Skip to main content
Log in

Moral and Vocational Dilemmas Meet the Common Currency Hypothesis: a Contribution to Value Commensurability

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

A Correction to this article was published on 28 October 2019

This article has been updated

Abstract

Moral dilemmas have long been debated in moral philosophy without reaching a definitive consensus. The majority of value pluralists attribute their origin to the incommensurability of moral values, i.e. the statement that, since moral values are many and different in nature, they may conflict and cannot be compared. Neuroscientific studies on the neural common currency show that the comparison between allegedly incompatible alternatives is a practical possibility, namely it is the basis of the way in which the agent evaluates choice options. Indeed, both in economic and moral decision-making, the value of options is represented and directly compared in the ventromedial prefrontal cortex. Therefore, we contend that moral dilemmas do not originate from value incommensurability and, on the basis of the neuroscientific discoveries on the neural currency, we derive the implications for the philosophical debate on moral dilemmas. We also provide a possible connection between the experience of moral dilemmas and their neural representation: one of the causes of the individual’s indecision is the neural tie, i.e. the condition in which two options have the same value at neural level, and her regret could be due to the motivational force of the rejected option that is still signalled by affective processes in the brain. We apply this interpretation and the common currency hypothesis to vocational decisions and propose that, although from the agent’s perspective the options are qualitatively different, they may be nevertheless equivalent at neural level. This can be seen as a reason for downgrading the importance commonly attributed to the risk of making the “wrong choice”.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Change history

  • 28 October 2019

    In the initial online publication, the second author’s given name should have been displayed in full and in the running head the names were not properly abbreviated.

Notes

  1. Hence, the difference between “decision” and “choice” does not derive from the kind of the alternatives (e.g. economic items, social rewards, moral norms). The difference is rather due to, in the first instance, the discipline-specific vocabularies of moral philosophy, on the one hand, and neuroscience and economics, on the other; in the second instance, it is due to the emphasis on the process of considering the reasons in favor of the alternatives, which is present in “decision” but not in “choice”.

  2. Sophie is a Polish woman forced by a guard of a Nazi concentration camp to choose which of her two children will be killed. In this moral dilemma, the same value, i.e. the life of one’s own children, demands two different actions but supplies the same reason to prevent their death.

  3. Rationalism and experientialism are to be understood as Weber’s ideal types: they are simplified general models, according to which we can establish if a philosopher has a rationalist or experientialist propensity. Hence, not every philosopher can be defined as rationalist or experientialist (Gowans 1996).

  4. See also Williams 1973: 172, 175-176; 1981 [1979]: 74.

  5. These different types of value are: (1) specific obligations towards some people and institutions, (2) duties deriving from people’s general rights, (3) utility, (4) perfectionist ends or values, and (5) commitment to one’s own projects or undertakings (1979: 129).

  6. Although value incommensurability is usually held by value pluralists, value monism, too, can admit value incommensurability if the moral value that is assumed to be the only one is conceived as complex and appearing in a variety of settings, as in Mill’s conception of higher and lower pleasures ((2003) [1863], parr. 4-8: 187-188).

  7. There is no agreement regarding what a case of parity means in a moral dilemma. According to authors such as Parfit (1984: 430-431) and Griffin (1986: 80-81, 95-98; 1997: 38-39), in cases of parity the alternatives are defined “roughly equal”, which is an imprecise or approximate version of “equally good” that is included in the Trichotomy Thesis (see Hsieh 2016); if two options, A and B are roughly equal, it means that neither is worse than the other and if a third option is better than B(A), it does not imply that it is better than A(B). According to Chang, however, there is a fourth relation, called “on a par”, defining a situation in which two options, A and B, are too different to be judged equally good and neither is better than the other, but they are nevertheless comparable (Chang 2002: 661-662).

  8. fMRI is a method of brain scanning that identifies the variation in oxygen uptake of the neurons, i.e. the nerve cells, by detecting the changes in the magnetic fields of the water molecules that are in the neurons. Hence, fMRI indirectly measures neural activity as it records the flow of blood, i.e. the metabolic demand of the brain, and not directly the activity of neurons.

  9. Non-invasive brain stimulation is a method for modulating brain activity through either the application of weak direct currents to the brain (transcranial direct current stimulation) or a strong short current (transcranial magnetic stimulation).

  10. Lesion studies assess if an area is necessary for the performance of a given task by testing if patients with a damage to that area are impaired in carrying out the task.

  11. Single-cell studies measure directly the electrical reaction of a neuron to a stimulus, namely its firing rate. As they rely on an invasive method, they are conducted on animals or when patients undergo brain surgery for other reasons.

  12. The preferences of each subject were elicited in a behavioral session consisting of same-type lotteries (in which the same kind of reward ranged in probability and quantity) and mixed-type lotteries (where the rewards were food or water and money). On the basis of the choices of the subjects, the indifference points were computed. The latter are the choices in which the two alternatives have the same economic value for the subject. See also Smith et al. 2010 for similar results with a different type of reward (pictures of attractive female faces).

  13. See also Hutcherson et al. 2015.

  14. Of course, this extends not only to the fact that rewards from different existential sources are expressed in a common currency, but, more generally, to the fact that the brain translates all different aspects of perceived reality in terms of the quite homogeneous kind of biochemical events that happen inside it. The former is just a subcase of the latter.

  15. In case the conflict is between two values that are deontological rules of the affective system, the more the two different motivations coming from the affective system are similar in force, the more the agent is undecided.

  16. The same obviously holds for minor things such as the choice between different places for a vacation period, a new car or a restaurant for the next evening.

  17. People are sometimes in anguish because they think that the choice they make may prove wrong in the future, and in some way they will be lost. In these cases, they are averse to the possible regret that their choice can bring about in the future. Yet even in such cases, the origin of their worry is the assumption that one choice option is right and the other wrong, together with the lack of information regarding the long-term expected benefits of the options.

References

  • Anderson, E. 1997. Practical Reason and Incommensurable Goods. In Incommensurability, Incomparability and Practical Reason, ed. R. Chang. Cambridge-London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bagnoli, C. 2006a. Breaking ties: The significance of choice in symmetrical moral dilemmas. Dialectica 60 (2): 157–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bagnoli, C. 2006b. Deliberare, comparare, misurare. Ragion Pratica 26: 65–79.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bagnoli, C. 2012. Reason and rationality. In Reason and Rationality, ed. M.C. Amoretti and N. Vassallo Ontos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumgartner, T., D. Knoch, P. Hotz, C. Eisenegger, and E. Fehr. 2011. Dorsolateral and ventromedial prefrontal cortex orchestrate normative choice. Nature Neuroscience 14 (11): 1468–1474.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernoulli, D. (1738). Specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis. Commentarii academiae scientiarum imperialis Petropolitanae.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandstätter, E., G. Gigerenzer, and R. Hertwig. 2006. The priority heuristic: Making choices without trade-offs. Psychological Review 113 (2): 409–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brosch, T., and Sander, D., 2016. From value to valuation: an interdisciplinary approach. In T. Brosch and D. Sander (Eds.), Handbook of Value: Perspectives from Economics, Neuroscience, Philosophy , Psychology, and Sociology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Camille, N., C.A. Griffiths, K. Vo, L.K. Fellows, and J.W. Kable. 2011. Ventromedial Frontal Lobe Damage Disrupts Value Maximization in Humans. Journal of Neuroscience 31 (20): 7527–7532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, R. 1997. Introduction. In Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, ed. R. Chang. Cambridge-London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, R. 2002. The Possibility of Parity. Ethics 112: 659–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, R. 2004. Putting Together Morality and Well-Being. In Practical Conflicts: New Philosophical Essays, ed. P. Baumann and M. Betzler. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chib, V.S., A. Rangel, S. Shimojo, and J.P. O’Doherty. 2009. Evidence for a Common Representation of Decision Values for Dissimilar Goods in Human Ventromedial Prefrontal Cortex. Journal of Neuroscience 29: 12315–12320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P.S. 2011. Braintrust: What Neuroscience Tells us About Morality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F., and J.D. Greene. 2012. Finding faults: How moral dilemmas illuminate cognitive structure. Social Neuroscience 7 (3): 269–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Martino, B., D. Kumaran, B. Holt, and R.J. Dolan. 2009. The Neurobiology of Reference-Dependent Value Computation. Journal of Neuroscience 29 (12): 3833–3842.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Sousa, R.B. 1974. The Good and the True. Mind 83 (332): 534–551.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elliott, R., Z. Agnew, and J.F.W. Deakin. 2008. Medial orbitofrontal cortex codes relative rather than absolute value of financial rewards in humans. European Journal of Neuroscience 27: 2213–2218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., and K.M. Schmidt. 1999. A theory of fairness, competition, and cooperation. Quarterly Journal of Economics 114 (3): 817–868.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fellows, L.K., and M.J. Farah. 2007. The role of ventromedial prefrontal cortex in decision making: Judgment under uncertainty or judgment per se? Cerebral Cortex 17 (11): 2669–2674.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gert, B., & Gert, J. (2017). The Definition of Morality. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/morality-definition/. Accessed 7 Sept 2019.

  • Gowans, C.W. 1996. Moral Theory, Moral Dilemmas, and Moral Responsibility. In Moral Dilemmas and Moral Theory, ed. H.E. Mason. New York-Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J.D. 2015. The Cognitive Neuroscience of Moral Judgment. In The Cognitive Neurosciences, ed. M.S. Gazzaniga, 4th ed. Cambridge-London: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, J. 1986. Well-Being: Its Meaning, Measurement and Moral Importance. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, J. 1997. Incommensurability: What’s the Problem? In Incommensurability, Incomparability, and Practical Reason, ed. R. Chang. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harbaugh, W.T., U. Mayr, and D.R. Burghart. 2007. Neural Responses to Taxation and Voluntary Giving Reveal Motives for Charitable Donations. Science 316 (5831): 1622–1625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, R.M. 1981. Moral Thinking: its Levels, Method, and Point. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, T.A., C.F. Camerer, and A. Rangel. 2009. Self-control in decision-making involves modulation of the vmPFC valuation system. Science 324 (5927): 646–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, T.A., C.F. Camerer, D.T. Knoepfle, J.P. O’Doherty, and A. Rangel. 2010. Value Computations in Ventral Medial Prefrontal Cortex during Charitable Decision Making Incorporate Input from Regions Involved in Social Cognition. Journal of Neuroscience 30 (2): 583–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hsieh, N. (2016). Incommensurable Values. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/value-incommensurable/.

  • Hutcherson, C.A., L. Montaser-Kouhsari, J. Woodward, and A. Rangel. 2015. Emotional and Utilitarian Appraisals of Moral Dilemmas are Encoded in Separate Areas and Integrated in Ventromedial Prefrontal Cortex. Journal of Neuroscience 35 (36): 12593–12605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Izuma, K., D.N. Saito, and N. Sadato. 2008. Processing of Social and Monetary Rewards in the Human Striatum. Neuron 58 (2): 284–294.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Izuma, K., D.N. Saito, and N. Sadato. 2010. Processing of the Incentive for Social Approval in the Ventral Striatum during Charitable Donation. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 22 (4): 621–631.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kable, J.W., and P.W. Glimcher. 2007. The neural correlates of subjective value during intertemporal choice. Nature Neuroscience 10 (12): 1625–1633.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., J.L. Knetsch, and R.H. Thaler. 1991. Anomalies: The Endowment Effect, Loss Aversion, and Status Quo Bias. Journal of Economic Perspectives 5 (1): 193–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2006) [1785]. Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals. (M. J. Gregor, Ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Landreth, A., and J. Bickle. 2008. Neuroeconomics, Neurophysiology and the Common Currency Hypothesis. Economics and Philosophy 24: 419–429.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lebreton, M., S. Jorge, V. Michel, B. Thirion, and M. Pessiglione. 2009. An Automatic Valuation System in the Human Brain: Evidence from Functional Neuroimaging. Neuron 64 (3): 431–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, D.J., and P.W. Glimcher. 2011. Comparing Apples and Oranges: Using Reward-Specific and Reward-General Subjective Value Representation in the Brain. Journal of Neuroscience 31 (41): 14693–14707.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, D.J., and P.W. Glimcher. 2012. The root of all value: A neural common currency for choice. Current Opinion in Neurobiology 22 (6): 1027–1038.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, I., J. Snell, A.J. Nelson, A. Rustichini, and P.W. Glimcher. 2010. Neural representation of subjective value under risk and ambiguity. Journal of Neurophysiology 103 (2): 1036–1047.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levy, I., S.C. Lazzaro, R.B. Rutledge, and P.W. Glimcher. 2011. Choice from Non-Choice: Predicting Consumer Preferences from Blood Oxygenation Level-Dependent Signals Obtained during Passive Viewing. Journal of Neuroscience 31 (1): 118–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., and R. Sugden. 1982. Regret Theory: an Alternative Theory of Rational Choice Under Uncertainty. Economic journal 92 (368): 805–824.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lukes, S. 1997. Comparing the Incomparable: Trade-Offs and Sacrifices. In Incommensurability, Incomparability and Practical Reason, ed. R. Chang. Cambridge-London: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. 1990. Moral Dilemmas. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 1: 367–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mason, E. 2018. Value Pluralism. In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. Stanford University. Available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/value-pluralism/. Accessed 7 Sept 2019.

  • McConnell, T. (2018). Moral Dilemmas. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/moral-dilemmas/. Accessed 7 Sept 2019.

  • Mill, J. S. (2003) [1863]. Utilitarianism and On liberty. (M. Warnock, Ed.). Malden: Blackwell Publishing.

  • Miller, R., and F. Cushman. 2017. Moral values and motivations: How special are they? 1–13. Mapping Good and Evil: The Atlas of Moral Psychology.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, P.R., and G.S. Berns. 2002. Neural economics and the biological substrates of valuation. Neuron 36 (2): 265–284.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montague, P.R., and B. Kings-Casas. 2007. Efficient statistics, common currencies and the problem of reward-harvesting. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 11 (12): 514–519.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. 1979. Mortal Questions. The Philosophical Review. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Padoa-Schioppa, C., and J.A. Assad. 2006. Neurons in the orbitofrontal cortex encode economic value. Nature 441 (7090): 223–226.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Padoa-Schioppa, C., and J.A. Assad. 2008. The representation of economic value in the orbitofrontal cortex is invariant for changes of menu. Nature Neuroscience 11 (1): 95–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and persons. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peters, J., and C. Büchel. 2009. Overlapping and Distinct Neural Systems Code for Subjective Value during Intertemporal and Risky Decision Making. Journal of Neuroscience 29 (50): 15727–15734.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Platt, M.L., and H. Plassmann. 2014. Multistage Valuation Signals and Common Neural Currencies. In Neuroeconomics: Decision Making and the Brain, ed. P.W. Glimcher and E. Fehr, 2nd ed. London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pochon, J.-B., Riis, J., Sanfey, A.G., Nystrom, L.E., and Cohen, J.D. (2008). Functional Imaging of Decision Conflict. Journal of Neuroscience 28(13), 3468–3473.

  • Putnam, H. 1989. Rationality in question: on Eastern and Western views of rationality. In Leiden: E.J, ed. S. Biderman and B.-A. Scharfstein Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rangel, A., and J.A. Clithero. 2014. The Computation of Stimulus Values in Simple Choice. In Neuroeconomics: Decision Making and the Brain, ed. P.W. Glimcher and E. Fehr, 2nd ed. London: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. 1986. The Morality of Freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richardson, H. S. (2018). Moral Reasoning. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reasoning-moral/. Accessed 7 Sept 2019.

  • Ross, W. D. (2002) [1930]. The right and the good. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Ruff, C. C. and Fehr, E. (2014) The neurobiology of rewards and values in social decision making, Nature Reviews Neuroscience 15, 549–562.

  • Samuelson, P.A. 1937. A Note on Measurement of Utility. The Review of Economic Studies 4 (2): 155–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Samuelson, P. 1947. Foundations of Economic Analysis. Harvard University Press.

  • Saxe, R., and J. Haushofer. 2008. For love or money: a common neural currency for social and monetary reward. Neuron 58 (2): 164–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheffler, S. 1992. Human Morality. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shenhav, A., and J.D. Greene. 2010. Moral judgments recruit domain-general valuation mechanisms to integrate representations of probability and magnitude. Neuron 67 (4): 667–677.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shenhav, A., and J.D. Greene. 2014. Integrative Moral Judgment: Dissociating the Roles of the Amygdala and Ventromedial Prefrontal Cortex. Journal of Neuroscience 34 (13): 4741–4749.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, D.V., B.Y. Hayden, T.-K. Truong, A.W. Song, M.L. Platt, and S.A. Huettel. 2010. Distinct Value Signals in Anterior and Posterior Ventromedial Prefrontal Cortex. Journal of Neuroscience 30: 2490–2495.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steele, K., & Stefánsson, H. O. (2016). Decision Theory. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Available at: https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/decision-theory/. Accessed 7 Sept 2019.

  • Stevenson, A., ed. 2010. Oxford Dictionary of English. 3rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, N. 2009. Decision by sampling: The role of the decision environment in risky choice. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 62 (6): 1041–1062.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, N., N. Chater, and G.D.A. Brown. 2006. Decision by sampling. Cognitive Psychology 53 (1): 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Styron, W. 1980. Sophie’s Choice. New York: Bantam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tassy, S., O. Oullier, J. Mancini, and B. Wicker. 2013. Discrepancies between judgment and choice of action in moral dilemmas. Frontiers in Psychology 4 (250).

  • Tom, S.M., C.R. Fox, C. Trepel, and R.A. Poldrack. 2007. The neural basis of loss aversion in decision-making under risk. Science 315 (5811): 515–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tusche, A., S. Bode, and J.-D. Haynes. 2010. Neural Responses to Unattended Products Predict Later Consumer Choices. Journal of Neuroscience 30 (23): 8024–8031.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Viganò, E. 2017. Adam Smith’s Theory of Prudence Updated with Neuroscientific and Behavioral Evidence. Neuroethics 10 (2): 215–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vlaev, I. Chater, N., Stewart, N., and Brown, G.D.A. (2011). Does the brain calculate value? Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15(11), 546–554.

  • Williams, B. (1973). Problems of the self: philosophical papers 1956-1972. The Journal of Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Williams, B. 1981. Moral Luck: Philosophical Papers 1973–1980. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Michele Loi for his helpful comments on the earlier draft of this manuscript.

Funding

Eleonora Viganò’s work was partly supported by the Cogito Foundation (grant number 17-117-S)

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Eleonora Viganò.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare that they have no conflict of interest.

Research Involving Human Participants and/or Animals

This article does not contain any studies with human participants or animals performed by the authors.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

The original version of this article has been revised: the second author's given name is displayed in full and the running head has been corrected.

Eleonora Viganò wrote sections 1-4 and 6 of the manuscript.

Edoardo Lombardi Vallauri wrote subsection 4.3 and section 5 of the manuscript.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Viganò, E., Lombardi Vallauri, E. Moral and Vocational Dilemmas Meet the Common Currency Hypothesis: a Contribution to Value Commensurability. Rev.Phil.Psych. 11, 83–102 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-019-00448-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-019-00448-7

Keywords

Navigation