Skip to main content
Log in

A Logic of Practical Reasoning

  • original article
  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper my primary aim is to present a logical system of practical reasoning that can be used to assess the validity of practical arguments, that is, arguments with a practical judgment as conclusion. I begin with a critical evaluation of other approaches to this issue and argue that they are inadequate. On the basis of these considerations, I explain in Sect. 2 the informal conception of practical validity and introduce in Sect. 3 the logical system P, which is an extension of propositional logic and can be used to assess the validity of a wide range of practical arguments. In the last section, I apply this system to some examples of practical reasoning in order to demonstrate how it can be used in practice.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See, for instance, Audi (1982, 25; 2004, 126), Cullity and Gaut (1997), and Davidson (2001, 31; 2004, 55).

  2. By claiming this, I do not deny the valuable contributions of so-called decision theory and deontic logic (both kinds of practical logic) to the theory of practical reasoning. However, the logical system I am going to present here is different, even though naturally related, to both of them.

  3. This does, however, not mean that the conclusion of a practical argument must be a value judgement (i.e., a judgement expressing a valuation); it can also be a statement about what should be done without expressing any valuation at all.

  4. Anscombe (1963) is a case in point, if I understand her correctly.

  5. See Audi (1982, 1991), Broome (2002), Clarke (1985), Davidson (2004), Jeffrey (1983), and von Wright (1977a), to name only some.

  6. Among them are Davidson (2001), Piller (2001), and von Wright (1997a). Dreier (1997, 96) claims that if this kind of reasoning does not count as a reason, then the request for reasons is empty, and Broome (2002) seems to regret that his account of correct practical reasoning cannot show the validity of a sufficient condition schema. Also Audi (2004, 128–9) accepts the validity of sufficient condition schemata if the conclusion is only a prima facie judgement.

  7. See also von Wright (1977b).

  8. Broome reserves the term ‘valid’ to the propositional content of practical reasoning and calls the reasoning itself only ‘correct.’ He holds that, given some constraints are met, practical reasoning is ‘correct’ if the propositional content gives a valid practical syllogism (see 2001, 177–8; 2002).

  9. See Audi (2004) or Davidson (2004).

  10. See Audi (1991, 2004) or the ‘best explanation model’ discussed by Broome (2002).

  11. It seems that this was the opinion of Aristotle (see, e.g., NE 1147a25–35). This view has been criticized by Audi (1982, 29)–among others.

  12. See Davidson (2004). However, ‘value judgement’ is too broad and too narrow because some value judgements do not refer to actions and not all conclusions are evaluative.

  13. Also this view has been criticized by Audi (1982, 29).

  14. See Broome (2001, 2002). It seems to me, however, that Broome adopted this view only to have a correspondence to the propositional attitude of believing.

  15. This requires that the ordering is (i) connected. If we choose the symbol ‘≥’ for a valuer’s preference relation, this relation is connected, if, for any two distinct consequences (x, y), either x ≥ y or y ≥ x (or both). It requires (ii) transitivity. The valuer’s preference relation is transitive, if, for all triplets of consequences (x, y, z), x ≥ y and y ≥ z entail x ≥ z. Furthermore, as an anonymous referee has pointed out, if ‘most valued’ means ‘uniquely most valued’ (as is indeed meant here), it requires (iii) that (∃x)(∀y) (x ≠ y → x > y), where ‘>’ stands for the irreflexive relation ‘x is more valued than y,’ That is, there must be a consequence that is more valued than any other.

  16. I use the term ‘implicate’ in the technical sense it has been given especially by H. P. Grice (Studies in the Way of Words, 1989).

  17. The symbols φ and ψ are here used as metavariables ranging over formulae of P.

  18. I use ‘+’ as the symbol for exclusive disjunctions.

  19. At this stage I can reply to the concern, expressed by an anonymous referee, that my criterion of practical validity implies contradictions. Let ‘b’ mean ‘I am taking a bottle of mineral water’ (where ‘a bottle’ means any of the available ones) and ‘b 1 ’ and ‘b 2 ’ mean ‘I am taking the first (second) bottle of mineral water.’ According to my criterion of validity, it is not the case that an agent who wants to take a bottle of mineral water should take the first bottle and it is not the case that he should take the second bottle also. (For the sake of simplicity, we assume that there are only two bottles the agent can choose from.) It seems, therefore, that the agent should not take any bottle. On the other hand, VbOb is a valid argument, according to my criterion, and from this it seems to follow that the agent should do both, taking a bottle and not taking one.

    I do not think, however, that this example causes problems because what follows from my view is that the agent should take any bottle. This can be seen when we symbolize the argument as follows: (b 1b), (b 2b), ¬(b 1 b 2) → ¬b, Vb ╞ O(b 1 b 2). That is, the agent should take any bottle, and this is here tantamount to saying that he should take ‘a bottle’ (Ob).

  20. The examples are taken, but adapted, from Hurley, P.J. (1994). A concise introduction to logic (5th edn.). Belmont/Cal.: Wadsworth.

  21. Please note that even though the conclusion is of the form O¬φ, doing the conclusion means here doing ¬a because from (a ∧ ¬a) ∨ ¬a follows ¬a.

  22. Even though the argument has apparently only one alternative, it contains in fact two, ‘l’ and ‘¬l’, because ‘fl’ is, of course, equivalent to ‘l → f’ and ‘¬l → ¬f’. Therefore, not doing the conclusion is tantamount to doing ‘¬l’. The analogous remark applies to the consequence ‘i.’

References

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1963). Intention (2nd edn.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (1982). A theory of practical reasoning. American Philosophical Quarterly, 19(1), 25–39.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (1991). Practical reasoning. London-New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Audi, R. (2004). Reasons, practical reason, and practical reasoning, Ratio, 17(2), 119–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2001). Normative practical reasoning. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 75(1), 175–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Broome, J. (2002). Practical reasoning. In J. Bermùdez & A. Millar (Eds.), Essays in the theory of rationality (pp. 85–112). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, D. S. (1985). Practical inferences. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cullity, G., & Gaut, B. (Eds.). (1997). Ethics and practical reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Davidson, D. (2001). Essays on actions and events (2nd ed.). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (2004). Problems of rationality. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, J. (1997). Human doubts about the practical justification of morality. In G. Cullity & B. Gaut (Eds.), Ethics and practical reason (81–99). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. C. (1983). The logic of decision (2nd ed.). Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kenny, A. (1966). Practical inferences. Analysis, 26, 65–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Piller, Ch. (2001). Normative practical reasoning. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 75(1), 195–216.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wright, G. H. v. (1977a). Praktisches Schließen. In H. Poser (Hrsg.), Handlung, Norm und Intention: Untersuchungen zur deontischen Logik (S. 41–S. 60). Berlin: de Gruyter. (Originally published: 1963).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, G. H. v. (1977b). Über sogenanntes praktisches Schließen. In H. Poser (Hrsg.), Handlung, Norm und Intention: Untersuchungen zur deontischen Logik (S. 61–S. 81). Berlin: de Gruyter. (Originally published: 1972).

    Google Scholar 

  • Žarnić, B. (1999). Validity of practical inference. ILLC Scientific Publications PP-1999–23. Amsterdam: Institute for Logic, Language and Computation, University of Amsterdam.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Georg Spielthenner.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Spielthenner, G. A Logic of Practical Reasoning. Acta Anal 22, 139–153 (2007). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-007-0005-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-007-0005-x

Keywords

Navigation