Skip to main content
Log in

Constraining (mathematical) imagination by experience: Nieuwentijt and van Musschenbroek on the abuses of mathematics

  • S.I.: Use & Abuse of Maths
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Like many of their contemporaries Bernard Nieuwentijt (1654–1718) and Pieter van Musschenbroek (1692–1761) were baffled by the heterodox conclusions which Baruch Spinoza (1632–1677) drew in the Ethics. As the full title of the EthicsEthica ordine geometrico demonstrata—indicates, these conclusions were purportedly demonstrated in a geometrical order, i.e. by means of pure mathematics. First, I highlight how Nieuwentijt tried to immunize Spinoza’s worrisome conclusions by insisting on the distinction between pure and mixed mathematics. Next, I argue that the anti-Spinozist underpinnings of Nieuwentijt’s distinction between pure and mixed mathematics resurfaced in the work of van Musschenbroek. By insisting on the distinction between pure and mixed mathematics, Nieuwentijt and van Musschenbroek argued that Spinoza abused mathematics by making claims about things that exist in rerum natura by relying on a pure mathematical approach (type 1 abuse). In addition, by insisting that mixed mathematics should be painstakingly based on mathematical ideas that correspond to nature, van Musschenbroek argued that René Descartes’ (1596–1650) natural-philosophical project (and that of others who followed his approach) abused mathematics by introducing hypotheses, i.e. (mathematical) ideas, that do not correspond to nature (type 2 abuse).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Whether Spinoza succeeded in proceeding in a mos geometricus in the Ethics and whether he himself thought that he had succeeded in doing so are issues from which I will abstract here. For discussion see e.g. Curley (1986), Steenbakkers (1994, pp. 141–151, 2009), Garrett (2003, pp. 99–103), Nadler (2006, ch. 2), van Bunge (2012, pp. 40–44), and Schliesser forthcoming.

  2. For more background on the religious context in the Dutch Republic, see van der Wall (2003) and Jorink (2010).

  3. For bibliographical details I have relied on anon. (1718) and Vermij (1991, ch. 1).

  4. On Boyle’s influence on Nieuwentijt, see Vermij (1987).

  5. On Verwer, see van Bunge et al. (2003, vol. 2, pp. 1026–1028). The selling catalogue of Nieuwentijt’s library, which appeared 2 years after his death, contains no copy of [Verwer] 1683. It does contain, however, a copy of Verwer (1698) (anon. 1720, p. 35, item n\({^{\circ }}\) 54).

  6. On Kuyper, see van Bunge et al. (2003, vol. 2, pp. 578–580). I have found no evidence that Nieuwentijt was familiar with [Kuyper] 1687.

  7. For the above biographical details I have relied on de Pater (1979, chapter 2).

  8. In order to contextualize the claims that van Musschenbroek develops in his 1723 oration, I will rely on other parts of his oeuvre. Since the core ideas of van Musschenbroek’s methodological programme on which I will focus here remained quite fixed during his career, as will be shown, his later work can, in my view, be legitimately used to shed light in his earlier work.

  9. Van Musschenbroek did not spell out in much detail how empirical data and mathematics are to be combined. See Ducheyne (2015, pp. 288–294) for further discussion.

  10. In Ducheyne (2015) I have argued that Newton’s methodology influenced van Musschenbroek’s only in a fairly general way.

  11. ‘Castus’ can both mean ‘virtuous’ and ‘pious’. Van Musschenbroek may have deliberately chosen to exploit this polysemy.

  12. The book sale catalogue of van Musschenbroek’s library contains a copy of Nieuwentijt’s Regt gebruik der wereldbeschouwingen en Gronden der zekerheid (see anon. 1762, p. 29, item no. 328).

  13. Willem Jacob ’s Gravesande, on whom more is to follow, also underscored that mathematical physics essentially explores relations between quantities. For discussion see Ducheyne (2014a, p. 101).

  14. This obviously put him in opposition with Spinoza, but also with Descartes. In the annotations in one of his copies of Institutiones physicae (1748) van Musschenbroek pointed out that teleology was banished from philosophy by “Descartes and his disciples [Cartesius cum suis Sectatoribus]” (BPL 240, no. 54, interleaved folio facing p. 2).

  15. Translation of: “Mathesis dividitur in mathesin puram et impuram: sive in abstractam et mixtam, quod idem significat. Pura considerat magnitudinis ac numeri generalem naturam, ac proprius affectiones, et consistit in Geometria et Arithmetica. Mixta vel concreta considerat magnitudines ut certis corporibus et subjectis specialibus applicatas [...]”.

  16. Unfortunately, van Musschenbroek did not provide further explication of what correspondence or homology amounts to.

  17. I am indebted to Jip Van Besouw for these two references, which he uses in Van Besouw ms., and for discussion of ’s Gravesande’s strategy of debunking Spinoza’s Ethics.

  18. Translation of: “Post varias Propositiones, per multas ambagas, tandem incidit in conclusionem, quam ex solis definitionibus potuisset deducere, si clare hae propositae fuissent. Quare autem ita agat, dicam. Definitiones captiosae sunt, & hac de causâ non statim patet, in his non servari verborum significationem vulgarem. Ineptum fuisset, conclusionem ex solis arbitrariis definitionibus deductam, ad res veras, vulgari sermone ipsis illis vocibus designatas, transferre: [...].”

  19. See Van Besouw ms. for an interesting analysis of the a priori demonstrations which ’s Gravesande relied on to make claims about God.

  20. Descartes’ view on the divisibility of matter was aired by his early eighteenth-century followers. In his Oratio pro philosophia (‘Oration for philosophy’) (1706), which he delivered upon becoming professor in mathematics and philosophy in Utrecht, Serrurier claimed that it can be shown mathematically that matter is infinitely divisible (Serrurier 1706, pp. 39–40).

References

  • anon. [= Frans Kuyper] (1687). Korte en bondige weederlegging van het wiskunstig bewijs van B. D. Spinosa. S.l.: s.n.

  • anon. [= Johannes Duijkerius] (1697 [1691]). Vervolg van ’t leven van Philopater. Groningen: Siewert van der Brug [= Aart Wolsgryn].

  • anon. (1718). [Obituary for Bernard Nieuwentijt]. Maendelyke uitreksels, of Boekzael der geleerde wereld, Pt. 3 (pp. 744–747).

  • anon. (1720). Catalogus variorum & insignium in omni doctrinarum genere librorum praecipue mathematicorum, quibus usus fuit, dum esset in vivis vir clarissimus & sagissimus Bernardus Nieuwentyt M.D. & urbis Purmurendanae consul & c. Amsterdam/Purmerend: Joannes Oosterwyk/Cornelis Hoogendorp.

  • anon. (1762). Bibliotheca Musschenbroekiana, sive catalogus librorum. Lugduni Batavorum: Per S. et L. Luchtmans.

  • Adam, C., & Tannery, P. (Eds.) (1897–1909). Oeuvres de descartes (Vol. 11). Paris: Leopold Cerf.

  • Bayle, P. (1697). Dictionnaire historique et critique (Vol. 2). Rotterdam: Reiniers Leers.

  • Bots, J. (1972). Tussen Descartes en Darwin, Geloof en natuurwetenschap in de achttiende eeuw in Nederland. Assen: Van Gorcum & Comp. N.V.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyle, R. (1772 [1744]). The works of the honourable Robert Boyle (Vol. 6) (T. Birch, Ed.). London: W. Johnston e.a.

  • Corneanu, S. (2011). Regimens of the mind: Boyle, Locke, and the Early Modern cultura animi tradition. Chicago/London: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Curley, E. (1986). Spinoza’s geometric method. Studia Spinozana, 2, 151–169.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Pater, C. (1979). Petrus van Musschenbroek (1692–1761), Een newtoniaans natuuronderzoeker. Ph.D dissertation, Utrecht University. Utrecht: Elinkwijk.

  • de Pater, C. (1995). ’s Gravesande on moral evidence. In M. F. Fresco, L. Geeraedts, & K. Hammacher (Eds.), Frans Hemsterhuis (1721–1790), Quellen, philosophie und rezeption (pp. 221–242). Münster/Hamburg: LIT Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, A. X. (2015). Spinoza and Dutch Cartesianism: Philosophy and theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ducheyne, S. (2014a). W. J. ’s Gravesande’s appropriation of Newton’s natural philosophy. Part II: Methodological Issues, Centaurus, 56, 97–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ducheyne, S. (2014b). W. J. ’s Gravesande’s appropriation of Newton’s natural philosophy. Part I: Epistemological and Theological issues, Centaurus, 56, 31–55.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ducheyne, S. (2014c). Celeberrimus Atheismi patronus praecedentis saeculi: Petrus van Musschenbroek’s anti-Spinozism unveiled. Lias, Journal of early modern intellectual culture and its sources, 41, 173–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ducheyne, S. (2015). Petrus van Musschenbroek and Newton’s vera stabilisque Philosophandi methodus. Berichte zur, Wissenschaftsgeschichte, 38, 279–304.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ducheyne, S. (2016). Petrus van Musschenbroek (1692–1761) on the scope of physica and its place in philosophy. Asclepio, Revista de historia de la medicina y de la ciencia, 68, article number: 123.

  • Ducheyne, S. (2017). Curing pansophia through eruditum nescire: Bernard Nieuwentijt’s (1654–1718) epistemology of modesty. HOPOS, 7 (in print).

  • Freudenthal, H. (1955). Nieuwentijt und der teleologische Gottesbeweis. Synthese, 9, 454–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garrett, A. V. (2003). Meaning in Spinoza’s method. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ’s Gravesande, W. J. (1717). Oratio inauguralis de matheseos, in omnibus scientiis, praecipue in physicis, usu, nec non de astronomiae perfectione ex physica haurienda. Lugduni Batavorum: Apud Samuelem Luchtmans.

  • ’s Gravesande, W. J. (1720–1721). Physices elementamathematica, experimentis confirmata, sive introductio adphilosophiam Newtonianam (Vol. 2). Lugduni Batavorum: ApudPetrum & Balduinum Janssonium vander Aa

  • ’s Gravesande, W. J. (1734). Orationes duae, Prima De vera, & nunquam vituperata philosophia... Altera De evidentia.... Lugduni Batavorum: Apud Samuelem Luchtmans.

  • ’s Gravesande, W. J. (1742\(^{2}\) [1720-1721]). Physices elementa mathematica experimentis confirmata, sive introductio ad philosophiam Newtoniam (Vol. 2). Leidae: Apud Johannem Arnoldum Langerak, Johannem et Hermannum Verbeek.

  • Hall, A. R. (1982). Further Newton correspondence. Notes and Records of the Royal Society of London, 37, 7–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Israel, J. I. (1996). The banning of Spinoza’s work in the Dutch Republic (1670–1678). In W. van Bunge & W. Klever (Eds.), Disguised and overt Spinozism around 1700. E. J. Brill: Leiden/New York/Köln.

  • Israel, J. I. (2001). Radical enlightenment: Philosophy and the making of modernity, 1650–1750. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jorink, E. (2009). Honouring Sic Isaac, or, exorcising the ghost of Spinoza: Some recent remarks on the success of Newton in the Dutch Republic. In S. Ducheyne (Ed.), Future perspectives on Newton Scholarship and the Newtonian Legacy (pp. 23–34). Brussels: Koninklijke Vlaamse Academie van België voor Wetenschappen en Kunsten.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jorink, E. (2010). Reading the Book of Nature in the Dutch Golden Age, 1575–1715. Leiden: Brill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jorink, E., & Zuidervaart, H. (2012). The miracle of our time, How Isaac Newton was fashioned in the Netherlands. In E. Jorink & A. Maas (Eds.), Newton and the Netherlands, How Isaac Newton was fashioned in the Dutch Republic (pp. 13–65). Amsterdam: Leiden University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kernkamp, G. W. (1936). De Utrechtsche Universiteit 1636–1936 (Vol. 2). Utrecht: A. Oosthoek’s uitgevers maatschappij.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klever, W. N. A. (1988). Letters to and from Neercassel about Spinoza and Rieuwertsz. Studia Spinozana, 4, 329–340.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klijnsmit, A. J. (1991). Spinoza en Verwer: Een zeventiende-eeuws meningsverschil over de grondslagen van de wetenschap. In J. Noordegraaf & R. Zemel (Eds.), Accidentia: Taal-en letterkundige oefeningen voor Jan Knol (pp. 9–20). Amsterdam: Stichting Neerlandistiek VU.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. (1996). Philosophy of mathematic and mathematical practice in the seventeenth century. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • More, H. (1679). Opera omnia (Vol. 2). Londoni: J. Macock sumptibus J. Martyn & Gualt. Kettilby.

  • Nadler, S. (2006). Spinoza’s Ethics: An introduction. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, F. (2008). Nieuwentijt, Leibniz, and Jacob Hermann on infinitesimals. In U. Goldenbaum & D. Jesseph (Eds.), Infinitesimal differences: Controversies between Leibniz and his contemporaries (pp. 199–214). Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nieuwentijt, B. (1694). Considerationes circa analyseos ad quantitates infinite parvas applicatae principia, et calculi differentialis usum in resolvendis problematibus gemetricis. Amstelaedami: Apud Joannem Wolters.

  • Nieuwentijt, B. (1695). Analysis infinitorum, seu curvilineorum proprietates ex polygonorum natura deductae. Amstelaedami: Apud Jooannem Wolters.

  • Nieuwentijt, B. (1696). Considerationes secundae circa calculi differentialis principia, & Responsio ad Virum Nobilissimum G.G. Leibnitium. Amstelaedami: Apud Jooannem Wolters.

  • Nieuwentijt, B. (1718), The religious philosopher: Or, the right use of comtemplating the works of the creator (Vol. 2) (J. Chamberlayne, Trans.). London: J. Senex and W. Taylor.

  • Nieuwentijt, B. (1725\(^{4}\) [1715]). Het regt gebruik der wereltbeschouwingen, ter overtuiginge van ongodisten en ongelovigen aangetoont. Amsterdam: Joannes Pauli.

  • Nieuwentijt, B. (1720). Gronden van zekerheid, of de regte betoogwyse der wiskundigen so in het denkbeeldige, als in het zakelyke: Ter wederlegging van Spinosaas denkbeeldige Samestel; en ter aanleiding van eene sekere sakelyke wijsbegeerte. Amsterdam: Joannes Pauli.

  • Petry, M. (1979). Nieuwentijt’s criticism of Spinoza. Mededelingen vanwege het Spinozahuis (Vol. 15). Leiden: E. J. Brill.

  • Petry, M. (1981). Kuyper’s analysis of Spinoza’s axiomatic method. In K. Cramer, W. G. Jacobs, & W. Schmidt-Biggemann (Eds.), Spinozas Ethik und ihre frühe Wirkung (pp. 1–18). Wolfenbüttel: Herzog August Bibliothek.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roux, S. (2010). Forms of mathematization (14th-17th centuries). Early science and medicine, 15, 319–337.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sassen, F. (1959). Geschiedenis van de wijsbegeerte in Nederland tot het einde der negentiende eeuw. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schliesser, E. (2012). Newton and Spinoza: On motion and matter (and God, of course). The Southern Journal of Philosophy, 50, 438–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schliesser, E. (forthcoming). Spinoza and the philosophy of science: Mathematics, motion, and being. In M. della Rocca (Ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Spinoza. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Schuurman, P. (2010). ‘Thou Knowest not the Works of God’: Gisbertus Voetius (1589–1676) and John Locke on learned ignorance. Westminster Theological Journal, 72, 59–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Serrurier, J. (1706). Oratio pro philosophia. Trajecti ad Rhenum: Ex officina Guillelmi vande Water.

  • Spinoza, B. (2002). Complete works (M. L. Morgan, Ed. and intro., S. Shirley, Trans.). Hackett: Indianapolis/Cambridge.

  • S., B. d. [= Spinoza, B.] (1677). Opera posthuma. S.l.: s.n.

  • Steenbakkers, P. (1994). Spinoza’s Ethica from manuscript to print: Studies on text form and related topics. Assen: Van Gorcum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steenbakkers, P. (2009). The geometrical order in the Ethics. In O. Koistinen (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Spinoza’s Ethics (pp. 42–55). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Van Besouw, J. (forthcoming). ’s Gravesande on the application of mathematics in physics and philosophy, Noctua.

  • Van Besouw, J. (ms.). ’s Gravesande Essais de métaphysique: ‘Leibnizian’ considerations on God, goodness, and liberty as foundation of empirical science.

  • van Blijenbergh, W. (1682). Wederlegging van de Ethica of Zede-Kunst, van Benedictus de Spinosa. Dordrecht: By de Weduwe van Jasper, en by Dirck Goris.

  • van Bunge, W. (2001). From Stevin to Spinoza, An essay on philosophy in the seventeenth-century Dutch Republic. Leiden/Boston/Köln: E.J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Bunge, W., Krop, H., Leeuwenburgh, B., Schuurman, P., van Ruler, H., & Wielema, M. (Eds.). (2003). Dictionary of seventeenth and eighteenth-Century Dutch philosophers (Vol. 2). Bristol: Thoemmes Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Bunge, L. (2012). Spinoza past and present, Essays on Spinoza, Spinozism, and Spinoza scholarship. Leiden/Boston: Brill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Bunge, W. (2017). The waning of the Radical Enlightenment in the Dutch Republic. In S. Ducheyne (Ed.), Reassessing the Radical Enlightenment (pp. 178–193). Abington: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • van der Wall, E. G. E. (2003). The religious context of the early Dutch Enlightenment: Moral religion and society. In W. van Bunge (Ed.), The early Enlightenment in the Dutch Republic (pp. 39–57). Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vandevelde, J. J. (1926). Bijdrage tot de bio-bibliographie van Bernard Nieuwentyt (1654\({\dagger }\) 1718). In Verslagen en mededelingen van de Koninklijke Vlaamse Academie voor Taal-en Letterkunde (pp. 709–718).

  • van Musschenbroek, P. BPL, codex 240, n\(^{\circ }\) 1–67, Special Collections Department, Leiden University Library, The Netherlands.

  • van Musschenbroek, P. (1723). Oratio de certa methodo philosophiae experimentalis, Dicta publice A. D. xiii. Septemb. Trajecti ad Rhenum: Apud Guilielmum Vande Water.

  • van Musschenbroek, P. (1726). Epitome elementorum physico-mathematicorum, conscripta in usus academicos. Lugduni Batavorum: Apud Samuelem Lugtmans.

  • van Musschenbroek, P. (1731). Oratio de methodo instituendi experimenta physica. In id., Tentamina experimentorum naturalium captorum in Academia del Cimento (Vol. xlviii). Lugduni Batavorum: Apud Joan. Et Herm. Verbeek.

  • van Musschenbroek, P. (1739\(^{2}\) [1736]). Beginsels der natuurkunde. Leyden: Samuel Luchtmans.

  • van Musschenbroek, P. (1741\(^{2}\) [1734]). Elementa physicae conscripta in usus academicos. Lugduni Batavorum: Apud Samuelem Luchtmans.

  • van Musschenbroek, P. (1744). The elements of natural philosophy, Chiefly intended for the use of students in universities (Vol. 2) (J. Colson, Trans). London: Printed for J. Nourse at the Lamb without Temple-Bar.

  • van Musschenbroek, P. (1748). Institutiones logicae, Praecipue comprehentes artem argumentandi. Lugduni Batavorum: Apud Samuelem Luchtmans et filium.

  • van Ruler, J. A. (1995). The crisis of causality, Voetius and Descartes on God, nature and change. Leiden/New York/Köln: E. J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek, T. (1988). René Descartes et Martin Schoock: La querelle d’Utrecht. Paris: Les impressions nouvelles.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verbeek, T. (1993). From ‘Learned Ignorance’ to Scepticism: Descartes and Calvinist Orthodoxy. In R. H. Popkin & A. J. Vanderjacht (Eds.), Scepticism and Irreligion in the Seventeenth and Eighteenth Centuries (pp. 31–45). Leiden/New York/Köln: E. J. Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermij, R. H. (1987). Bernard Nieuwentijt als experimentator. Tijdschrift voor geschiedenis der geneeskunde natuurwetenschappen, wiskunde en techniek, 10, 81–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermij, R. H. (1988). Bernard Nieuwentijt en de physico-theologie. Documentatieblad werkgroep Achttiende eeuw, 20, 215–229.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermij, R. H. (1989). Religion and mathematics in seventeenth-century Holland: The case of Bernard Nieuwentijt. In Ä. Bäumer & M. Büttner (Eds.), Science and Religion/Wissenschafts und Religion, Proceedings of the Symposium of the XVIIIth International Congress of History of Science at Hamburg-Munich, 1–9 August 1989 (pp. 152–158). Buchum: Universitätsverlag Dr. N. Brockmeyer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermij, R. H. (1991). Secularisering en natuurwetenschap in de zeventiende en achttiende eeuw: Bernard Nieuwentijt. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vermij, R. H. (2003). The formation of the Newtonian philosophy: The case of the Amsterdam mathematical amateurs. British Journal for the History of Science, 36, 183–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vermij, R. H. (2011). The light of nature and the allegorisation of science on Dutch frontispieces around 1700. In E. Jorink & B. Ramakers (Eds.), Art and science in the early modern Netherlands, Series: Netherlands yearbook for history of art (Vol. 61, pp. 209–237). Zwolle: WBOOKS.

    Google Scholar 

  • V., A. [=Adriaen Verwer] (1683). ‘t Mom-aensicht der atheistery afgerukt, Of de wederlegging der Zedekunst van Benedictus de Spinoza. Amsterdam: Wilhelmus Goeree.

  • Verwer, A. (1698). Inleiding tot de christelyke Gods-geleertheid. Amsterdam: Jan Rieuwertz.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Research for this paper was funded by the Vrije Universiteit Brussel under the form of a Research Professorship. Parts of this essay were delivered at the international workshop ‘The Uses and Abuses of Mathematics in Early Modern Philosophy’ which took place in Budapest on 10 March 2015. I am grateful to its audience for feedback. I am also indebted to the Special Collections Department at Leiden University Library for permission to quote from material in their care, to Ronald Desmet, Koen Lefever, and Jip Van Besouw for comments on an earlier version of this essay, to the editors of this special issue for their encouragement and hard work, and to the two anonymous referees of this journal for valuable feedback.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Steffen Ducheyne.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ducheyne, S. Constraining (mathematical) imagination by experience: Nieuwentijt and van Musschenbroek on the abuses of mathematics. Synthese 196, 3595–3613 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1392-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1392-1

Keywords

Navigation