with my overall defense of P2. Because my aim in this section is to explore the implications of each Euthyphro-option, however, I will temporarily put the issue aside.

  16. It may help to recall that Aristotle uses the same word—‘aition’—for ‘cause’ and ‘explanation’; these concepts were inextricably linked for Aristotle and his Scholastic follows. Of course such causation is not diachronic but synchronic, though according to the Scholastic it is causation all the same.

  17. Though it may well be that this was more a promissory note than something actually redeemed during the Early Modern period.

  18. I thank an anonymous referee for pressing an objection along these lines.

  19. Perhaps this shouldn’t be surprising. After all, even Grandy notes that “many philosophers (e.g. Wallace 1965) have claimed that the notion of a sortal is the same notion as developed by Aristotle under the label ‘secondary substance”’—a claim which Grandy does not dispute. Also telling is that the term ‘sortal’ was coined by Locke in order to discuss Scholastic notions of kind–essence (EssayConcerning Human Understanding, Bk.III, Ch.III, 15). Moreover, it’s not a coincidence that Baker calls her own assumptions “Aristotelian”, nor that the Scholastics were Aristotelians in the first place: something’s substantial identity being fundamental and yielding sort-specific properties such as persistence conditions just is a basic plank of the Aristotelian worldview that Scholastics and contemporary sortalists inherited.

  20. I thank two anonymous referees for this journal for pressing me on this point.

  21. For example, suppose the sortalist claims that unlike the Scholastic the sortalist’s explanation of sortal properties by a sortal identity is not meant metaphysically, and in so doing she denies any metaphysical relation whereby a sortal identity yields a sortal property—whether formal causation or metaphysical determination or anything else. Instead, the distancing suggesting goes, sortal identities explain sortal properties in some other way (say, conceptually or logically). But if so sortalism would no longer answer my Euthyphro-style question, which queries metaphysical explanation and seeks to reveal ontological—rather than logical or conceptual—priority. (Moreover, sortalism has hitherto been understood as a metaphysical theory of sortals, not a theory about how we employ sortal concepts or vocabulary.) Consequently the sortalist must have real metaphysical explanation and so real metaphysical determination in mind. (Surely this is how Baker’s passage is to read in any case.) But then if indeed the sortalist’s metaphysically explanatory determination relation is different than what the Scholastic calls ‘formal causation’, the sortalist should be able to articulate the difference in conversation. Because I can think of nothing plausible the sortalist might say here I can only conclude that the views are equivalent.

  22. Keeping in mind the metaphysics constraint discussed in the previous note, there is one candidate which may seem plausible: viz., that the historical view advocates a teleology the contemporary view lacks. But this is no defeater either, for two reasons. First, if the contemporary and historical views are the same except for a further posit of teleology, then teleology is not actually a logical commitment of the shared core and so could in principle be excised by a proponent of the historical view as well. Second, note that I made no appeal to teleology in order to show that substantial forms are incompatible with physicalism; it is simply the fundamentality of sortal identity and formal causation, I claimed, that renders the Scholastic view incompatible with physicalism. So even if there are further or additional Scholastic views that go beyond what I’ve discussed that the contemporary sortalist might disavow, this is irrelevant to my argument here: as long as the contemporary and historical views overlap or are substantively identical with respect to the tenets discussed above, this is sufficient to show that the contemporary view is incompatible with physicalism for the same reason the historical view is.

  23. Paul considers this a kind of bundle theory, but with the familiar mereological notion of fusion replacing the more traditional (and perhaps more obscure) notions of compresence or bundling.

  24. Even if the distribution of sortalish properties would supervene on the fundamental physical properties in this scenario, the latter would not determine the former. And as Bennett herself is at pains to point out, supervenience is insufficient for determination (2004, pp. 342–344, passim).

  25. An early instance is Gibbard (1975), whose famous case of Lumpl and Goliath spawned much of the material coincidence literature. In particular Gibbard argued for the (contingent) identity of the statue and the clay on the grounds that the denial of their identity has statues taking on a “ghostly air” (p. 192).

  26. Moreover, what the eliminativist ontology has instead of ordinary objects—namely, mereological simples in various arrangements—lacks precisely those features associated with a sortal identity. For instance, rather than being one unified tiger, say, simples arranged tigerwise are merely many loosely assembled objects. These simples would also lack the persistence conditions associated with tigers. And so on for all Fwise arrangements, for any putative sortal F.

  27. Strictly speaking Lewis only advocates identity for what might be called a ‘permanent overlap’ case, i.e., a case where x and y are created and destroyed simultaneously. For a ‘temporary overlap’ case—where one of x or y precedes or succeeds the other—Lewis thinks x and y are not identical, but are rather partially overlapping four-dimensional space-time “worms”. Even so, Lewis does not advocate material coincidence because in the temporary case there is “partial identity”, i.e., identity in the restricted region where otherwise distinct objects overlap; just as two intersecting roads completely overlap at their intersection (and so are identical there) but differ in virtue of nonshared parts elsewhere (the rest of each road). Accordingly, my discussion of Lewis’ “identity thesis” should be restricted to permanent overlap cases. That being said, I address the possible objection that this assumption isn’t innocent in footnote 32. I thank an anonymous referee for this journal for discussion on this point.

  28. Some reject the possibility of sortally-neutral reference (e.g. Thomasson 2007). Requiring sortally-specific reference does not sit well with Lewis’ mereological universalism, however. For Lewis, “arbitrary” mereological fusions (such as the sum of the Eiffel Tower and this sentence-token) do not fall under any familiar sortals—unless highly generic terms such as ‘object’ or ‘thing’ count. So if these are not sortal terms yet one can determinately refer to any given mereological sum reference need not be sortal-specific (and ‘Object’ may refer determinately absent a sortal). But even if ‘object’ and ‘thing’ do count as sortals my point goes through: because statues and lumps are both things (or objects), referring to this thing via the thing-name ‘Object’, without invoking either statues or lumps of clay, is legitimate.

  29. See Sidelle (2010) for criticism of this sortally-neutral view of objects.

  30. This scenario generalizes across worlds. In presenting Lewis’ view I took it for granted that Statue/Clay/Object has some counterparts that exist after a squashing and others that do not. But suppose we pick out a counterpart via a sortally neutral name; call one Object\(_{\mathrm{w1}}\). Does Object\(_{\mathrm{w1 }}\) survive the squashing in its world? Well, it does if it’s a lump but not if it’s a statue. But Object\(_{\mathrm{w1}}\) is no more a statue to the exclusion of a lump of clay (or vice versa) than Object is, in this world. So the scenario is reiterated at each world: at each world none of Object’s counterparts has an intrinsic sortal identity.

  31. It’s also worth noting that this is not simply a product of vagueness (or “semantic indecision”); even if ‘Object’ is initially ambiguous between any number of referent-candidates, for any given precisification of ‘Object’ it remains an open question whether it is a statue, lump, or something else.

  32. I noted earlier that my discussion of Lewis pertains to his account of permanent rather than temporary overlap cases (footnote 27). But one might think this assumption is not innocent. An anonymous referee for this journal points out regarding my “Object” argument that if Statue and Clay are squashed at \(\hbox {t}_{2}\) then Lewis can say Statue ceases to exist and Clay survives without even invoking his sortal–relative counterpart theory. Even if true this does not affect my argument, however. To see this note one can distinguish temporary from permanent overlap cases only if one comes equipped with knowledge of persistence conditions, such that one can judge that x continued while y ended. But then what are we to say about Object? Consider two variations. In the first Statue is destroyed but Clay remains, such that this is a temporary overlap case as far as Statue and Clay are concerned. But what about Object? Does Object continue to overlap with Clay or not? Because ‘Object’ is sortally neutral the answer is indeterminate, and as a result it is indeterminate whether this is a permanent or temporary overlap case. So consider the second variation: both Statue and Clay are destroyed at \(\hbox {t}_{2}\), rendering it a permanent overlap case as far as Statue and Clay are concerned. But is Object also destroyed? Because ‘Object’ is sortally neutral the answer again is indeterminate, and so again it is indeterminate whether this is a permanent or temporary overlap case. So regardless of the permanent/temporary distinction the sortal identity of Object is indeterminate, and my argument goes through.

  33. Moreover, sortals are often distinguished from non-sortals by their ability to confer unity and countability; tiger is a sortal but red is not because one can count individual tigers but not red things (Grandy 2016; Wiggins 2001).

  34. Because I take this meta-linguistic objection to involve a conceptualist or anti-realist view of sortal properties, I have not discussed conceptualism separately as a physicalist (dis)solution to the grounding problem. For that view, though, see Sidelle (1989, 1998, 2010) and Einheuser (2010).

  35. Worth noting is that Scholastics cited this consequence of a sortal-free world in defense of substantial forms against materialist atomism; Scholastics claimed that if there were no substantial forms, but only atoms moving about in the void, then there would be no distinction between substantial change and mere alteration, i.e., no substances would ever come to be or cease being, but, rather, there would only be the mere alterations of atoms taking on various accidental shapes or arrangements. Thinking this situation absurd Scholastics rejected atomism in favor of substantial forms (Pasnau 2011, pp. 553, 677).

  36. For instance, on Melnyk’s (2003) “realization physicalism” a sortal counts as physical if it is realized by physical entities, rather than being determined by them. So insofar as the (physical) lump realizes Statue’s and Clay’s sortal properties, sortals count as physical. There may remain the worry, though (as with Paul and Fine), that this presupposes that sortal properties exist rather than accounting for them given only a physical base (which is surely a task of the physicalist on any conception). Alternately, one might define ‘physical’ in terms of paradigm physical objects (Stoljar 2001; Strawson 2006). Such views either beg the question against the idealist, however—surely the idealist’s paradigms of mental objects look awfully similar to the physicalist’s paradigms of physical objects—or else this strategy fails to distinguish physicalism from idealism at all (though perhaps this is something that Strawson, who advocates panpsychism, might actually embrace). Another option is the via negativa strategy—defining the physical as the non-mental; see e.g. Montero and Papineau (2005). Whether the physical as the non-sortal will avoid the present difficulties, though, is not clear.

  37. One might wonder, as an anonymous referee for this journal did, whether on my account functional kinds or properties (such as being a clock) are inimical to physicalism. Space forbids in-depth discussion, but the brief answer is that they are not (at least, not necessarily). The reason is that something can posses the (physical) qualities or attributes necessary for fulfilling a function (e.g. being a clock) without that functional kind being what something most fundamentally is (i.e., its sortal identity), or without that functional kind governing or determining its persistence conditions (something might still exist after ceasing to function as a clock, for example). Moreover, and as a result, functional kinds so-construed would not yield coincidence-problems, and as a result would not be subject to the arguments given above. That being said, functional kinds, like everything else, are subject to the generic physicalist constraint of having to be physically fundamental or determined by what is fundamental in order to be counted physical (cf. my comments in the previous note regarding Melnyk’s 2003 “realization physicalism”).

References

  • Aristotle (1963). Categories and De Interpretatione (Clarendon Aristotle Series). Translation and notes, J. Ackrill. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Armstrong, D. (2004). Truth and truthmakers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Audi, P. (2012). Grounding: Towards a theory of the in-virtue-of relation. Journal of Philosophy, 109(12), 685–711.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baker, L. R. (2002). The ontological status of persons. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65(2), 370–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Banach, D. (2007). What killed substantial form? The Saint Anselm Journal, 5, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, K. (2004). Spatio-temporal coincidence and the grounding problem. Philosophical Studies, 118(3), 339–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Correia, F. (2012). On the reduction of necessity to essence. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 84(3), 639–653.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (1991). Why indeed? Papineau on supervenience. Analysis, 51, 32–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, S. (2014). The possibility of physicalism. Journal of Philosophy, 111(9/10), 557–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2008). Resurrecting biological essentialism. Philosophy of Science, 75, 344–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Divers, J. (2008). Coincidence and form. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 82(1), 119–137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dowell, J. (2006). The physical: Empirical, not metaphysical. Philosophical Studies, 131(1), 25–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Einheuser, I. (2010). Toward a conceptualist solution of the grounding problem. Noûs, 45(2), 300–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2001). Scientific essentialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, B. (2002). The philosophy of nature. Chesham: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (1995). The logic of essence. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 24, 241–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2003). The non-identity of a thing and its matter. Mind, 112, 195–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fine, K. (2008). Coincidence and form. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 82(1), 101–118.

  • Fine, K. (2012). Guide to ground. In F. Correia & B. Schnieder (Eds.), Metaphysical grounding (pp. 37–80). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbard, A. (1975). Contingent identity. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 4, 187–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grandy, R. (2016). Sortals. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/sortals/.

  • Hellman, G., & Thompson, F. (1975). Physicalism: Ontology, determination, and reduction. Journal of Philosophy, 72, 551–564.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, B. (2007). Substantial forms and the rise of modern science. The Saint Anselm Journal, 5, 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1982). Psychophysical supervenience. Philosophical Studies, 41, 51–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. (2004). Constitution and similarity. Philosophical Studies, 117, 327–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koslicki, K. (2008). The structure of objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1994). Humean supervenience debugged. Mind, 103, 473–490.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J (1975/1690). In P. H. Nidditch (Ed.), An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Loewer, B. (2001). From physics to physicalism. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp. 37–56). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2006). The four-category ontology: A metaphysical foundation for natural science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2007). Sortals and the individuation of objects. Mind and Language, 22, 514–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Melnyk, A. (2003). A physicalist manifesto: Thoroughly modern materialism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. (1999). The body problem. Noûs, 33(2), 183–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B. (2006). Physicalism in an infinitely decomposable world. Erkenntnis, 64(2), 177–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montero, B., & Papineau, D. (2005). A defence of the via negativa argument for physicalism. Analysis, 65(3), 233–237.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. (2007). Real essentialism. New York: Routledge Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2001). The rise of physicalism. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp. 3–36). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Pasnau, R. (2004). Form, substance, and mechanism. The Philosophical Review, 113(1), 31–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pasnau, R. (2009). Form and matter. In N. Kretzmann, et al. (Eds.), The Cambridge history of medieval philosophy (p. 46). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pasnau, R. (2011). Metaphysical themes: 1274–1671. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A. (2006). Coincidence as overlap. Nous, 40(4), 623–659.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Plato. Euthyphro (B. Jowett, Trans.) http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/euthyfro.html.

  • Rosen, G., & Dorr, C. (2002). Composition as a fiction. In R. Gale (Ed.), The Blackwell guide to metaphysics (pp. 151–174). Oxford: Blackwell Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2009). On what grounds what. In D. Manley, D. Chalmers, & R. Wasserman (Eds.), Metameta-physics: New essays on the foundations of ontology (pp. 347–383). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidelle, A. (1989). Necessity, essence, and individuation: A defense of conventionalism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidelle, A. (1998). A sweater unraveled: Following one thread of thought for avoiding coincident entities. Noûs, 32, 360–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sidelle, A. (2010). Modality and objects. The Philosophical Quarterly, 60(238), 109–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2001). Four dimensionalism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2006). Bare particulars. Philosophical Perspectives, Metaphysics, 20, 387–397.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sider, T. (2011). Writing the book of the world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2001). Two conceptions of the physical. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 62(2), 253–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. (2006). Realistic monism: Why physicalism entails panpsychism. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13(10–11), 3–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomasson, A. (2007). Ordinary objects. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wallace, J. (1965). Sortal predicates and quantification. Journal of Philosophy, 62, 8–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, D. (1967). Identity and spatio-temporal continuity. Oxford: Blackwell Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiggins, D. (2001). Sameness and substance renewed. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (1999). How superduper does a physicalist supervenience need to be? Philosophical Quarterly, 49, 33–52.

  • Wilson, J. (2006). On characterizing the physical. Philosophical Studies, 131, 61–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (2014). No work for a theory of grounding. Inquiry, 57(5–6), 535–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zalta, E. (2006). Essence and modality. Mind, 115, 659–693.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Many thanks to Peter Godfrey-Smith, Tommy Kivatinos, Barry Loewer, Andrew Melnyk, Barbara Montero, Alyssa Ney, Graham Priest, and Peter Simpson for helpful comments and discussion on earlier drafts. I also wish to thank two anonymous referees for Synthese for immensely helpful suggestions and comments, which are greatly appreciated.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonah Goldwater.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Goldwater, J. Physicalism and the sortalist conception of objects. Synthese 195, 5497–5519 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1459-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1459-z

Keywords

Navigation