Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Nativism and the Evolutionary Debunking of Morality

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Evolutionary debunking arguments purport to undercut the justification of our moral judgments by showing why a tendency to make moral judgments would evolve regardless of the truth of those judgments. (Machery and Mallon (2010). Evolution of morality. In J.M. Doris and The Moral Psychology Research Group (Eds.), The Moral Psychology Handbook (pp. 3–46). Oxford: Oxford University Press) have recently tried to disarm these arguments by showing that moral cognition – in the sense that is relevant to debunking – is not the product of natural selection. Specifically, they present a barrage of increasingly influential challenges against reciprocity-based approaches to moral nativism. In the present paper I defend the nativist account of moral cognition against these criticisms, thereby bolstering the skeptical conclusions of evolutionary debunking arguments. However, Machery and Mallon's critique does successfully highlight several vulnerabilities in Richard Joyce's approach to debunking, suggesting several ways in which it can be revised toward generating a more robust version of the argument.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This argument works most naturally with a cognitivist account of moral judgment, although Joyce (2006) endorses a hybrid position. Joyce (2013) has recently suggested that it can also be made to work on noncognitivist accounts.

  2. In what follows, all discussion of their work will be in reference to this chapter.

  3. Here I follow Joyce in interpreting the nativist claim to be that “the present-day existence of the trait is to be explained by reference to a genotype having granted ancestors reproductive advantage, rather than by reference to psychological processes of acquisition” (2008a, p. 213). I will also follow Joyce in taking the hypothesis to be primarily about the existence of our tendency to make moral judgments and experience moral motivation.

  4. It is important to also keep in mind that Joyce acknowledges (e.g. 2006 p. 140) the tremendous role culture plays in determining the content of a particular individual's moral judgments, and he does not rule out the relevance of group selection theories.

  5. Joyce opts for avoiding the label ‘reciprocal altruism’ due to its tendency to obscure debate (see West et al. 2007), and I will follow this convention.

  6. For comparison, consider that adults today might behave differently depending on whether or not they are using contraception. But the belief that a sexual act is unlikely to result in offspring does not eliminate its pleasure (or its capacity to arouse jealousy). This is because adaptive sexual behaviors are not driven by overt reasoning about their fitness consequences.

  7. Importantly, the force of these arguments relies only on direct reciprocity, and does not depend on any assumptions about reputation (see §5).

  8. This is not to deny that selection has operated between then and now. The point is just that the selection of cooperative tendencies is not hypothesized to have begun so recently in our evolution.

  9. Today the mere sense of being watched, even in the absence of an overt belief that someone is looking, is apparently enough to strengthen cooperative behavior in humans (Haley and Fessler 2005; Bateson, et al. 2006; cf. §4.1).

  10. Although there are various other ways to explain moral norms not governing social interaction (e.g. Kurzban et al. 2010), the important point to note is that Joyce is attempting to explain the existence of moral norms, not the content of all current moral norms. As he cautions (2006, p. 141): “…it might be protested that many present-day moral practices have little to do with reciprocation: our duties to children, to the severely disabled, to future generations, to animals, and (if you like) to the environment all are arguably maintained without expectation of payback. Yet this objection really misses the mark, for these considerations hardly undermine the hypothesis that it was for regulating reciprocal exchanges that morality evolved in the first place; it is not being claimed that reciprocity alone is what continues to sustain social relations.”

  11. See Baumard et al. (2013) and Baumard (2010) for helpful discussion of important differences between partner control and partner choice models of cooperation.

  12. I am grateful to an anonymous reviewer for pointing this out to me.

  13. There are several problems with this study, however (Sousa 2009; Sousa et al. 2009; Rosas 2012; but see Stich et al. 2009), not least among which is the fact that some of the harmful actions included punishment of guilty persons and warfare training (cf. Nichols 2004, pp. 16–17). It is far from clear that Kelly et al.'s findings call for a rejection, rather than a revision, of the research program.

  14. Here's a soft analogy with linguistics: it is plausible that the mind comes prepared to treat some noises as verbs and some noises as nouns, but leaves open what noises fall into which category, allowing for wide cultural divergence. See Nichols (2004) for a view along these lines.

  15. This is a prerequisite for moral cognition, but is not specific to morality.

  16. Thanks to Edouard Machery for pressing me on this point.

  17. Mackie (1977, p. 15) writes: “The claim that values are not objective, are not part of the fabric of the world…also includes non-moral values, notably aesthetic ones, beauty and various kinds of artistic merit.” He continues: “clearly much the same considerations apply to aesthetic and to moral values, and there would be at least some initial implausibility in a view that gave the one a different status from the other.”

  18. Joyce (2013) is relatively open about this. See also Kahane (2011).

References

  • Adam, T.C. 2010. Competition encourages cooperation: client fish receive higher-quality service when cleaner fish compete. Animal Behaviour 79: 1183–1189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aktipis, C.A. 2004. Know when to walk away: contingent movement and the evolution of cooperation. Journal of Theoretical Biology 231: 249–260.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aktipis, C.A. 2011. Is cooperation viable in mobile organisms?: simple Walk Away rule favors the evolution of cooperation in groups. Evolution and Human Behavior 32: 263–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexander, R.D. 1987. The biology of moral systems. Hawthorne, NY: Aldine de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ambady, N., and R. Rosenthal. 1992. Thin slices of expressive behavior as predictors of interpersonal consequences: a meta-analysis. Psychological Bulletin 111: 256–274.

    Google Scholar 

  • Astington, J.W., and L.A. Dack. 2013. Development of the deontic advantage in reasoning: reply to Cummins. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 116: 770–773.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barclay, P. 2004. Trustworthiness and competitive altruism can also solve the “tragedy of the commons.”. Evolution and Human Behavior 25: 209–220.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barclay, P., and R. Willer. 2007. Partner choice creates competitive altruism in humans. Proceedings of the Royal Society B 274: 749–753.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, M., D. Nettle, and G. Roberts. 2006. Cues of being watched enhance cooperation in a real-world setting. Biology Letters 2: 412–414.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumard, N. 2010. Has punishment played a role in the evolution of cooperation? A critical review. Mind & Society 9: 171–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumard, N., J. André, and D. Sperber. 2013. A mutualistic approach to morality: the evolution of fairness by partner choice. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 36: 59–78.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bereczkei, T., B. Birkas, and Z. Kerekes. 2007. Public charity offer as a proximate factor of evolved reputation-building strategy: an experimental analysis of a real-life situation. Evolution and Human Behavior 28: 277–284.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blair, R.J.R. 1995. A cognitive developmental approach to morality: investigating the psychopath. Cognition 57: 1–29.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom, P. 2013. Just babies: the origins of good and evil. New York: Crown Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boehm, C. 1999. Hierarchy in the forst: the evolution of egalitarian behavior. Cambridge: Cambridge. MA: Harvard University Press.

  • Boehm, C. 2008. Purposive social selection and the evolution of human altruism. Cross-Cultural Research 42: 319–352.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boehm, C. 2012. Moral origins: the evolution of virtue, altruism, and shame. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R., and P.J. Richerson. 1988. The evolution of reciprocity in sizable groups. Journal of Theoretical Biology 132: 337–356.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R., and P.J. Richerson. 1992. Punishment allows the evolution of cooperation (or anything else) in sizable groups. Ethology and Sociobiology 13: 171–195.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd, R., H. Gintis, S. Bowles, and P.J. Richerson. 2003. The evolution of altruistic punishment. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 100: 3531–3535.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brink, D.O. 1989. Moral realism and the foundations of ethics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brosig, J. 2002. Identifying cooperative behavior: some experimental results in a prisoner's dilemma game. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 47: 275–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brosnan, K. 2011. Do the evolutionary origins of our moral beliefs undermine moral knowledge? Biology & Philosophy 26: 51–64.

  • Brown, D. 1991. Human universals. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, W.M., B. Palameta, and C. Moore. 2003. Are there nonverbal cues to commitment? an exploratory study using the zero-acquaintance video paradigm. Evolutionary Psychology 1: 42–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bshary, R., and A. Grutter. 2005. Punishment and partner switching cause cooperative behaviour in a cleaning mutualism. Biology Letters 4: 396–399.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carter, D.B., and C.J. Patterson. 1982. Sex roles as social conventions: the development of children's conceptions of sex-role stereotypes. Developmental Psychology 18: 812–824.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chiang, Y. 2010. Self-interested partner selection can lead to the emergence of fairness. Evolution and Human Behavior 31: 265–270.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. 1980. Rules and representations. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P.S. 2011. Braintrust: what neuroscience tells us about morality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Copp, D. 2008. Darwinian skepticism about moral realism. Philosophical Issues, Interdisciplinary Core Philosophy 18: 186–206.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coricelli, G., D. Fehr, and G. Fellner. 2004. Partner selection in public goods experiments. Journal of Conflict Resolution 48: 356–378.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L., and J. Tooby. 2008. Can a general deontic logic capture the facts of human moral reasoning? How the mind interprets social exchange rules and detects cheaters. In Moral Psychology: The Evolution of Morality: Adaptations and Innateness, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 53–119. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cosmides, L., H.C. Barrett, and J. Tooby. 2010. Adaptive specializations, social exchange, and the evolution of human intelligence. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 107: 9007–9014.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crawford, J.T., Y. Inbar, and V. Maloney. 2014. Disgust sensitivity selectively predicts attitudes toward groups that threaten (or uphold) traditional sexual morality. Personality and Individual Differences 70: 218–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, D.D. 1996a. Evidence of deontic reasoning in 3- and 4-year-olds. Memory and Cognition 24: 823–829.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, D.D. 1996b. Evidence for the innateness of deontic reasoning. Mind & Language 11: 160–190.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, D.D. 2013a. Deontic and epistemic reasoning in children revisited: comment on Dack and Astington. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 116: 762–769.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, D.D. 2013b. Deontic reasoning as a target of selection: reply to Astington and Dack. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 116: 970–974.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dack, L.A., and J.W. Astington. 2011. Deontic and epistemic reasoning in children. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology 110: 94–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davies, S. 2012. The artful species. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F.B.M. 1982. Chimpanzee politics: power and sex among apes. New York: Harper and Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F.B.M. 1989. Food sharing and reciprocal obligations among chimpanzees. Journal of Human Evolution 18: 433–459.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F.B.M. 1997. The chimpanzee's service economy: food for grooming. Evolution and Human Behavior 18: 375–386.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F.B.M. 2006. Primates and philosophers: how morality evolved. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delton, A.W., M.M. Krasnow, L. Cosmides, and J. Tooby. 2011. Evolution of direct reciprocity under uncertainty can explain human generosity in one-shot encounters. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 108: 13335–13340.

    Google Scholar 

  • Denant-Boemont, L., D. Masclet, and C.N. Noussair. 2007. Punishment, counterpunishment and sanction enforcement in a social dilemma experiment. Economic Theory 33: 145–167.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D.C. 1995. Darwin's dangerous idea: evolution and the meanings of life. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreber, A., D.G. Rand, G. Fudenberg, and M.A. Nowak. 2008. Winners don't punish. Nature 425: 348–351.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunbar, R.I.M. 1993. Coevolution of neocortex size, group size and language in humans. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 16: 681–694.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dunfield, K.A., and V.A. Kuhlmeier. 2010. Intention-mediated selective helping in infancy. Psychological Science 21: 523–527.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dutton, D. 2009. The art instinct. New York: Bloomsbury Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, R. 2011. Justice for hedgehogs. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dwyer, S. 2006. How good is the linguistic analogy? In The innate mind, culture and cognition, vol. 2, ed. P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, and S. Stich, 237–256. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Ermer, E., S.A. Guerin, L. Cosmides, J. Tooby, and M.B. Miller. 2006. Theory of mind broad and narrow: reasoning about social exchange engages ToM areas, precautionary reasoning does not. Social Neuroscience 1: 196–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., and U. Fischbacher. 2004. Third-party punishment and social norms. Evolution and Human Behavior 25: 63–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., and S. Gächter. 2000. Cooperation and punishment in public goods experiments. The American Economic Review 90: 980–994.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., and S. Gächter. 2002. Altruistic punishment in humans. Nature 415: 137–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., and J. Henrich. 2003. Is strong reciprocity a maladaptation? On the evolutionary foundations of human altruism. In Genetic and Cultural Evolution of Cooperation, ed. P. Hammerstein, 55–82. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiddick, L. 2004. Domains of deontic reasoning: resolving the discrepancy between the cognitive and moral reasoning literatures. The Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology 57A: 447–474.

    Google Scholar 

  • FitzPatrick, W. 2014. Debunking evolutionary debunking of ethical realism. Philosophical Studies. doi:10.1007/s11098-014-0295-y.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foley, R., and C. Gamble. 2009. The ecology of social transitions in human evolution. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364: 3267–3279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, P. 1972. Morality as a system of hypothetical imperatives. Philosophical Review 81: 305–316.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forster, P. 2004. Ice ages and the mitochondrial DNA chronology of human dispersals: a review. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. Series B, Biological Sciences 359: 255–264.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R.H. 1988. Passions within reason: the strategic role of the emotions. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frank, R.H., T. Gilovich, and D.T. Regan. 1993. The evolution of one-shot cooperation: an experiment. Ethology and Sociobiology 14: 247–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabennesch, H. 1990. The perception of social conventionality by children and adults. Child Development 61: 2047–2059.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gächter, S., and A. Falk. 2002. Reputation and reciprocity: Consequences for labor relations. Scandinavian Journal of Economics 104: 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gächter, S., and B. Herrmann. 2009. Reciprocity, culture and human cooperation: previous insights and a new cross-cultural experiment. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364: 791–806.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gintis, H., S. Bowles, R. Boyd, and E. Fehr. 2003. Explaining altruistic behavior in humans. Evolution and Human Behavior 24: 153–172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gomes, C.M., R. Mundry, and C. Boesch. 2009. Long-term reciprocation of grooming in wild West African chimpanzees. Proceedings of the Royal Society B 276: 688–709.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guala, F. 2012. Reciprocity: weak or strong? what punishment experiments do (and do not) demonstrate. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 35: 1–15.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurven, M. 2004. To give and give not: the behavioral ecology of human food transfers. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 27: 543–583.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gurven, M., W. Allen-Arave, K. Hill, and A.M. Hurtado. 2000. “It’s a wonderful life”: signaling generosity among the Ache of Paraguay. Evolution and Human Behavior 21: 263–282.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hagen, E.H., and P. Hammerstein. 2006. Game theory and human evolution: a critique of some recent interpretations of experimental games. Theoretical Population Biology 69: 339–348.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. 2001. The emotional dog and its rational tail: a social intuitionist approach to moral judgment. Psychological Review 108: 814–834.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. 2007. The new synthesis in moral psychology. Science 316: 998–1002.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. 2012. The righteous mind: why good people are divided by politics and religion. New York: Pantheon Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J., S. Koller, and M. Dias. 1993. Affect, culture and morality, or is it wrong to eat your dog? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 65: 613–628.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haley, K.J., and D.M.T. Fessler. 2005. Nobody's watching?: subtle cues affect generosity in an anonymous economic game. Evolution and Human Behavior 26: 245–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin, J.K., and K. Wynn. 2011. Young infants prefer prosocial to antisocial others. Cognitive Development 26: 30–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin, J.K., K. Wynn, and P. Bloom. 2007. Social evaluation by preverbal infants. Nature 450: 557–559.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hamlin, J.K., K. Wynn, and P. Bloom. 2010. Three-month-olds show a negativity bias in their social evaluations. Developmental Science 13: 923–929.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, C.L., and M. Van Vugt. 2006. Nice guys finish first: the competitive altruism hypothesis. Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin 32: 1402–1413.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harman, G. 1977. The nature of morality: an introduction to ethics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, P.L., and M. Núñez. 1996. Understanding of permission rules by preschool children. Child Development 67: 1572–1591.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, P.L., M. Núñez, and C. Brett. 2001. Let's swap: early understanding of social exchange by British and Nepali children. Memory & Cognition 29: 757–764.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haselhuhn, M.P., and E.M. Wong. 2012. Bad to the bone: facial structure predicts unethical behavior. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 279: 571–576.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J., and R. Boyd. 2001. Why people punish defectors: Weak conformist transmission can stabilize costly enforcement of norms in cooperative dilemmas. Journal of Theoretical Biology 208: 79–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J., R. Boyd, S. Bowles, C. Camerer, E. Fehr, G. Gintis, R. McElreath, M. Alvard, A. Barr, J. Ensminger, N.S. Henrich, K. Hill, F. Gil-White, M. Gurven, F.W. Marlowe, J.Q. Patton, and D. Tracer. 2005. “Economic man” in cross-cultural perspective: behavioral experiments in 15 small-scale societies. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 28: 795–815.

    Google Scholar 

  • Henrich, J., R. McElreath, A. Barr, J. Ensminger, C. Barrett, A. Bolyanatz, J.C. Cardenas, M. Gurven, E. Gwako, N. Henrich, C. Lesorogol, F. Marlowe, D. Tracer, and J. Ziker. 2006. Costly punishment across human societies. Science 312: 1767–1770.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hill, K.R., R.S. Walker, M. Bozicevic, J. Eder, T. Headland, B. Hewlett, A.M. Hurtado, F. Marlowe, P. Wiessner, and B. Wood. 2011. Co-residence patterns in hunter-gatherer societies show unique human social structure. Science 331: 1286–1289.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inbar, Y., D.A. Pizarro, J. Knobe, and P. Bloom. 2009. Disgust sensitivity predicts intuitive disapproval of gays. Emotion 9: 435–439.

    Google Scholar 

  • Inbar, Y., D.A. Pizarro, and P. Bloom. 2012. Disgusting smells cause decreased liking of gays. Emotion 12: 23–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. 2001. The myth of morality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. 2006. The evolution of morality. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. 2008a. Précis of the evolution of morality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77: 245–267.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. 2008b. Replies. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77: 245–267.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. 2013. Irrealism and the genealogy of morals. Ratio 26: 351–372.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joyce, R. 2014. Evolution, truth-tracking, and moral skepticism. In Problems of Goodness: New Essays on Metaethics, ed. B. Reichardt. Germany: Bernstein Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahane, G. 2011. Evolutionary debunking arguments. Noûs 45: 103–125.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, H.S., P.L. Hooper, and M. Gurven. 2009. The evolutionary and ecological roots of human social organization. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B 364: 3289–3299.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, D. 2011. Yuck! the nature and moral significance of disgust. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, D., and S. Stich. 2007. Two theories about the cognitive architecture underlying morality. In The innate mind, foundations and the future, vol. 3, ed. P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, and S. Stich, 348–366. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Kelly, D., S. Stich, K.J. Haley, S.J. Eng, and D.M.T. Fessler. 2007. Harm, affect, and the moral/conventional distinction. Mind & Language 22: 117–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krasnow, M.M., A.W. Delton, J. Tooby, and L. Cosmides. 2013. Meeting now suggests we will meet again: implications for debates on the evolution of cooperation. Scientific Reports 3: 1747.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S.A. 1984. Wittgenstein on rules and private language. Cambrige, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kurzban, R., A. Dukes, and J. Weeden. 2010. Sex, drugs, and moral goals: reproductive strategies and views about recreational drugs. Proceedings of the Royal Society - B 277: 3501–3508.

  • Lieberman, D. 2008. Moral sentiments relating to incest: discerning adaptations from by-products. In Moral Psychology: The Evolution of Morality: Adaptations and Innateness, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 165–190. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. 2012. Deliniating the moral domain. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic and Communication 7: 1–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E. forthcoming. Discovery and confirmation in evolutionary psychology. In Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Psychology, ed. J. Prinz. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Machery, E., and R. Mallon. 2010. Evolution of morality. In The moral psychology handbook, eds. J.M. Doris and The Moral Psychology Research Group, 3–46. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Mackie, J.L. 1977. Ethics: inventing right and wrong. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marlowe, F.W. 2005. Hunter-gatherers and human evolution. Evolutionary Anthropology 14: 54–67.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellars, P. 2006. Going east: new genetic and archaeological perspectives on the modern human colonization of Eurasia. Science 313: 796–800.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A.N. 1995. Understanding the intentions of others: re-enactment of intended acts by 18-month-old children. Developmental Psychology 31: 838–850.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milinski, M., D. Semmann, and H. Krambeck. 2002. Reputation helps solve the ‘tragedy of the commons’. Nature 415: 424–426.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newton-Fisher, N.E., and P.C. Lee. 2011. Grooming reciprocity in wild male chimpanzees. Animal Behaviour 81: 439–446.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. 2004. Sentimental rules: on the natural foundations of moral judgment. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nikiforakis, N., and D. Engelmann. 2011. Altruistic punishment and the threat of feuds. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization 78: 319–332.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nowak, M.A., and K. Sigmund. 2005. Evolution of indirect reciprocity. Science 437: 1291–1298.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nucci, L.P., and M.S. Nucci. 1982. Children's responses to moral and social conventional transgressions in free-play settings. Child Development 53: 1337–1342.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E., J. Walker, and R. Gardner. 1992. Covenants with and without a sword: self-governance is possible. The American Political Science Review 86: 404–417.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pradel, J., H.A. Euler, and D. Fetchenhauer. 2009. Spotting altruistic dictator game players and mingling with them: the elective assortation of classmates. Evolution and Human Behavior 30: 103–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Premack, D., and A.J. Premack. 1997. Infants attribute value ± to the goal-directed actions of self-propelled objects. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 9: 848–856.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J.J. 2008. Is morality innate? In Moral Psychology: The Evolution of Morality: Adaptations and Innateness, ed. W. Sinnott-Armstrong, 367–406. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Railton, P. 1986. Moral realism. Philosophical Review 95: 163–207.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renfew, C. 2010. Achaeogenetics – towards a ‘new synthesis’? Current Biology 20: R162–R165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosas, A. 2012. Mistakes to avoid in attacking the moral/conventional distinction. The Baltic International Yearbook of Cognition, Logic, and Communication 7: 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruse, M. 1986. Taking Darwin seriously. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seinen, I., and A. Schram. 2006. Social status and group norms: indirect reciprocity in a repeated helping experiment. European Economic Review 50: 581–602.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, R. 2012. Evolutionary debunking, moral realism, and moral knowledge. Journal of Ethics & Social Philosophy 7: 1–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shweder, R.A., M. Mahapatra, and J. Miller. 1987. Culture and moral development. In The emergence of morality in young children, ed. J. Kagan and S. Lamb, 1–82. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smetana, J.G., and J.L. Braeges. 1990. The development of toddlers' moral and conventional judgments. Merrill-Palmer Quarterly 3: 329–346.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sousa, P. 2009. On testing the ‘moral law’. Mind & Language 24: 209–234.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sousa, P., C. Holbrook, and J. Piazza. 2009. The morality of harm. Cognition 113: 80–92.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., and N. Baumard. 2012. Moral reputation: an evolutionary and cognitive perspective. Mind & Language 27: 495–518.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sripada, C.S. 2005. Punishment and the strategic structure of moral systems. Biology and Philosophy 20: 767–789.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sripada, C.S., and S. Stich. 2006. A framework for the psychology of norms. In The innate mind, Culture and Cognition, vol. 2, ed. P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, and S. Stich, 280–301. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. 2008. Some questions about the evolution of morality. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 77: 228–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S., D.M.T. Fessler, and D. Kelly. 2009. On the morality of harm: a response to Sousa, Holbrook and Piazza. Cognition 113: 93–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stirrat, M., and D.I. Perrett. 2010. Valid facial cues to cooperation and trust: male facial width and trustworthiness. Psychological Science 21: 349–354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. 2006. A Darwinian dilemma for realist theories of value. Philosophical Studies 127: 109–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. 2008. Constructivism about reasons. In Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol. 3, ed. R. Shafer-Landau, 207–245. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. 2010. What is constructivism in ethics and metaethics? Philosophy Compass 5: 363–384.

    Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. 2011. Evolution and the normativity of epistemic reasons. Canadian Journal of Philosophy 35: 213–248.

    Google Scholar 

  • Street, S. 2014. Does anything really matter or did we just evolve to think so? In The Norton Introduction to Philosophy, eds. A. Byrne, J. Cohen, G. Rosen, and S. Shiffrin.

  • Sylwester, K., and G. Roberts. 2010. Cooperators benefit through reputation-based partner choice in economic games. Biological Letters 6: 659–662.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tinbergen, N. 1963. On aims and methods of ethology. Zeitschrift für Tierpsychologie 20: 410–433.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toner, C. 2011. Evolution, naturalism, and the worthwhile: a critique of Richard Joyce's evolutionary debunking of morality. Metaphilosophy 42: 520–546.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tooby, J., L. Cosmides, and M.E. Price. 2006. Cognitive adaptations for n-person exchange: the evolutionary roots of organizational behavior. Managerial and Decision Economics 27: 103–129.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trivers, R. 1971. The evolution of reciprocal altruism. Quarterly Review of Biology 46: 35–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trivers, R. 2004. Mutual benefits at all levels of life. Science 304: 964–965.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turiel, E. 1983. The development of social knowledge: Morality and convention. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vainstein, M.H., A.T.C. Silva, and J.J. Arenzon. 2007. Does mobility decrease cooperation? Journal of Theoretical Biology 244: 722–728.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaish, A., M. Carpenter, and M. Tomasello. 2010. Young children selectively avoid helping people with harmful intentions. Child Development 81: 1661–1669.

    Google Scholar 

  • Verplaetse, J., S. Vanneste, and J. Braeckman. 2007. You can judge a book by its cover: the sequel.: A kernel of truth in predictive cheating detection. Evolution and Human Behavior 28: 260–271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warneken, F., and M. Tomasello. 2006. Altruistic helping in human infants and young chimpanzees. Science 1301–1303.

  • Wedekind, C., and V.A. Braithwaite. 2002. The long-term benefits of human generosity in indirect reciprocity. Current Biology 12: 1012–1015.

    Google Scholar 

  • West, S.A., A.S. Griffin, and A. Gardner. 2007. Social semantics: altruism, cooperation, mutualism, strong reciprocity, and group selection. Journal of Evolutionary Biology 20: 415–432.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheatley, T., and J. Haidt. 2005. Hypnotic disgust makes moral judgments more severe. Psychological Science 16: 780–784.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wielenberg, E.J. 2010. On the evolutionary debunking of morality. Ethics 120: 441–464.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiessner, P. 2005. Norm enforcement among the Ju/’hoansi Bushmen: a case of strong reciprocity? Human Nature 16: 115–145.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, A.L. 1998. Infants selectively encode the goal object of an actor's reach. Cognition 68: 1–34.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wynn, K. 2008. Some innate foundations of social and moral cognition. In The innate mind, Foundations and the future, vol. 3, ed. P. Carruthers, S. Laurence, and S. Stich, 330–347. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yamagishi, T. 1986. The provision of a sanctioning system as a public good. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 51: 110–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yamagishi, T., S. Tanida, R. Mashima, E. Shimoma, and S. Kanazawa. 2003. You can judge a book by its cover: evidence that cheaters may look different from cooperators. Evolution and Human Behavior 24: 290–301.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yamaguchi, M., V.A. Kuhlmeier, K. Wynn, and K. vanMarle. 2009. Continuity in social cognition from infancy to childhood. Developmental Science 12: 746–752.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahn-Waxler, C., M. Radke-Yarrow, and E. Wagner. 1992. Development of concern for others. Developmental Psychology 28: 126–136.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

For their valuable comments on earlier drafts of this paper, I am very grateful to James Beebe, Edouard Machery, and an anonymous reviewer for this journal. I am also grateful for helpful discussion with Ariane Nomikos, Timothy Schroeder, and audiences at the University at Buffalo and the University at Albany.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brendan Cline.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cline, B. Nativism and the Evolutionary Debunking of Morality. Rev.Phil.Psych. 6, 231–253 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-014-0207-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-014-0207-2

Keywords

Navigation