Skip to main content
Log in

This is not an instance of (E)

  • S.I.: Minimalism about Truth
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Semantic paradoxes like the liar are notorious challenges to truth theories. A paradox can be phrased with minimal resources and minimal assumptions. It is not surprising, then, that the liar is also a challenge to minimalism about truth. Horwich (1998/1990) deals swiftly with the paradox, after discriminating between other strategies for avoiding it without compromising minimalism. He dismisses the denial of classical logic, the denial that the concept of truth can coherently be applied to propositions, and the denial that the liar sentence expresses a proposition, but he endorses the denial that the liar is an acceptable instance of the equivalence schema (E). This paper has two main parts. It first shows that Horwich’s preferred denial is also problematic. As Simmons (1999), Beall and Armour-Garb (2003), and Asay (2015) argued, the solution is ad hoc, faces a possible loss of expressibility, and is ultimately unstable. Finally, the paper explores a different combination of possibilities for minimalism: treating the truth-predicate as context-dependent, rejecting the notion that the liar expresses a proposition, and reinterpreting negation in some contexts as metalinguistic denial. The paper argues that these are preferable options, but signposts possible dangers ahead.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Various forms of deflationist views about truth were defended by Ramsey (1927), Ayer (1935), Strawson (1950), Quine (1970/1986), Field (1986, 1994), among others.

  2. See Horwich (1998/1990, pp. 2–3).

  3. For a good discussion on whether classical negation is compatible with a use-theoretic account of meaning, see Kürbis (2015).

  4. (Horwich 1998/1990, p. 72)

  5. See Horwich (1999, p. 72).

  6. See for example Field (2001, 2008).

  7. Soames (1999), for instance, took this as a motivation to argue that truth is a partially defined predicate. Another, perhaps less tempting, reaction, is to take the reasoning as showing what it seems to show: that indeed \(\langle \)(1) is not true\(\rangle \) is both true and not true as dialetheists assume. Several of the various options available are thoroughly explored in Field (2008). Many alternatives are not available to Horwich. On numerous occasions, he rejects the option of giving up classical logic or Bivalence because of non-referring terms (Horwich 1998/1990, p. 78), of vagueness (Horwich 1998/1990, p. 79), or of semantic paradoxes like the liar.

  8. As in, for instance, Tarski (1936), Kripke (1975).

  9. Horwich (2005, pp. 81–82, 2010, p. 91).

  10. Not all conceptual impossibilities are “semantically induced”. “Semantically induced” means that they arise, as in the present cases, from semantic notions or concepts, or are caused specifically by semantic indeterminacy or underdetermination.

  11. I’m grateful to an anonymous reviewer for pointing out the need to elaborate on the reply.

  12. Thanks to another anonymous reviewer for insisting on the clarification of this point.

  13. (Horwich 1998/1990, 72).

  14. (Horwich 2005, 81–82), (Horwich 2010, 91).

  15. I’ll use “make a statement” and “express a proposition” interchangeably for present purposes.

  16. Notice however that the reason why (23) is a FA is that the context of its use does not provide the required salient object of the ostensive demonstration. The failure to make a statement is explained by the semantics for ‘this’.

  17. I argued against using paradoxes as a reason to stipulate, or introduce, the semantic ambiguity of negation in [Author2008; Author2010].

  18. For a discussion of affixal negation, see for instance Horn (2001, Sect. 5.1).

  19. Ripley (2011) points to other problems that arise for the idea that negation and denial are separate independent phenomena.

  20. In fact, in the first footnote of his paper, Kripke says “I have chosen to take sentences as the primary truth vehicles not because I think that the objection that truth is primarily a property of propositions (or “statements”) is irrelevant to serious work on truth or to the semantic paradoxes...Occasionally we may speak as if every utterance of a sentence in the language makes a statement, although below we suggest that a sentence may fail to make a statement if it is paradoxical or ungrounded”(Kripke 1975, fn 1).

  21. It is worth noting that Sorensen (2001) denies Lewis’s insight that truths must supervene on what exists, and defends the claim that there are truths with no truthmakers, i.e., that there are truthmaker gaps. I briefly discuss this below at the end.

  22. Lewis further develops the principle in Lewis (2001).

References

  • Asay, J. (2015). Epistemicism and the liar. Synthese, 192(3), 679–699.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ayer, A. J. (1935). The criterion of truth. Analysis, 3(1/2), 28–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barker, S. J. (2000). Is value content a component of conventional implicature? Analysis, 60(267), 268–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J. C. (2001). A neglected deflationist approach to the liar. Analysis, 61(270), 126–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J. C., & Armour-Garb, B. (2003). Should deflationists be dialetheists? Noûs, 37(2), 303–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beall, J. C., & Armour-Garb, B. (2005). Deflationism and paradox. In J. C. Beall & B. Armour-Garb (Eds.), Deflationism and paradox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1937). The logical syntax of language. London: K. Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co. Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (1996). Metalinguistic negation and echoic use. Journal of Pragmatics, 25, 309–330.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carston, R. (1998). Negation, ‘presupposition’ and the semantics/ pragmatics distinction. Journal of Linguistics, 34, 309–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, E. (1985). Arithmetic and fact. In I. Hacking (Ed.), Exercises in analysis. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1986). The deflationary conception of truth. In G. MacDonald & C. Wright (Eds.), Fact, science and morality (pp. 55–117). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (1994). Deflationist views of meaning and content. Mind, 103(411), 249–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. (2001). Saving the truth schema from paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 31(1), 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Field, H. H. (2008). Saving truth from paradox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, B. (1998). The mechanisms of denial. Language, 74(2), 274–307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, L. (2000). A unified solution to some paradoxes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 100(1), 53–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, L. (2001). Truth-bearers and the liar—a reply to Alan Weir. Analysis, 61(2), 115–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herzberger, H. G. (1970). Paradoxes of grounding in semantics. Journal of Philosophy, 67(6), 145–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. (2001). A natural history of negation (Reissue ed.). CSLI.

  • Horwich, P. (1998). Meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (1998/1990). Truth (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Horwich, P. (1999). The minimalist conception of truth. In S. Blackburn & K. Simmons (Eds.), Truth. Oxford University Press.

  • Horwich, p. (2005). A minimalist critique of Tarski on truth. In J. C. Beall & B. Armour-Garb (Eds.), Deflationism and paradox (pp. 75–84). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (2008). Being and truth. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 32(1), 258–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horwich, P. (2010). Truth-meaning-reality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, H. K. Wettstein, & D. Kaplan (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C., & McNally, L. (2005). Scale structure and the semantic typology of gradable predicates. Language, 81(2), 1–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kürbis, N. (2015). What is wrong with classical negation? Grazer Philosophische Studien, 92, 51–86.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. A. (1975). Outline of a theory of truth. Journal of Philosophy, 72(19), 690–716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1980). Index, context, and content. In Philosophy and grammar (pp. 79–100). Dordrecht: Reidel.

  • Lewis, D. (1999). Armstrong on combinatorial possibility. In Papers in metaphysics and epistemology (Vol. 2, pp. 196–214). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Lewis, D. (2001). Truthmaking and difference-making. Noûs, 35(4), 602–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1998). Papers in philosophical logic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Parsons, T. (1984). Assertion, denial, and the liar paradox. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 13(2), 137–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1999). Being known. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1970/1986). Philosophy of logic. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • Ramsey, F. P. (1927). Facts and propositions. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 7(1), 153–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ripley, D. (2011). Negation, denial, and rejection. Philosophy Compass, 6(9), 622–629.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, K. (1999). Deflationary truth and the liar. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 28(5), 455–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soames, S. (1999). Understanding truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, R. (1988). Blindspots. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sorensen, R. (2001). Vagueness and contradiction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. Syntax and semantics (Vol. 9, pp. 315–332). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (2002). Common ground. Linguistics and Philosophy, 25(5–6), 701–721.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (2014). Context. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1950). Truth. Aristotelian Society Supplementary, 24, 111–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tappenden, J. (1999). Negation, denial, and language change in philosophical logic. In D. Gabbay & H. Wansing (Eds.), What is negation? (pp. 261–298). Berlin: Springer.

  • Tarski, A. (1936). The concept of truth in formalized languages. In A. Tarski (Ed.), Logic, semantics, metamathematics (pp. 152–278). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valor Abad, J., & Martínez Fernández, J. (2009). A failed “cassatio”: Goldstein on the liar. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 109, 327–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (1994). Vagueness. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1994/1922). Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus (Trans. Pears & McGuinness). London: Routledge.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I’m very grateful to Joe Ulatowski and to Cory Wright; I’m also grateful to José Martínez, Jordi Valor, Manuel García-Carpintero, and to Peter Sullivan, for the discussion of some of the problems covered in this paper. This work was supported by an FP7 Marie Curie Action, Grant Agreement Number: PIEF-GA-2012-622114; Grup de Recerca Consolidat en Filosofia del Dret, 2014 SGR 626, AGAUR de la Generalitat de Catalunya; project About Ourselves FFI2013-47948-P, Spanish Ministry for Economy.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Teresa Marques.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Marques, T. This is not an instance of (E). Synthese 195, 1035–1063 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1293-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1293-8

Keywords

Navigation