Skip to main content

Why Is Attributive “Heavy” Distributive?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Semantics of Plurals, Focus, Degrees, and Times

Abstract

Schwarzschild (2006, 2011) observes that adjectives like heavy are obligatorily distributive when attributive, but not when predicative. He proposes a non-monotonicity requirement on attributive modification which rules out the collective reading: because the dimension of weight is not allowed to be monotonic on the part–whole relation determined by the noun phrase, and a collective reading of attributive heavy will be monotonic, only the distributive reading is available. Here, we propose that non-monotonicity follows from the independently determined distributivity of certain attributive adjectives. In addition to dimension adjectives like heavy, evaluative adjectives like pretty also result in obligatory distributive readings when in attributive position, while allowing collective readings when predicative, despite the fact that they are non-monotonic on both readings. Other adjectives, e.g., numerous, are collective in attributive position, despite being monotonic. We propose that the requisite distributive reading with attributive heavy (and pretty) stems independently of non-monotonicity, and is due to the particular way the adjective’s comparison class is interpreted in the attributive position; the non-monotonicity of attributive heavy is then a consequence of distributivity.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    From now on, for reasons of brevity, when we say that an adjective is (non-)monotonic, we mean that the adjectival dimension is (non-)monotonic on the part–whole relation in the domain given by the noun phrase.

  2. 2.

    Word order is reversed in two particular constructions (see Ionin and Matushansky 2004; Solt 2007), which differs from (13b) in the presence of an article. Notably, the attributive adjective heavy has a collective interpretation:

    figure g

    The interpretation here is that the collection of boxes is heavy (the sentence is true even in the case where each box is light, but together the boxes weigh 30 lbs.).

    Kayne (2005) shows that a similar construction is possible involving both an attributive and a Q adjective in the reverse linear order (again, note the presence of the article):

    figure h

    On Kayne’s account, the adjective modifies a null quantity noun NUMBER, whose pseudo-partitive complement the lexical noun boxes is:

    figure i

    Extending this account to (i) would yield a null AMOUNT OF:

    figure j

    We also observe that higher syntactic placement of the attributive adjective results in the return of the collective/distributive ambiguity for dimension adjectives (Ouwayda 2011).

    figure k

    We take this to be a case of the same type of construction as in (i)—note the contrast in (vi)—and so a parallel structure to that of (iv) would be appropriate, as in (vii):

    figure l

    Such examples are thus not a counterexample to Schwarzschild’s generalization.

  3. 3.

    We note, however, that a search of Corpus of Contemporary American English Davies (2008) reveals several such examples. The presence of the expected worth (e.g., fifty-dollars-worth of gas) is apparently optional.

    figure o
  4. 4.

    Jessica Rett (p.c.) observes that when (17b) is in the present tense (They are expensive) the distributive reading is the only available reading. We agree that there is a difference between the present and the future in this respect, although the collective reading is not completely ruled out under our intuitions. We don’t know why the future allows a collective reading more easily than the present.

  5. 5.

    We use the term “dimensional” to refer to a subset of relative adjectives. Dimensional adjectives are associated with quantity scales such as length, weight, size. They come in antonym pairs, e.g., tallshort, widenarrow, heavylight, and the positive dimensional adjectives can typically be modified by conventional measure phrases: 6 ft tall, 4 cm wide. “Evaluative” adjectives like pretty, expensive, strong, lazy are also relative, but they are linked to quality scales, and often to more than one scale and so they don’t all have single antonyms, and they also are not associated with conventional measure phrases. See Bierwisch (1989).

  6. 6.

    As noted by Partee (1989), in the presence of the (as in (20b)), many only has a cardinal reading. The same is true for several and numeral determiners.

  7. 7.

    It has been argued that absolute adjectives also depend on a comparison class (van Rooij 2011; Toledo and Sassoon 2011) but not of the kind that can be expressed by a for-phrase as the one in (32)–(33). On Toledo and Sassoon’s (2011) account, absolute adjectives have a comparison class comprised of counterparts of the individual of which the adjective is predicated. Such a “counterpart” comparison class is incompatible with the extensional category generally referenced by for-phrases such as for a wine bottle. For-phrases that can co-occur with absolute adjectives have different form, and according to Toledo and Sassoon, reference individual counterparts (see (i) and (ii), Toledo and Sassoon’s 2011: ex. (24), (25)).

    figure ab
  8. 8.

    Different types of for-phrases may combine with gradable adjectives, not all of them expressing a comparison class (see Bylinina 2012). Other tests to distinguish between relative and absolute adjectives are discussed in Kennedy and McNally (2005), Kennedy (2007), Toledo and Sassoon (2011).

  9. 9.

    Ludlow (1989) also notes that predicative adjectives can have a comparison class that is more general than the denotation of the NP of the subject of predication. This is particularly clear in cases like (i), which, read generically, cannot limit the comparison class to elephants.

    figure ad

    He also notes a contrast with cases when the domain of quantification is restricted: in (ii) the comparison class is most naturally interpreted as being limited to elephants.

    figure ae

    What matters to us is that predicative adjectives allow wider settings of their comparison class, as in (i), in contrast to attributive adjectives, where the comparison class is fixed by the modified NP.

  10. 10.

    We do not discuss here nonlocal for-phrases as in (i) (from Schwarz 2010). The challenge with such examples is to determine how the comparison class set by the overt for-phrase interacts with the implicit comparison class associated with the positive attributive adjective.

    figure af
  11. 11.

    De Clercq (2008) discusses agreement patterns in object-denoting proper names used as common nouns (PUCs), as in (i), which is based on a personal proper name, and (ii), which is based on a brand name.

    figure ai

    De Clercq notes that German provides evidence for the underlying presence of a common noun in PUCs as the article varies in gender depending on the gender of the non-overt noun:

    figure aj

    In Belgian Dutch the article in such cases is invariably masculine, agreeing neither with the proper name nor with the likely underlying common noun. This complicates the analysis of the morphosyntax of the null expression that De Clercq posits, but for our purposes the details are immaterial, since we are focusing on the semantic effects.

  12. 12.

    In McKinney-Bock (2013) the comparison class is introduced by a deg head that is separate from pos. The advantage of this proposal is that the same pos can be used in combination with relative and absolute adjectives. We have made the simplified move to have a single quantifier, pos. Furthermore, on McKinney-Bock’s account, the covert comparison class-denoting argument is a syntactically complex expression, a for-phrase with an elided NP, whose content is recovered under identity with the attributively modified noun phrase, i.e., it is a case of ellipsis resolution. As our goals in this paper are different, we do not adopt this particular proposal, but we note that it would be compatible with our account of attributive relative adjectives. We also note that there are several counterarguments to the (abstract) pos morpheme (Rett 2015), and our account of attributive relative adjectives does not depend on the existence of the morpheme pos; the formal weight could be carried in another way.

  13. 13.

    We use interval semantics following McKinney-Bock (2013), although this is not crucial for our argument.

  14. 14.

    The lexical entry in (45) is from Heim (1999), updated to work with the interval semantics for gradable adjectives we assume here.

  15. 15.

    A pragmatic restriction to singularities has been suggested by Stateva (2005) for distributive readings of plural superlatives (e.g., the interpretation of John and Bill are the tallest students as Each of John and Bill is taller than any other (relevant) student). Plural superlatives also allow group readings, perhaps less saliently, see Fitzgibbons et al. (2008).

  16. 16.

    The other types of generic sentences are direct kind predications, in which indefinite singulars cannot participate, as in (i)–(ii).

    figure au

    The nominal phrases in direct kind predications (definite singulars and bare plurals) are standardly assumed to denote kinds, while the nominal phrases in characterizing generics (indefinite singulars and bare plurals) are assumed to denote predicates restricting a generic operator. Because definite singulars cannot occur in comparison class denoting for-phrases (e.g., * for the first-grader) we assume that the bare plurals that do occur (e.g., for wine bottles) are characterizing generic nominals rather than kinds. This is important because direct kind predications may express collective generalizations, as in (i)/(ii) and (iii)/(iv):

    figure av
  17. 17.

    A reviewer notes that prototypicality may not quite be the notion we need, given that not all NPs have prototypes, citing as examples “male nurse”, “non-Methodist”, “resident”. We acknowledge that this is a complex issue, but ultimately it is not essential for us to resolve: whatever notion best captures the semantics of characterizing generics is what is involved in comparison classes of relative adjectives.

    Additionally, the same reviewer points out the following intuition.

    figure ax

    In this example, the speaker has never had an experience of eating dragon fruit before, and so has no concept of a prototypical dragon fruit. The reviewer suggests that the comparison class in the above example is not restricted to the denotation of the NP, but instead to the speaker’s experience of eating foods (other than dragon fruit).

    We agree with the intuition in (i). At first, this appears to challenge Higginbotham’s generalization that attributive adjectives are interpreted relative to the head noun, but we believe this is not the case. Given the context in (i), the sentence is only felicitous when the adjective has a pitch accent/ is focused. Adjectives with focus are interpreted relative to other comparison classes than the default, possibly because they are in higher position within the nominal phrase (McKinney-Bock 2013, see also footnote 1), and so for focused adjectives like heavy the collective reading returns.

  18. 18.

    Since pos presupposes that its individual argument is a member of the comparison class, see (48), prototypicality will be ascribed to that argument by the presupposition.

  19. 19.

    The for-phrases that appear with numerous are of the type that are licensed with absolute adjectives as well, as we discussed in footnote 7. Consider (i) and (ii).

    figure bd
  20. 20.

    Numerous predicates only over pluralities, and to the extent that it allows distributive readings it distributes to sub-pluralities that are non-atomic. Champollion (2015) claims that sum predicates have distributive readings with numerous (a judgment that is not shared by several speakers who we consulted):

    figure bf

    Additionally, a Google search returns several hits that contain both many and possibly distributive numerous.

    figure bg

    However, several other results show that numerous can co-occur with many in a context that is clearly not distributive.

    figure bh

    Here, numerous seems to be modifying a dimension of density or frequency (according to our intuitions about these sentences). The stores are both many in number and numerous because they occur in clusters (and the same for nests in trees, or waterfalls along a hiking track).

  21. 21.

    On the semantics of many see Rett (2014), Solt (2015), a.o.

  22. 22.

    Although, plentiful and sparse can also appear in a pseudo-partitive structure, as revealed in the following examples.

    figure bl

    This raises the possibility that there is an analysis of numerous as well where it realizes a pseudo-partitive structure with a null NUMBER (a la Kayne 2005).

References

  • Bale, A. (2011). Scales and comparison classes. Natural Language Semantics, 19, 169–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartsch, R., & Theo Vennemann (1972). The grammar of relative adjectives and comparison. Linguistische Berichte, 20, 19–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bierwisch, M. (1989). The semantics of gradation. In M. Bierwisch & E. Lang (Eds.), Dimensional adjectives. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bolinger, D. (1967). Adjectives in English: Attribution and predication. Lingua, 18, 1–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bresnan, J. (1973). Syntax of the comparative clause construction in English. Linguistic Inquiry, 4, 275–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bylinina, L. (2012). Functional standards and the absolute/relative distinction. Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung, 16, 141–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Champollion, L. (2015). The common core of distributivity, aspect and measurement. In Talk at Munich Center for Mathematical Philosophy, 7 January 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cresswell, M. (1977). The semantics of degree. In P. Barbara (Ed.), Montague Grammar. Academic Press. New York, NY.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M. (2008). The corpus of contemporary American English (COCA): 560 million words, 1990-present. Available online at https://corpus.byu.edu/coca/.

  • De Clercq, K. (2008). Proper names used as common nouns in Belgian Dutch and German. Ms. Ghent University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fitzgibbons, N., Sharvit, Y., & Gajewski, J. (2008). Plural superlatives and distributivity. Proceedings of SALT, 18, 302–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graff, D. (2000). Shifting sands: An interest-relative theory of vagueness. Philosophical Topics, 28(1), 45–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1999). Notes on superlatives. MIT, Cambridge: Manuscript.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyer, G. (1990). Semantics and knowledge representation in the analysis of generic descriptions. Journal of Semantics, 7, 93–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Higginbotham, J. (1985). On semantics. Linguistic Inquiry, 16, 547–594.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ionin, T., & Matushansky, O. (2004). The composition of complex cardinals. Journal of Semantics, 23, 315–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kayne, R. (2005). A note on the syntax of quantity in English. In Movement and silence (pp. 73–98). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C. (1999). Projecting the adjective: The syntax and semantics of gradability and comparison. Garland Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C., & McNally, L. (2005). Scale structure, degree modification, and the semantics of gradable predicates. Language, 81, 345–381.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, C. (2007). Vagueness and grammar: The semantics of relative and absolute gradable adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 30, 1–45.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, E. (1980). A semantics for positive and comparative adjectives. Linguistics and Philosophy, 4, 1–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Landman, F. (2011). Count nouns, mass nouns, neat nouns, mess nouns. In Formal Semantics and Pragmatics: Discourse Context and Models: The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication (p. 6).

    Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, S.-J., & Lerner, A. (2016). Generic generalizations. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ludlow, P. (1989). Implicit comparison classes. Linguistics and Philosophy, 12(4), 519–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McKinney-Bock. (2013). An argument for interval semantics of gradable adjectives. In S. Keine & S. Sloggett (Eds.), Proceedings of the 42nd Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society. Amherst, MA: GLSA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morzycki, M. (2014, December 5). The landscape of nonlocal readings of adjectives. University of Maryland.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nickel, B. (2008). Generics and the way of normality. Linguistics and Philosophy, 31(6), 629–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ouwayda, S. (2011). Cardinals, agreement and plurality in Lebanese Arabic. Sinn und Bedeutung (SuB), 16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Partee, B. (1989). Many quantifiers. In The 5th Eastern States Conference on Linguistics (pp. 383–402). Reprinted in Partee, B. (2004). Compositionality in formal semantics (pp. 241–258). Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penka, D. (to appear). One many, many readings. Proceedings of Sinn und Bedeutung, 21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rett, J. (2014). The polysemy of measurement. Lingua, 143, 242–266.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rett, J. (2015). The semantics of evaluativity. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Rooij, R. (2011). Vagueness and linguistics. In G. Ronzitti (Ed.), Vagueness: A guide. Logic, Epistemology, and the Unity of Science Series (Vol. 19, pp. 123–170).

    Google Scholar 

  • von Stechow, A. (1984). Comparing semantic theories of comparison. Journal of Semantics, 3, 1–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rothstein, S., & Winter, Y. (2004). Total adjectives vs. partial adjectives: Scale structure and higher-order modifiers. Natural Language Semantics, 12, 259–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sauerland, U., & Yatsushiro, J. (2005). The plural is semantically unmarked. In S. Kepser & M. Reis (Eds.), Linguistic evidence. de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarz, B. (2010). A note on for-phrases and derived scales. Sinn und Bedeutung (SuB), 15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, R. (2006). The role of dimensions in the syntax of noun phrases. Syntax, 9, 67–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, R. (2011). Stubborn distributivity, multiparticipant nouns and the count/mass distinction. In S. Lima, K. Mullin, & B. Smith (Eds.), Proceedings of the 39th Meeting of the North East Linguistic Society (Vol. 2, pp. 661–678). Amherst, MA: GLSA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schwarzschild, R. (2015). Excess baggage. In UCLA Colloquium, 9 October 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solt, S. (2007). Two types of modified cardinals. In International Conference on Adjectives, Lille, France. 13–15 September 2007.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solt, S. (2015). Q-adjectives and the semantics of quantity. Journal of Semantics, 32, 221–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stateva, P. (2005). Presuppositions in superlatives. Berlin: Ms. ZAS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toledo, A., & Sassoon, G. (2011). Absolute vs. relative adjectives: Variance within vs. between individuals. Proceedings of SALT, 21, 135–154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The inspiration for this work was Roger Schwarzschild’s widely influential paper on the syntax of measurement (Schwarzschild 2006). Many thanks to Roger for his insights, on paper and in conversation. We are also indebted to Jim Higginbotham for discussion over the years, without which our understanding of adjectives would not be the same. Thanks to Jessica Rett and an anonymous reviewer for insightful comments. An early version of this work was presented at SALT 2012.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding authors

Correspondence to Katy McKinney-Bock or Roumyana Pancheva .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2019 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

McKinney-Bock, K., Pancheva, R. (2019). Why Is Attributive “Heavy” Distributive?. In: Altshuler, D., Rett, J. (eds) The Semantics of Plurals, Focus, Degrees, and Times. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-04438-1_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-04438-1_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-030-04437-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-030-04438-1

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics