Skip to main content
Log in

Explanation, understanding, and control

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

There is a recent interest within both philosophy of science as well as within epistemology to provide a defensible account of understanding. In the present article I build on insights from previous work in attempt to provide an account of two related forms of understanding in terms of the ability to form rational intentions when using specific types of mental representations. I propose first that “understanding that X” requires that one form a representation of X and, further, that one must be capable of forming rational intentions using this representation across a range of conceivable conditions. I then propose that “understanding why X” requires that one possess a representation of a successful explanation for why X, and that one must be similarly capable of forming rational intentions using this representation across a range of conceivable conditions. I conclude the manuscript by reviewing objections and considering the way this account relates to other literature on explanation and understanding.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Dieks (2009) also offers a contextualist (and pluralist) response with regard to this debate about relativity. He argues that there is no uniquely best way to explain these relativistic effects, and that the difference between geometric and dynamic explanations lies in the ways we use them within the same overarching theoretical framework. That is, the differences on Dieks’ view are pragmatic in that they relate to our specific interests and decided emphases in the context of the questions we are asking.

References

  • Avigad, J. (2010). Understanding, formal verification, and the philosophy of mathematics. Journal of the Indian Council of Philosophical Research, 27, 161–197.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balashov, Y., & Janssen, M. (2003). Presentism and relativity. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54, 327–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. (1986). Advertisement for a semantics for psychology. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 10(1), 615–678. doi:10.1111/j.1475-4975.1987.tb00558.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H. (2005). Physical relativity: Space–time structure from a dynamical perspective. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, H., & Pooley, O. (2006). Minkowski space–time: A glorious non-entity. In D. Dieks (Ed.), The ontology of spacetime (pp. 67–89). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • De Regt, H. (2009). Understanding and scientific explanation. In H. De Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Regt, H., & Dieks, D. (2005). A contextual approach to scientific understanding. Synthese, 144(1), 137–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dieks, D. (2009). Understanding in physics: Bottom-up versus top-down. In H. De Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific understanding: Philosophical perspectives. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. (1981). Knowledge and the flow of information. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elgin, C. (2009). Is understanding factive? In A. Haddock, A. Millar, & D. H. Pritchard (Eds.), Epistemic value (pp. 322–330). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1995). The elm and the expert: Mentalese and its semantics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A., & Lepore, E. (1991). Why meaning (probably) isn’t conceptual role. Mind and Language, 6(4), 328–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2009). Theory and reality: An introduction to the philosophy of science (pp. 190–201). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, M., & Harman, G. (2005). Conceptual role semantics. UCLA Public Law Series (September 1 2005), 5–16. UCLA School of Law.

  • Grimm, S. (2006). Is understanding a species of knowledge? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57(3), 515–535.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. (2010). The goal of understanding. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 41(4), 337–344.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grimm, S. (2012). Understanding as knowledge of causes. In A. Fairweather (Ed.), Virtue scientia: Essays in philosophy of science and virtue epistemology. New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C., & Oppenheim, P. (1948). Studies in the logic of explanation. Philosophy of Science, 15(2), 135–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K. (2012). Inaugurating understanding or repackaging explanation? Philosophy of Science, 79(1), 15–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khalifa, K., & Gadomski, M. (2013). Understanding as explanatory knowledge: The case of Bjorken scaling. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44(3), 384–392.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In P. Kitcher & W. Salmon (Eds.), Scientific explanation (pp. 410–505). Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. (2007). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kvanvig, J. (2009). The value of understanding. In A. Haddock & D. H. Pritchard (Eds.), Epistemic value (pp. 95–111). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2009). Why proofs by mathematical induction are generally not explanatory. Analysis, 69(2), 203–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lange, M. (2013). What makes a scientific explanation distinctively mathematical? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 64(3), 485–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, M. (2012). An inferential model of scientific understanding. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 26(1), 1–26. doi:10.1080/02698595.2012.653118.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, M. (2013). Refining the inferential model of scientific understanding. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 27(2), 173–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Newman, M. (2014). EMU and inference: What the explanatory model of scientific understanding ignores. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 4, 55–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. (2002). Furnishing the mind: Concepts and their perceptual basis. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1971). Statistical explanation and statistical relevance. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skow, B. (2013). Are there non-causal explanations (of particular events)? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1093/bjps/axs047.

  • Strevens, M. (2013). No understanding without explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 44(3), 510–515.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J. (2002). Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 69(2), 212–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J. (2005). Paying the price for a theory of explanation: De Regt’s discussion of Trout. Philosophy of Science, 72(1), 198–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J. (2007). The psychology of scientific explanation. Philosophy Compass, 2(3), 564–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilkenfeld, D. (2013). Understanding as representation manipulability. Synthese, 190, 997–1016.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. Making things happen a theory of causal explanation (Vol. 14). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author would like to acknowledge and thank Richard Healey for his thoughtful comments and feedback on this manuscript.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ryan Smith.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Smith, R. Explanation, understanding, and control. Synthese 191, 4169–4200 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0521-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-014-0521-3

Keywords

Navigation