Skip to main content
Log in

The biogenic approach to cognition

  • Review
  • Published:
Cognitive Processing Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

After half a century of cognitive revolution we remain far from agreement about what cognition is and what cognition does. It was once thought that these questions could wait until the data were in. Today there is a mountain of data, but no way of making sense of it. The time for tackling the fundamental issues has arrived. The biogenic approach to cognition is introduced not as a solution but as a means of approaching the issues. The traditional, and still predominant, methodological stance in cognitive inquiry is what I call the anthropogenic approach: assume human cognition as the paradigm and work ‘down’ to a more general explanatory concept. The biogenic approach, on the other hand, starts with the facts of biology as the basis for theorizing and works ‘up’ to the human case by asking psychological questions as if they were biological questions. Biogenic explanations of cognition are currently clustered around two main frameworks for understanding biology: self-organizing complex systems and autopoiesis. The paper describes the frameworks and infers from them ten empirical principles—the biogenic ‘family traits’—that constitute constraints on biogenic theorizing. Because the anthropogenic approach to cognition is not constrained empirically to the same degree, I argue that the biogenic approach is superior for approaching a general theory of cognition as a natural phenomenon.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. ‘Anthropogenic’ is an adjective long used in plant ecology to refer to plants introduced by humans; it increasingly refers to climate change associated with human activity. ‘Biogenic’ is used in geology to refer to the origins of certain rock strata. Limestone is biogenic, for example, because its origin is material that once formed part of living organisms. I am indebted to Jon Opie for suggesting that I devise neologisms for this distinction and to my husband, Richard Bradshaw, for finding them.

  2. An example: “As our species designation—sapiens—suggests, the defining attribute of human beings is an unparalleled cognitive ability. We think differently from all other creatures on earth, and we can share those thoughts with one another in ways that no other species even approaches. In comparison, the rest of our biology is almost incidental” (Deacon 1997).

  3. Biosemiotics should not be conflated with biosemantics, with which it is congenial but not identical. Biosemantics is Millikan’s relentlessly biological rendering of intentionality within the content of ongoing anthropogenic debates (Millikan 1989). Biosemiotics, by contrast, is grounded in Jacob von Uexküll’s biological theory of meaning, Piercean sign theory and contemporary molecular biology—its leading advocates are, in fact, biologists—and does not engage with analytic philosophical debates.

  4. Whereas some thinkers (e.g., Matthen and Levy 1986) are comfortable ascribing intentionality to macromolecules, others (e.g., Rosenberg 1986) strongly oppose such attribution.

  5. Erwin Schrödinger is commonly credited with pointing out the peculiarity of organisms relative to the laws of classical thermodynamics, which ultimately led to the development of nonclassical elaborations such as dissipative structures. In reality, the German theoretical biologist Ludwig von Bertalanffy proposed the idea of a thermodynamically open system in 1940, which forced physicists (and chemists such as Prigogine) to take note. Ironically, Bertalanffy proposed the open system concept as a counter to metaphysical vitalism, only to have his own general system theory tarred with the vitalist brush by reductionists such as Jacques Monod.

  6. ‘True equilibrium’ here refers to thermodynamic equilibrium, or total molecular disorder, which is death for a living system. The phonemic similarity but conceptual antonymity of thermodynamic equilibrium and metabolic balance maintained by homeostasis, which is often referred to in terms of equilibrium, is an unfortunate fact of interdisciplinary history and is an object lesson in the problems of overlapping terminologies.

  7. Homeostasis is defined as “the regulation by an organism of the chemical composition of its body fluids and other aspects of its internal environment so that physiological processes can proceed at optimum rates. It involves monitoring changes in the external and internal environments by means of receptors and adjusting the composition of the body fluids accordingly; excretion and (osmotic) regulation are important in this process” (Martin and Hine 2000). Two examples of homeostatic regulation are the acid-base balance and body temperature.

  8. Kringelbach points out that relatively slow metabolic processes, in humans at least, means that internal system changes do not swiftly track food intake, thus regulation of eating behaviour requires “sophisticated [neural] mechanisms to learn to predict in advance when a meal should be initiated and terminated” (2004, p 808).

  9. For this reason Kringelbach suggests that food intake in nonhuman mammals may provide good model systems for investigating the neurobiology of phenomenal experience.

  10. Another gap relates to organisms’ “limited autonomy from local energy potentials” and their ability to “vary their rate of energy consumption independently of variations in local gradients” (Barham 1996). This is possible because organisms have their own on-board energy supply in the form of adenosine triphosphate (ATP). It is a biological system’s “ability to use low-energy fluxes from a distal source in order to detect high-energy potentials before it becomes thermodynamically coupled with them” that is the odd trick, according to Barham (p 239). This capacity is contingent upon the system’s ability to “distinguish between those conditions external to itself that will support its continued oscillation, and those which will not” (p 238). Under starvation conditions, for example, certain species of bacteria will sporulate, a process that induces dramatic, global changes in cell state such that the organism can hunker down indefinitely until conditions improve (Marahiel and Zuber 1999). Sporulation is highly energy intensive and, in some cases, irreversible to the extent that the bacterium cannot ‘change its mind’ halfway through the process. The sporulation option, therefore, involves a calculated risk regarding the extent to which conditions will support “continued oscillation”.

  11. This section is a summary of a longer, more detailed presentation in Lyon (2004). Please note that Maturana has consistently declined to characterize as a ‘theory’ the framework he developed in partnership with Varela and others, and indeed it has been criticized for not being a proper theory (see especially Scheper and Scheper 1996). But as autopoiesis constitutes a coherent conceptual structure that provides explanations and makes predictions, ‘theory’ is an appropriate label, in my view.

  12. It is beyond the scope of this paper to show how autopoietic theory accounts for complex cognitive phenomena such as language use. Suffice to say that the theory recently has proven as influential in disciplines related to education, business systems, management and nursing as it has in relation to cognition.

  13. Maturana and Varela in their early work resiled from using the word ‘environment’ on the basis that it was observer-dependent and encompassed a broader view than which the system itself was capable. The observer/system distinction is critical to the autopoietic model.

  14. Robert Rosen came to a similar conclusion regarding ‘state determinism’ in his biological rendering of dynamical systems theory. “In a nutshell, a system which is both (thermodynamically) open and autonomous...must have the property that the flows from environment to system, and from system to environment, are determined by what is inside the system” (Rosen 2000).

  15. I have niggling doubts about this claim. If a shark eats a fish, autopoiesis will cease and the fish will die. Granted, the cessation of autopoiesis is the immediate cause of death, but surely the shark is more than a mere ‘trigger’ for change.

References

  • Adler J, Tso W-W (1974) ’Decision’-making in bacteria: chemotactic response of Escherichia coli to conflicting stimuli. Science 184(4143):1292–2294

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Anolli L, Riva G et al (eds) (2005) The hidden structure of interaction: from neurons to culture patterns. Emerging communication: studies on new technologies and practices in communication. IOS Press, Amsterdam

  • Atkinson N (2004) Insect policing carries costs. The Scientist, BioMed Central

  • Bak P (1996) How nature works: the science of self-organized criticality. Copernicus/Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Balazs A (2004) What does a molecule want? The myth of the self-replicating molecule (comments on the "selfish-gene" paradigm). Biosystems 73(1):1–11

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Barham J (1996) A dynamical model of the meaning of information. Biosystems 38(2–2):235–541

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Bateson G (1979) Mind and nature: a necessary unity. E.P. Dutton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W (1998) Representations and cognitive explanations: assessing the dynamicist’s challenge in cognitive science. Cogn Sci 22(3):295–517

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W, Abrahamsen A (1990) Beyond the exclusively propositional era. Synthese 82(2):223–353

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel W, Abrahamsen A et al. (1998) The life of cognitive science. In: Bechtel W, Graham G (eds) A companion to cognitive science. Blackwell, Malden, pp 1–104

    Google Scholar 

  • Beer RD (1990) Intelligence as adaptive behavior: an experiment in computational neuroethology. Academic, San Diego

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (1980) Cognition, convention, and communication. Praeger Publishers, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH (1998) Levels of representationality. J Exp Theor Artif Intell 10(1998):179–915

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard MH, Terveen L (1995) Foundational issues in artificial intelligence and cognitive science: impasse and solution. Elsevier, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Bingham PM (2000) Human evolution and human history: a complete theory. Evol Anthropol: Issue News Rev 9(6):248–857

    Google Scholar 

  • Boden MA (ed) (1996). The philosophy of artificial life. Oxford Readings in Philosophy. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Brier S (2000) Biosemiotics as a possible bridge between embodiment in cognitive semantics and the motivation concept of animal cognition in ethology. Cybernet Human Know 7(1):57–75

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks R (1991) Intelligence without representation. Artif Intell 47(1–1):139–959

    Google Scholar 

  • Byrne RW, Barnard PJ et al. (2004) Understanding culture across species. Trends C Sc 8(8):341–146

    Google Scholar 

  • Cairns-Smith AG (1985) Seven clues to the origin of life. Cambridge University Press/Canto, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell DT (1974) Evolutionary epistemology. In: Schlipp PA (ed) The philosophy of Karl Popper. Open Court, La Salle, Ill., 1:413–363

  • Chalmers DJ (1996) The conscious mind. In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Cherniak C (1986) Minimal rationality. MIT Press/Bradford, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (1981) The case against B.F. Skinner. In: Bolles EB (ed) Galileo’s commandment. Abacus (Little, Brown and Company), London, pp 80–107

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen WD (2004) Self-directedness: a process approach to cognition. Axiomathes 14:171–189

    Google Scholar 

  • Christensen WD, Hooker CA (2000) Autonomy and the emergence of intelligence: organized interactive construction. Commun Cogn Artif Intell 17(3/4):133–357

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PS (1987) Epistemology in the age of neuroscience. J Philos 84:544–455

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland PM (1989) A neurocomputational perspective: the nature of mind and the structure of science. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Clapin H, Staines P et al (eds) (2004) Representation in mind: new approaches to mental representation. Perspectives on cognitive science. Elsevier, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1997a) Being there: putting brain, body and world back together again. MIT Press/Bradford, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark A (1997b) The dynamical challenge. Cogn Sci 21(4):461–181

    Google Scholar 

  • Cliff D, Noble J (1997) Knowledge-based vision and simple visual machines. Philos Trans: Biol Sci (R Soc Lond) 352:1165–5175

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Copeland BJ (1996) What is computation? Synthese 108(3):335–559

    Google Scholar 

  • Corning PA, Kline SJ (1998a) Thermodynamics, information and life revisited, Part I: ’To be or entropy’. Syst Res Be 15(4):273–395

    Google Scholar 

  • Corning PA, Kline SJ (1998b) Thermodynamics, information and life revisited, Part II: Thermoeconomics and control information. Syst Res Be 15(6):453–382

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane T (1998) Intentionality as the mark of the mental. In: O’Hear A (ed) Current issues in philosophy of mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 229–951

    Google Scholar 

  • Crist E (2002) The inner life of earthworms: Darwin’s argument and its implications. In: Bekoff M, Allen C, Burghardt G (eds) The cognitive animal: empirical and theoretical perspectives on animal cognition. MIT/Bradford Book, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Damasio AR (1999) The feeling of what happens, body and emotion in the making of consciousness. Harcourt Brace & Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin C (1874/1909) The descent of man. Selection in relation to sex. John Murray, London

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal FBM (2001) The ape and the sushi master. Cultural reflections by a primatologist, Allen Lane. The Penguin Press, London

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal FBM (2002) Evolutionary psychology: the wheat from the chaff. Curr Directions Psychol Sci 11(6):187–791

    Google Scholar 

  • Deacon TW (1997) The symbolic species: the co-evolution of language and the brain. W. W. Norton & Company, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1989) Cognitive ethology: hunting for bargains or a wild goose chase? In: Montefiore A, Noble D (ed) Goals, no-goals and own goals. A debate on goal-directed and intentional behavior. Unwin Hyman, London, pp 101–116

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1991) Consciousness explained. Penguin Books, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett DC (1996) Kinds of minds. Towards an understanding of consciousness. Weidenfeld & Nicolson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • di Primio F, Müller BS et al. (2000) Minimal cognition in unicellular organisms. In: SAB 2000, sixth international conference on the simulation of adaptive behaviour, Paris, International Society for Adaptive Behaviour

  • Dretske F (1988) Explaining behavior. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske F (2000) Perception, knowledge and belief: selected essays. Cambridge University press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupuy J-P (2000) The mechanization of the mind: on the origins of cognitive science. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Eder J, Rembold H (1992) Biosemiotics—a paradigm of biology. Naturwissenschaften 79:60–107

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Eigen M, Schuster P (1979) The hypercycle: a principle of natural self-organization. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche C (1998) Defining life as a semiotic phenomenon. Cybernet Human Know 5(1):3–37

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer JH, Freake MJ et al (2001) Evidence for the use of magnetic map information by an amphibian. Anim Behav 62(1):1–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor JA (1986) Why paramecia don’t have mental representations. Midwest Stud Philos X:3–33

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman WJ (1999) How brains make up their minds. Phoenix Paperback, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner H (1985) The mind’s new science: a history of the cognitive revolution. Basic Books, Inc., Publishers, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson JJ (1979) The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton Mifflin, Dallas

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (1996) Complexity and the function of mind in nature. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2003) Between Baldwin skepticism and Baldwin boosterism. In: Weber BH, Depew DJ (eds) Evolution and learning: the Baldwin effect reconsidered. MIT Press/Bradford, Cambridge, pp 53–37

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodson FE (2003) The evolution and function of cognition. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Inc., Mahwah, NJ

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray RD (1994) Sparrows, matching and the ideal free distribution - Can biological and psychological approaches be synthesized. Anim Behav 48(2):411–123

    Google Scholar 

  • Hammond RL, Keller L (2004) Conflict over male parentage in social insects. PLoS Biol 2(9):e248

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hardcastle VG (2001) Consciousness: chili of the brain. Conscious C 10:418–820

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Harnad S (1993) Problems, problems: the frame problem as a symptom of the symbol grounding problem. Psycholoquy 4(34):(11)

    Google Scholar 

  • Haselager P, de Groot A et al. (2003) Representationalism vs. anti-representationalism: a debate for the sake of appearance. Philos Psyc 16(1):5–53

    Google Scholar 

  • Haugeland J (1997) What is mind design? In: Haugeland J (ed) Mind design II: philosophy, psychology, artificial intelligence. MIT/Bradford, Cambridge, pp 1–18

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmeyer J, Emmeche C (1991) Code-duallity and the semiotics of nature. In: Anderson M, Merrell F (ed) On semiotic modeling. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 117–766

    Google Scholar 

  • Holmes B (2004) Manna or millstone. New Sci 183(2465):29–91

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull DL (2001) That just don’t sound right: a plea for real examples. In: Hull DL (ed) Science and selection: essays on biological evolution and the philosophy of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 196–621

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurley SL (1998) Consciousness in action. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl E (1952) Ideas: general introduction to a pure phenomenology. Allen & Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Jennings HS (1905/1962) Behavior of the lower organisms. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman S (2000) Investigations. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Keijzer F (2001) Representation and behavior. MIT Press/Bradford Book, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Kerepesi A, Jonsson GK et al (2005) Detection of temporal patterns in dog-human interaction. Behav Proc 70(1):69–99

    CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Kitano H (2002) Systems biology: a brief overview. Science 295(1 March 2002):1662–2664

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Koshland DE Jr (1980) Bacterial chemotaxis as a model behavioral system. Raven Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Kringelbach ML (2004) Food for thought: hedonic experience beyond homeostasis in the human brain. Neuroscience 126(4):807–719

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • La Cerra P, Bingham R (2002) The origin of minds. Harmony Books, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawton G (2004) Urban legends. New Sci 183(2465):32–25

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi-Strauss C (1969) The raw and the cooked. Harper & Row, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Lockery S (1989) Representation, functionalism, and simple living systems. In: Montefiore A, Noble D (eds) Goals, no-goals and own goals. A debate on goal-directed and intentional behaviour. Unwin Hyman, London, pp 117–758

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyon P (2004) Autopoiesis and knowing: reflections on Maturana’s biogenic explanation of cognition. Cybernet Human Know 11(4):21–16

    Google Scholar 

  • Lyon P (2005) Agent in the organism: toward a biogenic theory of cognition. PhD thesis, Australian National University (forthcoming)

  • Macnab RM, Koshland DE (1972) The gradient-sensing mechanism in bacterial chemotaxis. PNAS 69(9):2509–9512

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Macphail EM, Bolhuis JJ (2001) The evolution of intelligence: adaptive specialization versus general process. Biol Rev Camb Philos Soc 76(3):341–164

    PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Marahiel MA, Zuber P (1999) Sporulation and cell differentiation. In: Lengeler JW, Drews G, Schlegel HG (eds) Biology of the prokaryotes. Blackwell, New York, pp 586–601

    Google Scholar 

  • Margulis L (2001) The conscious cell. Ann N Y Acad Sci 929:55–50

    Article  PubMed  CAS  Google Scholar 

  • Martin E, Hine RS (eds) (2000) A dictionary of biology. Oxford Reference Paperback. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana HR (1970/1980) Biology of cognition. In: Maturana HR, Varela FJ (eds) Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, 42:1–18

  • Maturana HR (1990) The biological foundations of self-consciousness and the physical domain of existence. In: Luhmann N, Maturana HR, Namiki M, Redder V, Varela F (eds) Beobachter: Konvergenz der Erkenntnistheorien? Wilhelm Fink Verlag, Munich, pp 47–717

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana HR (2003) Autopoiesis, structural coupling and cognition: a history of these and other notions in the biology of cognition. Cybernet Human Know 9(3–3):5–54

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana HR, Varela FJ (1973/1980) Autopoiesis: the organization of the living. In: Maturana HR, Varela FJ (eds) Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, 42:59–938

  • Maturana HR, Varela FJ (1980) Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Boston, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Maturana HR, Varela FJ (1992) The tree of knowledge: the biological roots of human understanding. Shambala Publications Inc. Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Maynard Smith J, Szathmáry E (1999) The origins of life: from the birth of life to the origin of language. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • McCulloch WS, Pitts W (1943) A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. B Math Biophys 5:115–53

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty M (1962) Phenomenology of perception. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller GA (2003) The cognitive revolution: a historical perspective. Trends C Sc 7(3):141–144

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan RG (1989) Biosemantics. J Philos 86(6):281–197

    Google Scholar 

  • NIH (2001) Elucidation of the underlying mechanisms of placebo effect (research funding announcement), National Institues of Health (USA). 2001

  • Nordstrom K, Wallen R et al. (2003) A simple visual system without neurons in jellyfish larvae. P Roy Soc B 270(1531):2349–9354

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien G, Opie J (2004) Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation. In: Clapin H, Staines P, Slezak P (eds) Representation in mind: new approaches to mental representation. Elsevier, New York, pp 1–10

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson ET (1997) The human animal: personal identity without psychology. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Pattee HH (1969) How does a molecule become a message? Dev Biol Suppl 3:1–16

    Google Scholar 

  • Piaget J (1970) Genetic epistemology. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper KR (1965/1972) Of clouds and clocks: an approach to the problem of rationality and the freedom of man. In: Popper KR (ed) Objective knowledge. An evolutionary approach. Clarendom, Oxford, pp 206–655

    Google Scholar 

  • Prete FR. (ed) (2004) Complex worlds from simpler nervous systems. MIT Press/Bradford, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Prigogine I (1996) The end of certainty: time, chaos, and the new laws of nature. The Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam H (1988) Representation and reality. MIT Press/Bradford, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards RJ (1987) Darwin and the emergence of evolutionary theories of mind and behavior. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose S (1998) The rise of neurogenetic determinism. In: Cornwell J (ed) Consciousness and human identity. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 86–600

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen R (1985) Anticipatory systems: philosophical, mathematical, and methodological foundations. Pergamon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen R (2000) Essays on life itself. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg A (1986) Intention and action among the macromolecules. In: Rescher N (ed) Current issues in teleology. University Press of America, Lanham, pp 65–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheper WJ, Scheper GC (1996) Autopsies on autopoiesis. Behav Sci 41(1):3–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle JR (1981) Minds, brains, and programs. In: Hofstadter DR, Dennett DC (eds) The mind’s I. Penguin Books, London, pp 351–173

    Google Scholar 

  • Sebeok TA (ed) (1996) Advances in semiotics. Indiana University Press, Bloomington

    Google Scholar 

  • Shannon CE, Weaver W (1949) The mathematical theory of communication. University of Illinois Press, Urbana

    Google Scholar 

  • Silver BL (1998) The ascent of science. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2001) The evolution of agency and other essays. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny K (2003) Thought in a hostile world: the evolution of human cognition. Blackwell, Malden, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart J (1996) Cognition = life: implications for higher-level cognition. Behav Proc 35(1–1):311–126

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart J, Coutinho A (2004) The affirmation of self: a new perspective on the immune system. Artif Life 10(3):261–176

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Stich SP (1983) From folk psychology to cognitive science: the case against belief. MIT/Bradford, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Tebbich S, Bshary R (2004) Cognitive abilities related to tool use in the woodpecker finch, Cactospiza pallida. Anim Behav 67(4):689–997

    Google Scholar 

  • Trefil J (2003) The nature of science: an A-Z guide to the laws & principles governing our universe. Houghton Mifflin Company, Boston

    Google Scholar 

  • Turing AM (1936) On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proc Lond Math Soc 42(ser 2):230–305

    Google Scholar 

  • Varela FJ, Thompson E et al (1991) The embodied mind: cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Vertosick FTJ (2002) The genius within: discovering the intelligence of every living thing. Harcourt Inc, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bertalanffy L (1968) General system theory: foundations development applications. Penguin Books, Harmondsworth

    Google Scholar 

  • von Glasersfeld E (1997) Distinguishing the observer: an attempt at interpreting Maturana. Ecology of Mind, 2003

  • Washburn MF (1936) The animal mind: a text-book of comparative psychology. MacMillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein L (1953/1994) Philosophical investigations. Basil Blackwell Ltd., Oxford

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Jon Opie for his invaluable help in developing the anthropogenic/biogenic distinction, and to two anonymous reviewers whose comments greatly improved the paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Pamela Lyon.

Additional information

Communicated by John Sutton

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Lyon, P. The biogenic approach to cognition. Cogn Process 7, 11–29 (2006). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10339-005-0016-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10339-005-0016-8

Keywords

Navigation