Skip to main content
Log in

Rethinking the problem of cognition

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The present century has seen renewed interest in characterizing cognition, the object of inquiry of the cognitive sciences. In this paper, I describe the problem of cognition—the absence of a positive characterization of cognition despite a felt need for one. It is widely recognized that the problem is motivated by decades of controversy among cognitive scientists over foundational questions, such as whether non-neural parts of the body or environment can realize cognitive processes, or whether plants and microbes have cognitive processes. The dominant strategy for addressing the problem of cognition is to seek a dichotomous criterion that vindicates some set of controversial claims. However, I argue that the problem of cognition is also motivated by ongoing conceptual development in cognitive science, and I describe four benefits that a characterization of cognition could confer. Given these benefits, I recommend an alternative criterion of success, ecumenical extensional adequacy, on which the aim is to describe the variation in expert judgments rather than to correct this variation by taking sides in sectarian disputes. I argue that if we had an ecumenical solution to the problem of cognition, we would have achieved much of what we should want from a “mark of the cognitive”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Throughout, I employ the convention of small capitalization to indicate reference to concepts. Cognition is a natural phenomenon, “cognition” is a word, and cognition is a concept.

  2. It seems that, excepting some enactivists, there is a consensus that cognition is not in general to be identified with a kind of behavior (op. cit.), at least when speaking carefully. Given the significant minority status of the view that cognition is behavior, its failure to be taken up in careful theoretical discussion outside of philosophy, and its failure to have a discernible effect on empirical research independently of other enactivist claims, I will not consider it in this paper. I thank an anonymous reviewer for vigorously pressing me on this point.

  3. I adopt the term “explication” or “conceptual explication” in place of “conceptual analysis” because it seems to have fewer controversial Kantian connotations regarding analyticity.

  4. The history is of course complicated. Some border war controversies have predecessors. The characterization by scientists of “unconscious” processes by analogy to highfalutin cognitive processes like inference goes back at least as far as the nineteenth century, e.g. Helmholtz’ (1867) “unconscious inference.” Scientific consideration of microbe cognition goes back at least as far as early enactivism among Chilean biologists in the 1970s (Maturana and Varela 1980, originally published in 1970). However, the mainstreaming (or re-adoption) of these perspectives has accelerated since the 1980s, when the border wars began.

  5. Ramsey (2015) also claims that cognitive science should be understood as the study of cognition, whatever cognition is, but denies that any speculative “mark of the cognitive” should limit our inquiry. I am inclined to agree that it should not, as will become clearer, but disagree with Ramsey that there is therefore no important end served by trying to resolve the problem of cognition. However, cf. Rupert (2013) for a dissenting view, that cognitive science is not aptly characterized as the study of cognition; his dissent is based on the premises that in order for that description to be a happy one cognition must be a well-behaved natural kind, and that cognition is not a natural kind.

  6. Even Buckner, whose goal is to demarcate cognition from association rather than to take a side in the border wars per se, takes his account to have alarming revisionary consequences, e.g. that cases of associative learning, such as taste aversion, are not cognitive phenomena (2015, p. 315). This consequence may be appropriate for highfalutin cognition, but is alarming for inclusive cognition.

  7. As Adam Marushak says regarding contextualist approaches in philosophy of language (and echoing Lewis): “If the house is going to shake, you want the foundations to sway, too” (Marushak, personal communication; cf. Lewis 1973, p. 92).

  8. A scholar of journalism or political science might be reminded here of Daniel C. Hallin’s characterization of objectivity in media coverage (1986). Hallin suggests that a journalist’s claim may fall into either of the “sphere of consensus,” the “sphere of legitimate controversy,” or the “sphere of deviance.” These spheres describe the boundaries between claims that may be taken for granted by journalists, those that call for epistemic distancing or “balancing” evidence, and those that are generally considered unworthy of serious attention. My suggestion is that, in ecumenically characterizing cognition, we make similar distinctions regarding membership in the extension of cognition.

  9. I am thankful to an anonymous reviewer for putting this objection to me insistently.

References

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2001). The bounds of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 14, 43–64.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Aizawa, K. (2008). The bounds of cognition. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Adams, F., & Garrison, R. (2013). The mark of the cognitive. Minds and Machines, 23, 339–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa, K. (2014). Extended cognition. In L. A. Shapiro (Ed.), The routledge handbook of embodied cognition (pp. 31–38). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aizawa, K. (2015). Cognition and behavior. Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0645-5.

  • Akagi, M. (2016). Cognition in practice: Conceptual development and disagreement in cognitive science (Doctoral dissertation). Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atkinson, R. C., & Shiffrin, R. M. (1968). Human memory: A proposed system and its control processes. In K. W. Spence & J. T. Spence (Eds.), The psychology of learning and motivation: Advances in research and theory (Vol. 2, pp. 90–197). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, F. (1902). Novum organum. New York: P.F. Collier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1980). Troubles with functionalism. In N. Block (Ed.), Readings in philosophy of psychology (pp. 171–184). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boorse, C. (1977). Health as a theoretical concept. Philosophy of Science, 44, 542–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bourgine, P., & Stewart, J. (2004). Autopoiesis and cognition. Artificial Life, 10, 327–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R. N. (1991). Realism, anti-foundationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philosophical Studies, 61, 127–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, R. (1991). Intelligence without representation. Artificial Intelligence, 47, 139–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2015). A property cluster theory of cognition. Philosophical Psychology, 28, 307–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess, A., & Plunkett, D. (2013a). Conceptual ethics I. Philosophy. Compass, 8, 1091–1101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burgess, A., & Plunkett, D. (2013b). Conceptual ethics II. Philosophy. Compass, 8, 1102–1110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calvo Garzón, F. (2007). The quest for cognition in plant neurobiology. Plant Signaling & Behavior, 2, 208–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (2011). A computational foundation for the study of cognition. Journal of Cognitive Science, 12, 323–357.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2008). Inventing temperature: Measurement and scientific progress. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A. (2009). Radical embodied cognitive science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chemero, A., & Silberstein, M. (2008). After the philosophy of mind: Replacing scholasticism with science. Journal of Philosophy, 75, 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1981). Eliminative materialism and the propositional attitudes. Philosophy of Science, 78, 67–90.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (1997). Being there: Putting brain, body and world together again. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2001). Reasons, robots, and the extended mind. Mind and Language, 16, 121–145.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2010). Memento’s revenge: The extended mind, extended. In R. Menary (Ed.), The extended mind (pp. 43–66). Cambridge, MA: Bradford.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleland, C. E. (2012). Life without definitions. Synthese, 185, 125–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1987). The intentional stance. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eliasmith, C. (2002). The myth of the turing machine: The failure of functionalism and related theses. Journal of Experimental and Theoretical Artificial Intelligence, 14, 1–8.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallagher, S. (2005). How the body shapes the mind. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gettier, E. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibbs, R. W, Jr. (2005). Embodiment and cognitive science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2002). Environmental complexity and the evolution of cognition. In R. J. Sternberg & J. C. Kaufman (Eds.), The evolution of intelligence (pp. 233–249). Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. D., Nystrom, L. E., Engell, A. D., Darley, J. M., & Cohen, J. D. (2004). The neural bases of cognitive conflict and control in moral judgment. Neuron, 44, 389–400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P., Machery, E., & Linquist, S. (2009). The vernacular concept of innateness. Mind and Language, 24, 605–630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P., & Stotz, K. (2006). Genes in the postgenomic era. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 27, 499–521.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hallin, D. C. (1986). The uncensored war: The media and Vietnam. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslanger, S. (2000). Gender and race: (What) are they? (What) do we want them to be? Noûs, 34, 31–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. L. (1998). Consciousness in action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1973). Counterfactuals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lilienfeld, S. O., & Marino, L. (1995). Mental disorder as a Roschian concept: A critique of Wakefield’s ‘harmful dysfunction’ analysis. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 104, 411–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyon, P. (2006). The biogenic approach to cognition. Cognitive Processing, 7, 11–29.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacFarlane, J. (2014). Assessment sensitivity: Relative truth and its applications. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2009). Doing without concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. (2012). Why I stopped worrying about the definition of life.. and why you should as well. Synthese, 185, 145–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maturana, H. R., & Varela, F. (1980). Autopoiesis and cognition: The realization of the living. Boston: D. Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2006). Action in perception. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ohlsson, S. (1993). Abstract schemas. Educational Psychologist, 28, 51–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orlandi, N. (2014). The innocent eye: Why vision is not a cognitive process. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2004). Gut reactions: A perceptual theory of emotions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1967). The mental life of some machines. In H.-N. Castañeda (Ed.), Intentionality, minds, and perception. Detroit: Wayne State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. O. (1960). Word and object. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. M. (1992). Prototypes and conceptual analysis. Topoi, 11, 59–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. M. (2007). Representation reconsidered. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ramsey, W. M. (2015). Must cognition be representational? Synthese. doi:10.1007/s11229-014-0644-6.

  • Robbins, P., & Aydede, M. (Eds.). (2008). The cambridge handbook of situated cognition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E., & Mervis, C. B. (1975). Family resemblance: Studies in the internal structure of categories. Cognitive Psychology, 7, 573–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2009). Extended cognition and the mark of the cognitive. Philosophical Psychology, 22, 1–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind: From extended mind to embodied phenomenology. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart, D. E. (1989). The architecture of mind: A connectionist approach. In M. I. Posner (Ed.), Foundations of cognitive science (pp. 133–159). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. (2004). Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. Journal of Philosophy, 51, 389–428.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. (2009). Cognitive systems and the extended mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rupert, R. (2013). Memory, natural kinds, and cognitive extension; or, Martians don’t remember, and cognitive science is not about cognition. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 4, 25–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, L. A. (2013). Dynamics and cognition. Minds and Machines, 23, 353–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smart, J. J. C. (1959). Sensations and brain processes. Philosophical Review, 68, 141–156.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sprevak, M. (2009). Extended cognition and functionalism. The Journal of Philosophy, 106, 503–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, J. (1996). Cognition = life: Implications for higher-level cognition. Behavioural Processes, 35, 311–326.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. (1983). From folk psychology to cognitive science: The case against belief. Cambridge, MA: Bradford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thelen, E., & Smith, L. B. (1994). A dynamic systems approach to the development of cognition and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, E. (2010). Mind in life: Biology, phenomenology, and the sciences of the mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trewavas, A. (2003). Aspects of plant intelligence. Annals of Botany, 92, 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tulving, E. (1972). Episodic and semantic memory. In E. Tulving & W. Donaldson (Eds.), Organization of memory (pp. 381–403). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. M. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, 59, 433–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science, 185, 1124–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Duijn, M., Keijzer, F., & Franken, D. (2006). Principles of minimal cognition: Casting cognition as sensorimotor coordination. Adaptive Behavior, 14, 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Gelder, T. (1998). The dynamical hypothesis in cognitive science. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21, 615–665.

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela, F., Thompson, E., & Rosch, E. (1991). The embodied mind: Cognitive science and human experience. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Helmholtz, H. (1867). Handbuch der physiologischen Optik. Leipzig: Voss.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wakefield, J. C. (1992). The concept of mental disorder: On the boundary between biological facts and social values. American Psychologist, 47, 373–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walter, S. (2010). Cognitive extension: The parity argument, functionalism, and the mark of the cognitive. Synthese, 177, 285–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Webb, B. (1994). Robotic experiments in cricket phonotaxis. In D. Cliff, P. Husbands, J.-A. Meyer, & S. W. Wilson (Eds.), From animals to animats 3: Proceedings of the third international conference on simulation of adaptive behavior (pp. 45–54). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, M. (2006). Wandering significance: An essay on conceptual behavior. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. A. (2010). Review of Robert D. Rupert’s cognitive systems and the extended mind. Notre Dame Philosophical Reviews, March 7, 2010. https://ndpr.nd.edu/news/24309-cognitive-systems-and-the-extended-mind/.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful for generous feedback on these ideas from many people, including Joseph McCaffrey, Robert Brandom, Edouard Machery, Mark Sprevak, Zoe Drayson, William Bechtel, three anonymous reviewers, and colleagues at the Society for Philosophy and Psychology, the University of Pittsburgh, the University of Edinburgh, and the University of Glasgow. An earlier version of this paper appears as Chapter 2 of my PhD dissertation, “Cognition in Practice: Conceptual Development and Disagreement in Cognitive Science” (2016, University of Pittsburgh). I received financial support from University of Pittsburgh Department of Philosophy, the University of Pittsburgh Office of the Provost, and the Wesley C. Salmon Fund.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Mikio Akagi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Akagi, M. Rethinking the problem of cognition. Synthese 195, 3547–3570 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1383-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1383-2

Keywords

Navigation