Skip to main content
  • 1467 Accesses

Abstract

The two main topics here are Brouwer’s Berlin lectures and the Vienna lectures. The Berlin lectures were held in 1927 on invitation of the math faculty. Reports tell us that Brouwer made furor in Berlin, students form all over the country flocked to Berlin to hear the mysterious great man. Students called themselves putschists, in reaction to a reaction of Hilbert to Weyl’s battle cry ‘And Brouwer, that is the revolution’. The future for intuitionism looked rosy for a while.

A year later Brouwer lectured in Vienna, this was essentially the first public exposition of his philosophy since his dissertation. Wittgenstein attended the lecture, which influenced his return to philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Brouwer (1925a, 1926a, 1927a).

  2. 2.

    The reception of the papers was, judging from the review in the Fortschritte, rather nondescript. The reviewer, Arthur Rosenthal, one of Brouwer’s topology friends, restricted himself to a few lines, referring to his earlier review of the old Begründungs-papers. But even that review of more than two pages did little to lift the veil of mystery that covered Brouwer’s writings (Jahrbuch der Fortschritte der Mathematik 47, p. 171, 51, p. 164).

  3. 3.

    Virtuelle und unerweiterbare Ordnung, Brouwer (1927c). A proof of the main theorem of this paper already occurs in Brouwer’s classroom notes of 1925.

  4. 4.

    Cf. p. 316 and Brouwer (1921a).

  5. 5.

    Cf. p. 377 and Brouwer and de Loor (1924), Brouwer (1924b).

  6. 6.

    Brouwer (1925b).

  7. 7.

    Ibid.

  8. 8.

    Brouwer (1926b).

  9. 9.

    Brouwer (1927b), also cf. pp. 372, 373.

  10. 10.

    Of course, also for later branches of constructive mathematics.

  11. 11.

    ‘Congruent’ means roughly ‘identical up to a double negation’.

  12. 12.

    Zermelo (1929), Hilbert (1930).

  13. 13.

    Cf. the Denjoy affair, p. 336 ff.

  14. 14.

    Cf. p. 316 ff.

  15. 15.

    Forman (1986), see also p. 316 ff.

  16. 16.

    Reichsverband deutscher mathematischer Gesellschaften und Vereine.

  17. 17.

    For further information and literature, cf. Mehrtens (1984).

  18. 18.

    Brouwer (1905, 1907, 1908b).

  19. 19.

    van der Waerden (1928).

  20. 20.

    Brouwer to Curators of the UVA, 10 January 1927.

  21. 21.

    According to Freudenthal, Loewner’s approach was far too complicated—‘In short, a catastrophe’, see Freudenthal (1987a).

  22. 22.

    Weil (1991).

  23. 23.

    Informal meeting after a lecture.

  24. 24.

    Verkrachen Sie sich mit ihm.

  25. 25.

    Brouwer to Alexandrov, 3.II.1927.

  26. 26.

    Henri Borel to Brouwer, 19.I.1927.

  27. 27.

    Frederik Van Eeden to Brouwer, 16.I.1927.

  28. 28.

    Mannoury to Brouwer, 26.I.1927.

  29. 29.

    A somewhat outdated term for ‘symbolic (universal) language’, often used by Mannoury.

  30. 30.

    Just had opened the Spa Jungborn in 1896. The German vicar Felke followed Just’s example and opened in 1915 his own Spa, organised in accordance with Just’s ideas. Brouwer referred to Felke in his ‘Life, Art, and Mysticism’.

  31. 31.

    Brouwer to Hopf, 21.XII.1925. Cf. p. 154 ff.

  32. 32.

    Geschichtliche Entwicklung der Topologie, Feigl (1928).

  33. 33.

    There were more rumours about Brouwer’s behaviour and personality than about most mathematicians, some of them absolutely unfounded. I recall that in the sixties a leading mathematician gave a talk at a monthly meeting of the Dutch Math. Soc., who at one point remarked ‘Brouwer no longer believed in the real numbers, did he?’

  34. 34.

    Brouwer to Hopf, 8.III.1927.

  35. 35.

    Haalmeijer and Schogt (1927).

  36. 36.

    Eva Wernicke to Brouwer, 30.III.1927.

  37. 37.

    Brouwer to Heyting, 17.VII.1928.

  38. 38.

    Brouwer (1992).

  39. 39.

    A partially ordered set is ordered under Brouwer’s definition if aba<bb<a, this is weaker than the trichotomy property. Brouwer (1992), p. 50.

  40. 40.

    Brouwer (1950).

  41. 41.

    Brouwer (1952a).

  42. 42.

    Jubiläumsband I. Aus Anlass des 100 jährigen Bestehens.

  43. 43.

    Henri Borel to Brouwer, 26.III.1927.

  44. 44.

    Brouwer to Eva Wernicke, 22.XII.1927.

  45. 45.

    For the Koebe-affair, see p. 180 ff.

  46. 46.

    Alexandrov to Hopf, 15.II.1927.

  47. 47.

    Alexandrov to Brouwer, 15.III.1927. Shatunovsky may have approached Mrs. Ehrenfest for an introduction to Brouwer.

  48. 48.

    Brouwer to Mrs. Ehrenfest, 3.VII.1927.

  49. 49.

    A gifted ‘Eigenbrötler’.

  50. 50.

    Cf. p. 379.

  51. 51.

    The paper was also published in the reports of the Berlin Academy, Brouwer (1928c).

  52. 52.

    Lize to Louise, 27.XI.1949. Lize spoke of ‘a nitwit of a doctor’.

  53. 53.

    This was indeed an incredible feat, the savings amounted to more than twice the annual income of a full professor.

  54. 54.

    Cf. p. 59.

  55. 55.

    Interview, H.J. Looman.

  56. 56.

    Aldert had been very successful in his profession. After his Ph.D. in 1910 (Delft) he worked as a geologist in the Dutch Indies (now Indonesia); in 1918 he got a chair in Delft, and in 1925 he was an exchange professor in Michigan. Utrecht made him an extraordinary professor in 1925. The Royal Academy in Amsterdam elected him a member in 1922. His chair in Amsterdam was in ‘general and practical petrology’.

  57. 57.

    He actually formalised a fragment of full intuitionistic predicate logic, cf. van Heijenoort (1967), p. 414, van Dalen (2005).

  58. 58.

    Cf. Plisko (1988b, 1988a), Troelstra and van Dalen (1988a), p. 59; Troelstra (1978); van Heijenoort (1967). Another famous Russian, Molotov, also proposed a translation, albeit in a completely different setting. According to Leonard Mosley in Dulles, 1978, Molotov once during a negotiation said ‘I propose that we insert a “not” before every verb in the text’.

  59. 59.

    Cf. Church (1928).

  60. 60.

    Lize ran the pharmacy, but Brouwer was formally the owner. See pp. 53 ff., 195 ff.

  61. 61.

    There were extensive grounds behind the building, stretching all the way into what is now the Vondelpark.

  62. 62.

    Bonger was a through and through socialist. Later he became a violent opponent of national socialism, and at the German invasion of Holland he committed suicide rather than fall in the hands of his arch enemies.

  63. 63.

    Cf. Mannoury (1930), e.g. the executions following the assassination of Wojkof.

  64. 64.

    Prof. Van der Hoeve, the same person who met Urysohn and Alexandrov in Norway.

  65. 65.

    Afbeelding van Ruimten, Wilson (1928), Brouwer (1924f).

  66. 66.

    Komitee zur Veranstaltung von Gastvorträge ausländischer Gelehrter der exacten Wissenschaften.

  67. 67.

    Mathematik, Wissenschaft und Sprache, Brouwer (1929a) and Die Struktur des Continuums, Brouwer (1930), p. 83.

  68. 68.

    Cf. p. 92 ff.

  69. 69.

    In German Brouwer uses ‘einzelner Mensch’. We will use ‘individual’. It is important to note that in this paper Brouwer does not take a solipsist position.

  70. 70.

    In Brouwer (1933a) Brouwer uses ‘tijdsgewaarwording’ and ‘causale aandacht’, translated as ‘perception of time’ and ‘causal attention’.

  71. 71.

    See pp. 66, 88 ff. and Brouwer (1905), p. 19.

  72. 72.

    Which much later is called the ‘cunning act’, Brouwer (1948b).

  73. 73.

    The terminology may seem confusing. Brouwer had observed that PEM itself is not contradictory. For consider some open problem, e.g. the Riemann hypothesis R. Then if ‘R or not-R’ were contradictory, both R and not-R would yield contradictions, So both not-R and not-not-R would be true, which is impossible. Hence the negation of PEM for a single statement is consistent. The same argument works for finitely many statements, R 1R 2∧⋯∧R n . However for an infinite set of statements (the extended case of PEM) this is no longer the case. Consider ‘for all real numbers x, x is rational or x is irrational’. This cannot be true, because it would yield a decomposition of the continuum, which is impossible, cf. p. 375.

  74. 74.

    Menger (1994), Chap. X.

  75. 75.

    Brouwer (1908b, 1923f), Borel (1908a).

  76. 76.

    Brouwer (1923f, 1992).

  77. 77.

    Cf. van Dalen (1999a).

  78. 78.

    Wittgenstein (1984), no. 179.

  79. 79.

    Wittgenstein’s arguments, however, should be distinguished from those of Hilbert, Brouwer, Heyting, and Martin-Löf.

  80. 80.

    pp. 101, 313.

  81. 81.

    Cf. p. 795. Finch to Van Dalen, 10.X.1990.

  82. 82.

    See Köhler (1991). There is however a letter from Gödel to the American Philosophical Society of 19.I.1967 in which he says ‘I have seen Brouwer only on one occasion, in 1953, when he came to Princeton for a brief visit’. If ‘seen’ means ‘met’ there is no contradiction.

  83. 83.

    Gödel über Unerschöpflichkeit der Mathematik. Erst danach Brouwer Wiener Vortrag zu diesen Gedanken angeregt worden’. Carnap 14.II.1928 and 23.XII.1929. See also Wang (1987), p. 50.

  84. 84.

    The Amsterdamer Vorträge were published in Husserl (1997).

  85. 85.

    Husserl to Heidegger, 5.V.1928, Husserl (1994).

  86. 86.

    Hier tummelt sich jetzt Husserl herum, wobei ich stark mit herangezogen werde. Er findet Frä ulein Gawehn den intelligensten Kopf, der er in Holland angetroffen hat.

  87. 87.

    The oral exam was in 1925. Rosenthal and Liebmann examined her in mathematics, Lenard in physics and Jaspers in philosophy.

  88. 88.

    Rector Oslo University to Brouwer, 19.II.1929.

  89. 89.

    For details, see Schmitz (1990a), 6.3.

  90. 90.

    Brouwer et al. (1937a, 1937b, 1937c, 1939).

  91. 91.

    Oral communication, C. Vuysje-Mannoury.

  92. 92.

    He got a mortgage of 29,000 guilders.

  93. 93.

    Interview R.A.F. Guasco.

  94. 94.

    Suriname place or square.

  95. 95.

    The transaction was concluded on 2 April 1930.

  96. 96.

    Lize to Louise, 17.V.1935.

References

  • Borel, É.: Les “paradoxes” de la théorie des ensembles. Ann. Sci. Éc. Norm. Super. 25, 443–448 (1908a)

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Leven, Kunst en Mystiek. Waltman, Delft (1905). Translation by W.P. van Stigt in Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 37, 381–429 (1966)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Over de grondslagen der wiskunde. Ph.D. thesis, Amsterdam (1907)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: De onbetrouwbaarheid der logische principes. Tijdschr. Wijsb. 2, 152–158 (1908b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Begründung der Mengenlehre unabhängig vom logischen Satz vom ausgeschlossenen Dritten. Zweiter Teil, Theorie der Punktmengen. Verh. K. Akad. Wet. Amst. 7, 1–33 (1919a)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Besitzt jede reelle Zahl eine Dezimalbruch-Entwickelung? Math. Ann. 83, 201–210 (1921a)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Über die Bedeutung des Satzes vom ausgeschlossenen Dritten in der Mathematik insbesondere in der Funktionentheorie. J. Reine Angew. Math. 154, 1–8 (1923f)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Intuitionistische Ergänzung des Fundamentalsatzes der Algebra. K. Ned. Akad. Wet. Proc. Sect. Sci. 27, 631–634 (1924b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: On the n-dimensional simplex star in R n . K. Ned. Akad. Wet. Proc. Sect. Sci. 27, 778–780 (1924f)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Zur Begründung der intuitionistischen Mathematik I. Math. Ann. 93, 244–257 (1925a). Corr. in Brouwer (1926a)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Intuitionistischer Beweis des Jordanschen Kurvensatzes. K. Ned. Akad. Wet. Proc. Sect. Sci. 28, 503–508 (1925b)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Zur Begründung der intuitionistischen Mathematik II. Math. Ann. 95, 453–472 (1926a)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Intuitionistische Einführung des Dimensionsbegriffes. K. Ned. Akad. Wet. Proc. Sect. Sci. 29, 855–873 (1926b)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Zur Begründung der intuitionistischen Mathematik III. Math. Ann. 96, 451–488 (1927a)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Über Definitionsbereiche von Funktionen. Math. Ann. 97, 60–75 (1927b)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Virtuelle Ordnung und unerweiterbare Ordnung. J. Reine Angew. Math. 157, 255–257 (1927c)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Intuitionistische Betrachtungen über den Formalismus. Sitz.ber. Preuss. Akad. Wiss. Phys.-Math. Kl., 48–52 (1928c)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Mathematik, Wissenschaft und Sprache. Monatshefte Math. Phys. 36, 153–164 (1929a)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Die Struktur des Kontinuums [Sonderabdruck] (1930)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Willen, Weten, Spreken. Euclides 9, 177–193 (1933a)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Discussion. (Following “Les conceptions mathématiques et le reel” of Gonseth). In: Symposium de l’Institut des Sciences théoriques. Bruxelles 1947. Actualités scientifiques et Industrielles, pp. 31–60. Hermann, Paris (1948b)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: De non-aequivalentie van de constructieve en negatieve orderelatie in het continuum. Indag. Math. 11, 37–39 (1949a). Transl. “The non-equivalence of the constructive and the negative order relation in the continuum” in CW 1, pp. 495–496

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Sur la possibilité d’ordonner le continu. C. R. Math. Acad. Sci. Paris 230, 349–350 (1950)

    MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: An intuitionist correction of the fixed-point theorem on the sphere. Proc. R. Soc. Lond. Ser. A 213, 1–2 (1952a)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J.: Intuitionismus. van Dalen, D. (ed.). Bibliographisches Institut Wissenschaftsverlag, Mannheim (1992)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J., de Loor, B.: Intuitionistischer Beweis des Fundamentalsatzes der Algebra. K. Ned. Akad. Wet. Proc. Sect. Sci. 27, 186–188 (1924)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J., et al.: Signifische dialogen. Synthese 2, 168–174 (1937a)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J., et al.: Signifische dialogen. Synthese 2, 261–268 (1937b)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J., et al.: Signifische dialogen. Synthese 2, 316–324 (1937c)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brouwer, L.E.J., et al.: Signifische Dialogen. J. Bijleveld, Utrecht (1939)

    Google Scholar 

  • Church, A.: On the law of the excluded middle. Bull. Am. Math. Soc. 34, 75–78 (1928)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Feigl, G.: Geschichtliche Entwicklung der Topologie. Jahresber. Dtsch. Math.-Ver. 37, 273–286 (1928)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Forman, P.: Il Naturforscherversammlung a Nauheim del settembre 1920: una introduzione alla vita scientifica nella Republica de Weimar. In: Rossi, A., Battimelli, G., de Maria, M. (eds.) La ristrutturazione delle scienze tra le due guerre mondiali, vol. 1, pp. 59–78. La Goliardica, Rome (1986)

    Google Scholar 

  • Freudenthal, H.: Berlin 1923–1930. Studienerinnerungen von Hans Freudenthal. de Gruyter, Berlin (1987a)

    Google Scholar 

  • Haalmeijer, B.P., Schogt, J.H.: Inleiding tot de leer der verzamelingen. Noordhoff, Groningen (1927)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hilbert, D.: Die Grundlegung der elementaren Zahlenlehre. Math. Ann. 104, 485–494 (1930)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E.: Edmund Husserl: Briefwechsel. Schuhmann, K. (ed.). Springer, Dordrecht (1994)

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E.: Husserliana, vol. 6. Palmer, R.E., Sheehan, T. (eds.). Kluwer, Dordrecht (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  • Köhler, E.: Gödel und der Wiener Kreis. In: Kruntorad, P. (ed.) Jour Fixe der Vernunft. Der Wiener Kreis und die Folgen, pp. 127–158. Verlag Hölder–Pichler–Temsky, Vienna (1991)

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewner, C.: Charles Loewner. Collected Papers. Bers, L. (ed.). Birkhäuser, Basel (1988)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Mannoury, G.: Heden is het keerpunt (1930)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mehrtens, H.: Anschauungswelt versus Papierwelt – Zur Interpretation der Grundlagenkrise der Mathematik. In: Poser, H., Schütt, H.-W. (eds.) Ontologie und Wissenschaft. Philosophische und wissenschafts-historische Untersuchungen zur Frage der Objektkonstitution, vol. 19, pp. 231–276. Technische Universität, Berlin (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  • Menger, K.: Reminiscences of the Vienna Circle and the Mathematical Colloquium. Golland, L., McGuinness, B., Sklar, A. (eds.). Kluwer, Dordrecht (1994)

    Book  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Plisko, V.E.: Letters of A.N. Kolmogorov to A. Heyting. Russ. Math. Surv. 43, 89–93 (1988a). Usp. Math. Nauk 43, 75–77 (1988)

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  • Plisko, V.E.: The Kolmogorov calculus as a part of minimal calculus. Russ. Math. Surv. 43, 95–110 (1988b). Usp. Math. Nauk 43, 79–91 (1988)

    Article  MathSciNet  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Schmitz, H.W.: Frederik van Eeden and the introduction of significs into the Netherlands: from Lady Welby to Mannoury. In: Schmitz, H.W. (ed.) Essays on Significs. Papers Presented on the Occasion of the 150th Birtday of Victoria Lady Welby (1837–1912), vol. 23, pp. 219–246. Benjamins, Philadelphia (1990a)

    Google Scholar 

  • Troelstra, A.S.: A. Heyting on the formalization of intuitionistic logic. In: Grootendorst, A.W., Bertin, E.M.J., Bos, H.M.J. (eds.) Two Decades of Mathematics in the Netherlands, vol. 1, pp. 153–175. Mathematical Centre, Amsterdam (1978)

    Google Scholar 

  • Troelstra, A.S., van Dalen, D.: Constructivism in Mathematics, vol. 1. North-Holland, Amsterdam (1988a)

    Google Scholar 

  • van Dalen, D.: From Brouwerian counter examples to the creating subject. Stud. Log. 62, 305–314 (1999a)

    Article  MATH  Google Scholar 

  • van Dalen, D.: Mystic, Geometer, and Intuitionist: The Life of L.E.J. Brouwer. Volume 2: Hope and Disillusion. Oxford University Press, Oxford (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Waerden, B.L.: De strijd om de abstraktie. Noordhoff, Groningen (1928). Inaugural address

    Google Scholar 

  • van Heijenoort, J.: From Frege to Gödel. A Source Book in Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931. Harvard University Press, Cambridge (1967)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, H.: Reflections on Kurt Gödel. MIT Press, Cambridge (1987)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  • Weil, A.: Soevenirs d’apprentisage. Birkhäuser, Zürich (1991)

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, W.: Afbeeldingen van Ruimten. Ph.D. thesis, Amsterdam (1928)

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L.: Philosophische Untersuchungen. Surkamp, Frankfurt (1984). First ed. Blackwell, Oxford (1964). Manuscript (1930)

    Google Scholar 

  • Zermelo, E.: Über den Begriff der Definitheit in der Axiomatik. Fundam. Math. 14, 339–344 (1929)

    MATH  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2013 Springer-Verlag London

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

van Dalen, D. (2013). From Berlin to Vienna. In: L.E.J. Brouwer – Topologist, Intuitionist, Philosopher. Springer, London. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4471-4616-2_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics