Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

The unity of neuroscience: a flat view

  • S.I.: Neuroscience and Its Philosophy
  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper offers a novel view of unity in neuroscience. I set out by discussing problems with the classical account of unity-by-reduction, due to Oppenheim and Putnam. That view relies on a strong notion of levels, which has substantial problems. A more recent alternative, the mechanistic “mosaic” view due to Craver, does not have such problems. But I argue that the mosaic ideal of unity is too minimal, and we should, if possible, aspire for more. Relying on a number of recent works in theoretical neuroscience—network motifs, canonical neural computations (CNCs) and design-principles—I then present my alternative: a “flat” view of unity, i.e. one that is not based on levels. Instead, it treats unity as attained via the identification of recurrent explanatory patterns, under which a range of neuroscientific phenomena are subsumed. I develop this view by recourse to a causal conception of explanation, and distinguish it from Kitcher’s view of explanatory unification and related ideas. Such a view of unity is suitably ambitious, I suggest, and has empirical plausibility. It is fit to serve as an appropriate working hypothesis for 21st century neuroscience.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Oppenheim and Putnam do address the worry that “some things do not belong at any level” (Ibid, p. 11). But the case they discuss (“a man in a phone booth”) is, by their own lights, uninteresting from a scientific view-point and they thus conclude that “the problem posed by such [cases] is not serious...” (Ibid). The problems Kim alludes to are, however, interesting and serious.

  2. For a vivid example of this way of thinking about levels—see the image in Churchland and Sejnowski (1988, p. 16).

  3. A related argument is made by Potochnick and McGill (2012, p. 131) with respect to pheromones.

  4. I add the qualifier ‘direct’ for in a sufficiently broad and indirect sense, almost anything interacts with anything else. But that would not make for a useful notion of levels.

  5. For more on action potentials and the mechanistic outlook see (Levy 2014).

  6. Several authors with mechanist leaning have developed views of the relation between different parts of science in terms of theoretical integration. See for instance Darden and Maull (1977), Bechtel (1984), and Craver and Darden (2013, Ch. 10). These views are kindred spirits to Craver’s, as he himself notes. But as my discussion is geared towards understanding unity within a domain, namely neuroscience, and as I do not presuppose that what holds for neuroscience holds in other cases, or vice versa, I will not discuss inter-field integration here.

  7. The mosaic can, in principle, encompass synergies of a non-evidential sort—for instance by mutually supportive explanations (where one field explains one aspect of a process or system, another field a different aspect), synergistic experimental techniques (e.g. recording from a cell while a subject performs a behavioral task) and so on. These kinds of aspects are emphasized in (Darden and Maull 1977) and in (Craver and Darden 2013)

  8. PR involves a change in the period of an oscillatory pattern of firing within a neuronal population, resulting in the amplification or dampening of further incoming stimuli, depending on where in the (reset) phase they “hit”.

  9. The references to design, here and in the book’s title, are not incidental. Sterling and Laughlin believe that many of the principles stem from the design-like character of natural selection, and appeal to many ideas from electrical engineering, computer science and related areas in the course of the book. In this respect too there are similarities between this approach and the motifs and CNC cases discussed earlier, in which the notion of design plays a central motivating role. But a discussion of this interesting connection won’t be possible here.

  10. This is not to say they are mechanistic explanations—a matter which is controversial, especially with regards to CNCs (Chirimuuta 2014). But this will not make a difference here.

  11. As noted in footnote 10, part of the motivation for work on motifs, CNCs, and design principles such Sparsify is the thought that they are subject to constraints akin to those under which engineered (manmade) devices are made. From this point of view, the prospect of a unified account of neural systems and, say, the internet is not problematic. It is a prediction of such approaches and its confirmation supports it.

References

  • Alon, U. (2007). Network motifs: Theory and experimental approaches. Nature Reviews Genetics, 8, 450–461.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, M. & Casini, L. (forthcoming). An abductive theory of constitution. Philosophy of Science.

  • Bechtel, W., & Craver, C. F. (2006). Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biology & Philosophy, 22, 547–563.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W. (1984). Reconceptualization and interfield connections: The discovery of the link between vitamins and coenzymes. Philosophy of Science, 51, 265–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bechtel, W., & Hamilton, A. (2007). Reduction, integration, and the unity of science: Natural, behavioral, and social sciences and the humanities. In T. Kuipers (Ed.), Philosophy of Science: Focal Issues. New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bialek, W. (2012). Biophysics: Searching for principles. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carandini, M., & Heeger, D. J. (2012). Normalization as a canonical neural computation. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 13, 51–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1999). The dappled world: A study of the boundaries of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cat, J. (2013). In In E. N. Zalta (ed.), The unity of science. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/scientific-unity/.

  • Chirimuuta, M. (2014). Minimal models and canonical neural computations: The distinctness of computational explanation in neuroscience. Synthese, 191(2), 127–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S., & Sejnowski, T. J. (1988). The computational brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C. F. (2007). Explaining the brain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Craver, C., & Darden, L. (2013). In search of mechanisms: Discoveries across the life sciences. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L., & Maull, N. (1977). Interfield theories. Philosophy of Science, 43, 44–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupré, J. (1993). The disorder of things: Metaphysical foundations of the disunity of science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eronen, M. I. (2013). No levels, no problems: Downward causation in neuroscience. Philosophy of Science, 80(5), 1042–1052.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eronen, M. I. (2014). Levels of organization: A deflationary account. Biology & Philosophy, 30(1), 39–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glennan, S. (2010). Mechanisms causes and the layered model of the world. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, LXXX, I(2), 362–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harbecke, J. (2015). The regularity theory of mechanistic constitution and a methodology for constitutive inference. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part C, 54, 10–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (2002/2010). The layered world: Metaphysical considerations. Essays in the metaphysics of mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Kitcher, P. (1981). Explanatory unification. Philosophy of Science, 48, 507–531.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher & W. C. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A. (2014). What was Hodgkin and Huxley’s achievement? British Journal for Philosophy of Science, 65(3), 469–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, A., & Bechtel, W. (2013). Abstraction and the organization of mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 80(2), 241–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, & Li,. (2013). Stochastic resonance in feedforward-loop neuronal network motifs in astrocyte field. Journal of Theoretical Biology, 335, 265–275.

  • Marder, E. (2012). Neuromodulation of neuronal circuits: Back to the future. Neuron, 76(1), 1–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McShea, D. (1991). Complexity: What everyone knows. Biology & Philosophy, 6, 303–324.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olsen, S. R., Bhandawat, V., & Wilson, R. I. (2008). Divisive normalization in olfactory population codes. Neuron, 66, 287–299.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheim, P., & Putnam, H. (1958). The unity of science as a working hypothesis. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 2, 3–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oshiro, T., Angelaki, D. E., & DeAngelis, G. C. (2011). A normalization model of multisensory integration. Nature Neuroscience, 14, 775–782.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potochnick, A., & McGill, B. (2012). The limitations of hierarchical organization. Philosophy of Science, 79(1), 120–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sompolinski, H. (2014). Computational neuroscience: Beyond the local circuit. Current Opinion in Neurosciencȩ, 25, 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sporns, O. (2010). Networks of the brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sporns, O., & Kötter, R. (2004). Motifs in brain networks. PLos Biology, 2(11), e369.

  • Sterling, P., & Laughlin, S. (2015). Principles of neural design. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Atteveldt, N., Murray, M. M., Thut, G., & Schroeder, C. E. (2014). Multisensory integration: Flexible use of general operations. Neuron, 81(6), 1240–1253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, R. I. (2013). Early olfactory processing in Drosophila: Mechanisms and principles. Annual Reviews in Neuroscience, 36, 217–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1976a). Reductionism, levels of organization, and the mind-body problem. In I. Savodnik (Ed.), Consciousness and the brain: A acientific and philosophical inquiry (pp. 202–267). New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of scientific explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Arnon Levy.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Levy, A. The unity of neuroscience: a flat view. Synthese 193, 3843–3863 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1256-0

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-016-1256-0

Keywords

Navigation