Skip to main content
Log in

Activity Theories and the Ontology of Psychology: Learning from Danish and Russian Experiences

  • Regular Article
  • Published:
Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Psychology has permanent problems of theoretical coherence and practical, analytic and critical efficiency. It is claimed that Activity Theory (AT) with roots in a long European philosophical tradition and continued in Russian AT is a first step to remedy this. A Danish version of AT may have a key to exceed some, mostly implicit, ontological restrictions in traditional AT and free it from an embracement of functionalism and mechanicism, rooted in Renaissance Physics. The analysis goes back to Aristotle’s understanding of the freely moving animal in its ecology and introduces some dualities in the encounter between subject and object which replace the dualistic dichotomies traditionally splitting Psychology in Naturwissenschaft vs. Geisteswissenshaft. This also implies a “Copernican turn” of Cartesian dualism. The perspectives are to give place for a phenomenology of meaning without cutting human psyche out of Nature and to open Psychology to its domain.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. “There’s nothing more practical than a good theory” (Lewin 1952, p. 169).

  2. Smedslund and Ross are discussing the usefulness of empirical research, and empirical “evidens”, for psychological practice with clinical work as key example. In different degree they agree that empirical studies of functional, parametric correlations and “influences” are of little value when dealing with specific and often unique clinical cases. The value, if any, is an attention towards contextual factors influencing the client and potentially biasing the practitioner, and in some cases correcting pre-scientific lay knowledge. What they don’t discuss is the value of theoretical reflections and conceptual enrichment which could educate the practitioner to be sensitive to phenomena and “dimensions” not covered sufficient in lay knowledge, although they touch this subject when (p. 374) talking of “existence proofs”. Smedslund and Ross focus on psychological theories as containers of knowledge and not very much as analytical tools, which is in focus of the present paper, and in relation to which we are a little more optimistic, as we hope to promote here.

  3. It should be stressed, however, that pure empiricism is an unattainable ideal, and that nobody in practice can clear his mind for a priori assumptions interacting with or framing data, or derive theories by pure induction from data frequencies. There will always, alone from logical reasons, be other theories which also fit the data. In practice induction is mixed with some “intuitive” Bayesian Logic, with hidden assumptions. The unattainable ideal of empiricism is in contrast to the situation in rationalism, to be discussed below, which is both attainable and practicable on a common sense level, but has serious problems when confronted with the ideals of modern science, as we shall see.

  4. On the one hand, philosophical empiricism as an “epistemology” is based on sense impressions from which all knowledge and concepts should be derived and explained, including physical-chemical processes. On the other hand, when adopted by psychology, the physical-chemical processes in the sense-organs are declared to be sources of, and explanations of, sense-impressions. The pure inductive or mechanistic understanding of the basis for knowledge in this way unites the two contradictory ontologies behind psychological empiricism.

  5. https://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1845/theses/theses.htm

    Der Hauptmangel alles bisherigen Materialismus (den Feuerbachschen mit eingerechnet) ist, daß der Gegenstand, die Wirklichkeit, Sinnlichkeit, nur unter der Form des Objekts oder der Anschauung gefaßt wird; nicht aber als sinnlich menschliche Tätigkeit, Praxis; nicht subjektiv. Daher die tätige Seite abstrakt im Gegensatz zu dem Materialismus vom dem Idealismus—der natürlich die wirkliche, sinnliche Tätigkeit als solche nicht kennt—entwickelt. Feuerbach will sinnliche—von den Gedankenobjekten wirklich unterschiedne Objekte: aber er faßt die menschliche Tätigkeit selbst nicht als gegenständliche Tätigkeit. Er betrachtet daher im “Wesen des Christenthums” nur das theoretische Verhalten als das echt menschliche, während die Praxis nur in ihrer schmutzig-jüdischen Erscheinungsform gefaßt und fixiert wird. Er begreift daher nicht die Bedeutung der “revolutionären”, der “praktisch-kritischen” Tätigkeit. (Marx 1845, Marx’ emphases)

  6. It should be noted, that Ivan Pavlov died long before and this session was nothing but using his name.

  7. An essential thesis of Marx’s theory is that evolution of society is determined by labor productivity. Socialism was expected to overcome capitalism for labor productivity would be higher.

  8. Since 1938—State Institute for Brain Research named after Bekhterev; in 1948 renamed as Institute for Physiology of the Central Nervous System of the Academy of Medical Sciences of the USSR; since 1950 – part of the Physiological Institute of the USSR Academy of Sciences named after Pavlov.

  9. Kierkegaard’s concept of the “leap”, of courage and uncertainty, has perhaps a theoretical cousin in Niels Bohr’s concept of spontaneous and discontinuous leaps in Physics. In both cases a phenomenon, a choice or an act in Kierkegaard’s case, and a physical event in Bohr’s, is happening without sufficient (but perhaps with some necessary) causation or reason. There is even a cousin in modern Mathematics after the introduction of the Axiom of Choice where a selection or a choice from some source takes place without a sufficient defining criterion. There is a discontinuity or “gap” between act and premises, and this is not considered as a deficiency, as it should be in a mechanistic understanding, but as an ontological condition. To take a more everyday example well-known from clinical psychological practice, to stop smoking it is not sufficient to be motivated and have the full insight in the negative consequences of continuing. Premises are never sufficient, you simply have to decide to stop. And back to the philosophical classics: In the triple of Wissen, Wünschen and Willen, the last can’t be reduced to the first two, to paraphrase the Danish-Holstein philosopher and psychologist Johan Nicolai Tetens (1738–1807) who heavily influenced Immanel Kant and Danish philosophy and psychology.

  10. There are many of these “Numskull” tales in other cultures also, e.g. about “Numskull Ivan” and “Numskull Emelya” in Russian folklore and literature, and of course the famous old Persian fairy tale of “The three princes of Serendip”.

  11. In some way Descartes was right in his distinction between a punctiform Res Cogitans and an extensive Res Extensa. But instead of the first representing psyche and the second the physical world, it should rather be opposite if we focus on what is the defining context of phenomena. This is the “Copernican turn” needed in ontology!

  12. To prevent possible misunderstandings it should be stressed that entanglement between distant particles is not an example of causal interaction and that entanglement can’t be used as a carrier of information from one particle to another in which case it would also be in contradiction with Theory of Relativity, which it is not, despite some popular interpretations. So, we must disappoint those who think entanglement opens for Extrasensory Perception, interactions exceeding the speed of light, and the like. In the same way breaking of the principles of universality and proximal causation in Psychology is not in any way in contradiction with the laws of Physics and does not open for any “supernatural” phenomena. That these principles apply to some domains in Reality, and not to others, is no contradiction if the domains are well defined. And once more: Because both entanglement and Psyche are not restricted by principles of mechanicism, this does not in itself mean that Psyche has anything to do with entanglement. Here the latter is just used as a counterexample of the hegemony of mechanicism.

  13. This is in fact taken seriously in modern Mathematical Logic which cannot be grounded without imagination of so-called “models” (Crossley et al. 1972). That imagination of the counterfactual is a necessary tool in so-called indirect proofs in Mathematics has been known since Antiquity.

  14. All works in the reference list by Engelsted and Mammen can be downloaded freely from the links, respectively:

    http://engelsted.net/engelstedbibliografi.htm

    http://engelsted.net/mammenbibliografi.htm

References

All works in the reference list by Engelsted and Mammen can be downloaded freely from the links, respectively:

http://engelsted.net/engelstedbibliografi.htm

http://engelsted.net/mammenbibliografi.htm

  • Ananiev, B. G. (1961). Teoria ozhuzheniy [sensory processes]. Leningrad: Izdatel’stvo LGU.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ananiev, B. G. (1977). O problemah sovremennogo chelovekoznania [current problems of human nature investigations]. Moscow: Nauka.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bærentsen, K. B. (2003). Hvordan får man en fjernbetjening til at give mening? [Making sense of a remote control]. In A. Aboulafia, H. Hybschmann Hansen, T. Hansen, & J. Bang (Eds.), Virksomhed, betydning, mening (pp. 141–171). Roskilde: Roskilde Universitetsforlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bærentsen, K. B., & Trettvik, J. (2002). An activity approach to affordance. In O. W. Bertelsen, S. Bødker, & K. Kuuti (Eds.), Proceedings of the second Nordic conference on human-computer interaction (NordicCHI 2002) (pp. 51–60). Aarhus: Association for Computer Machinery.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Basov, M. J. (1928). Obzhie osnovy pedologii [general foundations of pedology]. Moscow-Leningrad: Gosudarstvennoje isdatel’stvo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blonsky, P. P. (1934). Pedologija [pedology]. Moscow: Gosudarstvennoje uchebno-pedagogicheskoje isdatel’stvo, tip “Pech.dvor”.

  • Bødker, S., & Klokmose, C. N. (2011). The human-artifact model: an activity theoretical approach to artifact ecologies. Human Computer Interaction, 26(4), 315–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Castro, J., & Lafuente, E. (2007). Westernalization in the mirror: on the cultural reception of western psychology. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 41(1), 106–113.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Christensen, A.-L. (1974). Luria’s neuropsychological investigations. Copenhagen: Munksgaard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cole, M., & Wertsch, J. (1996). Contemporary implications of Vygotsky and Luria. Worcester: Clark University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crossley, J. N., Ash, C. J., Brickhill, C. J., Stillwell, J. C. & Williams, N. H. (1972). What is mathematical logic? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Davidov, V. (1986). Problemy razvivajuzhego obuchenia [problems of developmental education]. Moscow: Pedagogika.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dreier, O. (Ed.). (1979). Den kritiske psykologi. [The Critical Psychology]. Copenhagen: Rhodos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelsted, N. (1989a). What is the psyche and how did it get into the world? In N. Engelsted, L. Hem, & J. Mammen (Eds.), Essays in general psychology. Seven Danish contributions (pp. 13–48). Århus: Aarhus University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelsted, N. (1989b). Personlighedens almene grundlag I & II [The general foundation of personality, Vol. I & II]. Århus: Aarhus Universitetsforlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelsted, N. (1992). A missing link in AT? Multidisciplinary Newsletter for Activity Theory, (11/12), 49–54.

  • Engelsted, N. (1993). At a crossroads—an introduction. In N. Engelsted, M. Hedegaard, B. Karpatschof, & A. Mortensen (Eds.), The societal subject (pp. 1–14). Århus: Aarhus University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelsted, N. (2002). Back to basics. Journal of Anthropological Psychology, 11, 44–57.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engelsted, N. (2006). Humans are apes, only they know. Commentary to Jill Byrnit: primate theory of mind: a state-of-the-art review. Journal of Anthropological Psychology, 17, 34–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Engeström, Y., Hakkarainen, P., & Hedegaard, M. (1984). On the methodological basis of research in teaching and learning. In M. Hedegaard, P. Hakkarainen, & Y. Engeström (Eds.), Learning and teaching on a scientific basis. Methodological and epistemological aspects of the activity theory of learning and teaching. Aarhus: Institute of Psychology, Aarhus University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fromm, E. (1956). The art of loving. New York: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galperin, P. Y. (1983). K vospominaniam ob A.N. Leontieve [concerning memoirs about A.N.Leontiev]. In A. Zaporozhetz & V. Zinchenko (Eds.), A.N. Leontiev i sovremennaja psykhologia [A.N. Leontiev and contemporary psychology] (pp. 240–244). Moscow: Izdatel’stvo MGU.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1966). The senses considered as perceptual systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedegaard, M. (2011). A cultural-historical approach to children’s development of multiple identities. In M. Kontopodis, C. Wulf, & B. Fichtner (Eds.), Children-culture emerging educational challenge (pp. 117–135). N. Y: Springer. International perspectives on early childhood education and development; Nr. 2, vol. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hedegaard, M. (2012). A cultural-historical theory of children’s development. In L. Miller, R. Drury, & C. Cable (Eds.), Extending professional practice in the early years (pp. 193–210). London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holzkamp, K. (1973). Sinnliche erkenntnis—Historischer Ursprung und gesellschaftlicher Funktion der Wahrnehmung. Frankfurt a. M: Fischer Athenäum Taschenbuch Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holzkamp, K. (1983). Grundlegung der Psychologie. Frankfurt: Campus Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ilyenkov, E. V. (1977). The concept of the ideal. In Philosophy in the USSR. Problems of dialectical materialism (pp. 71–91). Moscow: Progress Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jørgensen, T. E., & Jensen, S. L. B. (2008). 1968—og det der fulgte [1968—and what followed]. Copenhagen: Gyldendal.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jung, C. G. (1971). Psychological types. Princeton: Princeton University Press. German original, 1921.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1956, orig. 1781/1787). Kritik der reinen Vernunft. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

  • Kornilov, K. N. (1924). Sovremennaja psihologija i marksizm [modern psychology and Marxism]. Leningrad: Gosudarstvennoye isdatel’stvo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krøjgaard, P. (2000). Object individuation in 10-month-old infants: do significant objects make a difference? Cognitive Development, 15, 169–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krøjgaard, P. (2003). Object individuation in 10-month-old infants: manipulating the amount of introduction. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 21, 447–463.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krøjgaard, P. (2007). Comparing infants’ use of featural and spatiotemporal information in an object individuation task using a new event-monitoring design. Developmental Science, 10(6), 892–909.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Krøjgaard, P. (2009). The human ability to single out and track specific objects through space and time: origin and application. In H. Høgh-Olesen, J. Tønnesvang, & P. Bertelsen (Eds.), Human characteristics. Evolutionary perspectives on human mind and kind (pp. 89–116). Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lazursky, A. F. (1918). Estestvennii eksperiment i ego shkol’noje primenenije [a natural experiment and its school application]. Petrograd: Tipographija Rikkera.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lektorsky, V. (2013). German philosophy and Russian humanitarian thought: Sergei Rubinstein and Gustav Shpet. Russian Studies in Philosophy, 52(1), 82–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leontiev, A. N. (1973). Probleme der Entwicklung des Psychischen. Berlin: Volk und Wissen. Russian ed., 1959.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leontiev, A. N. (1979). Tätigkeit, Bewusstsein, Persönlichkeit. Berlin: Volk und Wissen. Russian ed. 1977 (1975).

    Google Scholar 

  • Leontiev, A. N. (1982). Psychologie des Abbilds. Forum Kritische Psychologie, 9, 5–9. translated from a Russian manuscript, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leontiev, A. N. (1986). Problema dejatelnosty v istorii sovetskoi psikhologii [problems of activity in the history of Soviet psychology]. Voprosy Psikhologii, 4, 109–120.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewin, K. (1931). Der Übergang von aristotelischen zur galileischen Denkweise in Biologie und Psychologie. Erkenntnis, 1(1931), 421–466. Reprinted in: K. Lewin: Werkausgabe (hrsg. von C.-F. Graumann), Bd. 1 . Bern/Stuttgart: Hans Huber/Clett Cotta, 1981, pp. 233–278. The conflict between Aristotelian and Galilean modes of thought in contemporary psychology. Journal of General Psychology, 5 , 141–177. Reprinted in: K. Lewin: A dynamic theory of personality . N.Y.: McGraw-Hill, 1935, pp. 1–42.

  • Lewin, K. (1952). Field theory in social science: Selected theoretical papers by Kurt Lewin. London: Tavistock.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mammen, J. (1968a). Uklarheder i fænomenologien [confusions in phenomenology]. Dansk Psykolognyt, 22(4), 50–51. Reprinted in: M. Brun (red.). Fænomenologi til debat (pp. 60–61). Danmarks Lærerhøjskole og Københavns Universitet, 1975.

  • Mammen, J. (1968b). Det er emnelærens metodik, som kritiseres [the methodology of Copenhagen descriptive psychology (“emnelære”) is what I criticize]. Dansk Psykolognyt, 22(10), 171–172. Reprinted in: M. Brun (red.). Fænomenologien til debat .(pp. 72–73). Danmarks Lærerhøjskole og Københavns Universitet, 1975.

  • Mammen, J. (1973). Gensvar til Tranekjær [reply to Tranekjær]. Dansk Psykolognyt, 27(23), 453–454.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mammen, J. (1986). Erkendelsen som objektrelation [cognition as object relation]. Psyke & Logos, 7(1), 178–202 (Summary, p. 207).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mammen, J. (1989). The relationship between subject and object from the perspective of activity theory. In N. Engelsted, L. Hem, & J. Mammen (Eds.), Essays in general psychology. Seven Danish contributions (pp. 71–94). Århus: Aarhus University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mammen, J. (1993). The elements of psychology. In N. Engelsted, M. Hedegaard, B. Karpatschof, & A. Mortensen (Eds.), The societal subject (pp. 29–44). Århus: Aarhus University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mammen, J. (1994). Rubinstein’s conception of the “leap” to the specifically human consciousness in Sein und Bewußtsein: a critical evaluation. Multidisciplinary Newsletter for Activity Theory, 15(16), 29–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mammen, J. (1996). Den menneskelige sans. Et essay om psykologiens genstandsområde [the human sense. An essay on the object of psychology]. Copenhagen: Dansk Psykologisk Forlag. 1st ed. 1983, 2nd ed. 1989.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mammen, J. (1997). Menneskebilleder i psykologien—og en diskussion med teologien [the conception of human in psychology—and a discourse with theology]. In P. Bertelsen, L. Hem, & J. Mammen (Eds.), Erkendelse, stræben, følelse (pp. 103–119). Århus: Aarhus Universitetsforlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mammen, J. (2002). Mapping the subject: the renewal of scientific psychology. Journal of Anthropological Psychology, 11, 77–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mammen, J. (2009a). Findes der en særlig dansk psykologi? [Is there a specific Danish psychology?]. Psyke og Logos, 30(1), 355–379.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mammen, J. (2009b). Til forsvar for den sunde fornuft. Kan psykologien blive en videnskab uden at fjerne sig fra virkeligheden? [a plea for common sense: can psychology become a science without disowning reality? Inaugural lecture as honorary professor at University of Aalborg]. Psyke & Logos, 30(2), 759–777.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mammen, J., Engelsted, N., et al. (2000). Psykens topologi. Det matematiske grundlag for teorien om sanse- og udvalgskategorier. Breve til Selskabet for Teoretisk Psykologi [the topology of psyche. The mathematical foundation for the theory of sense and choice categories. Letters to the society for theoretical psychology]. Psykologisk Skriftserie, Psykologisk Institut, Aarhus Universitet, Vol. 25, No. 1.

  • Marsella, A. (2012). Psychology and globalization: understanding a complex relationship. Journal of Social Issues, 68(3), 454–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marx, K. (1844). Ökonomisch-Philosophische Manuskripte. Drittes Manuskript. In: Marx/Engels. Werke, Bd. 40. Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1965–1975.

  • Marx, K. (1845). Thesen über Feuerbach. In: Marx/Engels. Werke, Bd. 3, p. 3, & Ergänzungsband. Berlin: Dietz Verlag, 1965–1975.

  • Mironenko, I. A. (2006). O koncepcii predmeta psikhologicheskoi nauki [what is the domain of psychological science?]. Metodologia i Historia Psychologii, № 1, 160–173.

  • Mironenko, I. A. (2008). On some difficulties in the dialogue with foreign colleagues. In Y. Zinchenko & V. Petrenko (Eds.), Psychology in Russia: State of the art (pp. 41–47). Moscow: Department of Psychology MSU & IG-SOCIN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mironenko, I. A. (2009a). “Great ideas” in Russian psychology: personality impact on psycho-physiological functions and causal approach to self-determination. In Y. Zinchenko & V. Petrenko (Eds.), Psychology in Russia: State of the art (pp. 225–238). Moscow: Department of Psychology MSU & IG-SOCIN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mironenko, I. A. (2009b). O proshlom, nastojazhem i buduzhem otechestvennoi sravnitelnoi psichologii [the past, the present and the future of Russian school in comparative psychology]. Metodologia i Historia Psychologii, 4(2), 45–59.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mironenko, I. A. (2010). Life and work of a woman who pioneered evolutionary psychology: Nadezhda Ladygina-Kots. In J. Boos & M. Sinatra (Eds.), The history of the human sciences: An open atmosphere (pp. 231–238). Bari: Pensa Multimedia Editore.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mironenko, I. A. (2013). Concerning interpretations of activity theory. Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 47(3), 376–393.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Moghaddam, F. M. (1987). Psychology in the three worlds: as reflected by the crisis in social psychology and the move toward indigenous third-world psychology. American Psychologist, 42(10), 912–920.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. H. (1982). Zermelo’s axiom of choice. Its origins, development, and influence. N. Y.: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nygren, A. (1956). Den kristna kärlekstanken genom tiderna, Vol. I-III. [The Christian concept of love through the times]. Stockholm: Svenska Kyrkans Diakonisbestyrelses Bokförlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penrose, R. (1989). The emperor’s new mind. Concerning computers, minds, and the laws of physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pind, J. (2014). Figure and ground: Edgar Rubin and psychology in Denmark 1850–1950. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Poulsen, H. (1993). Guds kærlighed og menneskenes. [God’s love, and man’s]. Aarhus: Aarhus University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, D. N. (2002). Inventing the subject: the renewal of “psychological” psychology. Journal of Anthropological Psychology, 11, 6–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rose, N. (2008). Psychology as a social science. Subjectivity, 23, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, S. L. (1940). Osnovy obzhej psykhologii [foundations of general psychology]. Мoscow: Uchpedgiz.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, S. L. (1945). Puti i dostizhenia sovetskoi psikhologii (o soznanii I dejatelnosti cheloveka) [ways and achievements of Soviet psychology (on human consciousness and activity)]. Bulletin from the Academy of Science, 4, 67–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, S. L. (1971). Grundlagen der allgemeinen Psychologie. Berlin: Volk und Wissen. from Russian edition in1946.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, S. L. (1973). Sein und Bewußtsein. Berlin: Akademie-Verlag. from Russian edition in 1957.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein, S. L. (1974). Das Denken und die Wege seiner Erforschung. Berlin: Deutscher Verlag der Wissenschaften. from Russian edition in 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rubinstein. (1997). O philosofskoi systeme Hermana Kogena [about the philosophical system of Hermann Cohen]. In A. Brushlinsky (Ed.), Chelovek i mir [human being and the world] (pp. 138–160). Moscow: Nauka.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sechenov, I. M. (1873a). Psikhologicheskie etudy [Psychological Studies]. St. Petersburg: Sushchinskii.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sechenov, I. M. (1873b). Komu i kak razrabatyvat’ psikhologiiu? [who must investigate the problems of psychology, and how]. St. Petersburg: Sushchinskii.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sechenov I. M. (1878). Elementy mysli [elements of thought]. Vestnik Evropy, 1878, # 4.

  • Smedslund, J., & Ross, L. (2014). Research-based knowledge in psychology: what, if anything, is its incremental value to the practioner? Integrative Psychological and Behavioral Science, 43(4), 363–383.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1964). Individuals. An essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Methuen. University Paperbacks, original, 1959.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toomela, A. (2000). Activity theory is a dead end for cultural-historical psychology. Culture & Psychology, 6, 353–364.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turing, A. M. (1950). Computing machinery and intelligence. Mind, 59, No. 236, (Oct.). Reprinted in L. Bannon & Z. Pylyshyn (eds.). Perspectives in the computer revolution. Norwood, NJ: Ablex, 1989.

  • Valsiner, J. (2012). A guided science: History of psychology in the mirror of its making. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. S. (1931). Psihotehnika i pedologija [psychotechnics and pedology]. Psihotehnika i Psihofiziologiâ Truda, 2–3, 173–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vygotsky, L. S. (1982). Sobranie sochinenij [the collected works], V. 1–6. Moscow: Pedagogika.

    Google Scholar 

  • Xu, F., & Carey, S. (1996). Infants’ metaphysics: the case of numerical identity. Cognitive Psychology, 30, 111–153.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jens Mammen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Mammen, J., Mironenko, I. Activity Theories and the Ontology of Psychology: Learning from Danish and Russian Experiences. Integr. psych. behav. 49, 681–713 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-015-9313-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-015-9313-7

Keywords

Navigation