Skip to main content
Log in

The Practitioner of Science: Everyone her Own Historian

  • Published:
Journal of the History of Biology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Carl Becker's classic 1931 address ``Everyman his own historian''holds lessons for historians of science today. Like the professional historians he spoke to, we are content to displaythe Ivory-Tower Syndrome, writing scholarly treatises only forone another, disdaining both the general reader and our naturalreadership, scientists. Following his rhetoric, I argue thatscientists are well aware of their own historicity, and wouldbe interested in lively and balanced histories of science. It isironic that the very professionalism that ought to equip us towrite such histories has imposed on us a powerful taboo that rendersus unable to do so.

We who count ourselves sophisticated in describing the effects ofsocial forces upon past scientists have been remarkably unconsciousof the ways our own practices are being shaped by our need (and perhapsmore importantly, the needs of our teachers' teachers) to distinguish ourselves from scientists who write history. Our fear of presentism ingeneral and Whig history in particular is really a taboo, that is, anexcessive avoidance enforced by social pressure. It succeeds at makingour work distinct from histories written by scientists, but at the awful cost of blotting out the great fact of scientific progress.Scientists may be misguided in expecting us to celebrate great men,but they are right to demand from historians an analysis of the processof testing and improvement that is central to science. If progress in general is a problematic term, we could label the process ``emendation.''

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Ashplant, T.G. and Wilson, A. 1988. “Present-Centered History and the Problem of Historical Knowledge.” The Historical Journal 31: 253–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biagioli, M. 1996. “From Relativism to contingentism.” In: The Disunity of Science: Boundaries, Contexts, and Power, eds. P. Galison and D.J. Stump, pp. 189–206 Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Becker, C.L. 1935. “Everyman his Own Historian.” Everyman his Own Historian: Essays on History and Politics, pp. 233–255. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bliss, M. 1991. “Privatizing the Mind: The Sundering of Canadian History, the Sundering of Canada.” Journal of Canadian Studies 26: 5–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Broad, W. and Wade, N. 1982. Betrayers of the Truth: Fraud and Deceit in the Halls of Science. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brush, S.G. 1995. “Scientists as Historians.” Osiris 10: 215–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfield, H. 1931. The Whig Interpretation of History. London: G. Bell.

  • Carr, E.H. 1961. What Is History? London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Choudhry, A. 1997. “Donald Griffin and Animal Minds: The Taboo of Animal Consciousness in the Making.” Unpublished paper for ZOO 498Y, University of Toronto.

  • Coleman, W. 1985. “The Cognitive Basis of the Discipline.” Isis 76: 49–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Danto, A.C. 1985. Narration and Knowledge. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Desmond, A. and Moore, J. 1992. Darwin. New York: Warner Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drake, S. 1978. Galileo at Work. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forman, P. 1991. “Independence, Not Transcendence, for the Historian of Science.” Isis 82: 71–86.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gerson, E.M. 1983. “Scientific Work and Social Worlds.” Knowledge: Creation, Diffusion, Utilization 4: 356–377.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. 1996. Full House: The Spread of Excellence from Plato to Darwin. New York: Harmony Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graham, L. 1981. “Why Can't History Dance Contemporary Ballet? or Whig History and the Evils of Contemporary Dance.” Science, Technology & Human Values 6: 3–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, A.R. 1983. “On Whiggism.” History of Science 21: 45–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardcastle, G. 1991. “Presentism and the Indeterminacy of Translation.” Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 22: 321–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harrison, E. 1987. “Whigs, Prigs and Historians of Science.” Nature 329: 213–214.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hessen, B. 1931. “The Social and Economic roots of Newton's Principia.” In: Science at the Crossroads. London: Kniga.

    Google Scholar 

  • Himmelfarb, G. 1987. “History and the Idea of Progress.” In: The New History and the Old. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hingham, J. 1965. History: The Development of Historical Studies in the United States. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hull, D. 1979. “In Defense of Presentism.” History and Theory 18: 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. 1993. The Advancement of Science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krieger, L. 1977. Ranke: The Meaning of History. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T.S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Laudan, L. 1977. Progress and its Problems: Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——1990a. “The History of Science and the Philosophy of Science.” In: Companion to the History of Modern Science, eds. R.C. Olby, G.N. Cantor, J.R.R. Christie and M.J.S. Hodge, pp. 47–59. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——1990b. Science and Relativism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levere, T.H. 1999. “Introduction.” In: Essays on Galileo and the History and Philosophy of Science, pp. xi–xviii. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. 1977. “Epistemological Crisis, Dramatic Narrative and the Philosophy of Science.” The Monist 60: 453–472.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1990. “When Is Historiography Whiggish?” Journal of the History of Ideas 51: 301–309.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. 1996. “Metabiological Reflections on Charles Darwin.”In: Telling Lives in Science: Essays on Scientific Biography, eds. M. Shortland and R. Yeo, pp. 267–281. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Novick, P. 1988. That Noble Dream: The ‘Objectivity Question’ and the American Historical Profession. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pickering, A. 1995. The Mangle of Practice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Pickstone, J.V. 1995. “Past and Present Knowledges in the Practice of the History of Science.” History of Science 33: 203–224.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rouse, J. 1990. “The Narrative Reconstruction of Science.” Inquiry 33: 179–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. 1996. From Monad to Man. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, C. 1984. “Whigs and Professionals.” Nature 308: 777–778.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. 1990. “Consciousness, Explanatory Inversion, and Cognitive Science.” The Behavioral and Brain Sciences 13: 585–642.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J.M. 1991. “Forward.” In: The Ant and the Peacock: Altruism and Sexual Selection from Darwin to Today, Helena Cronin. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. ix–x.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sobel, D. 1995. Longitude: The True Story of a Lone Genius Who Solved the Greatest Scientific Problem of His Time. New York: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sulloway, F.J. 1992. Freud, Biologist of the Mind: Beyond the Psychoanalytic Legend. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thackray, A. 1972. “On Discipline Building: The Paradoxes of George Sarton.” Isis 63: 473–495.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——1975. “Reflections on Half a Century of the History of Science Society: I. Five Phases of Prehistory, Depicted from Diverse Documents.” Isis 65: 445–453.

    Google Scholar 

  • ——1980a. “The Pre-History of an Academic Discipline: The Study of the History of Science in the United States, 1891–1941.” Minerva 18: 448–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ——1980b. “History of Science.” In: A Guide to the Culture of Science, Technology, and Medicine, ed. Paul T. Durbin, pp. 3–69. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Winsor, M.P. 1991. Reading the Shape of Nature. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, A. and Ashplant, T.G. 1988. “Whig History and Present-Centered History.” The Historical Journal 31: 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Winsor, M.P. The Practitioner of Science: Everyone her Own Historian. Journal of the History of Biology 34, 229–245 (2001). https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1010398900038

Download citation

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1023/A:1010398900038

Navigation