Skip to main content
Log in

Philo’s Argument from Evil in Hume’s Dialogues X: A Semantic Interpretation

  • Published:
Sophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Philo's argument from evil in a much-discussed passage in Part X of Hume's Dialogues concerning Natural Religion (1779) has been interpreted in three main ways: as a logical argument from evil, as an evidential argument from evil, and as an argument against natural theology's inference of a benevolent and merciful God from the course of the world. I argue that Philo is not offering an argument of any of these sorts, but is arguing that there is a radical disanalogy between the meanings of terms like ‘merciful’ and ‘benevolent’ when applied to God and human beings respectively. Drawing on the new ‘Irreligious Interpretation’ of Hume's philosophy developed by Paul Russell (2002, 2008), I suggest that the underlying aim of Philo's argument appears to be to show, in opposition to Christian teaching, that these terms, when applied to God, are in effect meaningless.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. See in particular Russell 2002 and 2008.

  2. Hume 1779, 105–106. Numbered square brackets have been added to facilitate future referencing.

  3. Hume 1779, 106–107.

  4. Hume 1779, 110–111.

  5. Hume 1779, 111.

  6. Hume 1779, 112.

  7. Others who concur with this interpretation include Henry D. Aiken 1958, 79; Robert and Marilyn Adams 1990, 3; D.Z. Phillips 2004, 3–5; and Holden 2010, 149–152.

  8. Nelson Pike 1963, 180–181.

  9. Pike 1963, 182.

  10. Pike 1963, 182.

  11. Pike 1963, 182.

  12. Hume 1779, 182.

  13. It may be worth noting that even if the claims (4) and (5) were argued for by Philo, they are not – contrary to what Pike maintains – formally inconsistent with (1), for they are consistent with the claim that ‘God does not want to prevent suffering,’ which, via (4), entails that God is not able to prevent suffering, which in turn entails, via (5), that God would not prevent suffering, which is consistent with there being suffering in the world.

  14. Pike 1963, 182.

  15. See, e.g., Ralph Cudworth 1743, 78–79; Pierre Bayle 1734, 513; and King 1732, 77–78. For documentation of Hume’s acquaintance with these three books, see Ernest Campbell Mossner 1948, 501–503. Lactantius’ statement occurs in his ‘A Treatise on the Anger of God’ (De ira Dei); see Lactantius 1974, 271.

  16. J.C.A. Gaskin 1978, 54.

  17. Davies 2006, 11.

  18. Gaskin 1978, 54.

  19. Davies 2006, 10.

  20. Gaskin 1978, 54.

  21. Others who concur with this interpretation include Keith Yandell 2005, 125; Beryl Logan 1996, 198; Klaas J. Kraay 2003, 285; and Tony Pitson 2008, 92.

  22. William Capitan 1966, 82.

  23. Stanley Tweyman 1991, 70.

  24. William Lad Sessions 2002, 156.

  25. Capitan 1966, 84.

  26. Sessions 2002, 156.

  27. Tweyman 1991, 71.

  28. Hume 1779, 48.

  29. Hume 1779, 24.

  30. By the ‘underlying aim’ of an argument I mean the objective that the author of the argument had in mind in proposing the argument.

  31. See, e.g., Norman Kemp Smith 1935, 73–96; Ernest Mossner 1977, 1–22; Dorothy Coleman 1989, 179–190; R.H. Hurlbutt III 1956, 486–497; and Charles Echelbarger 1975, 19–35.

  32. Kemp Smith 1935, 87.

  33. Mossner 1977, 4. (The letter is to Gilbert Elliot of Minto and is dated March 10, 1751.)

  34. Coleman 1989, 183.

  35. B.M. Laing 1937, 178.

  36. Shane Andre 1993, 156. (The letter is to William Strahan and is dated June 8, 1776.)

  37. Hume 1779, 154.

  38. James Noxon 1964, 256. For Hume’s aversion to Christianity, see Kemp Smith 1935, 11–31.

  39. See, e.g., Charles Hendel 1963, 271; Anders Jeffner 1966, 208; and Gaskin 1993, 490n10.

  40. Hume 1779, 112.

  41. Hume 1748, 159, 162–163. Hume says that all attempts to circumvent this retraction involve ‘inextricable Difficulties, and even Contradictions.’

  42. See especially Russell’s 2008. The ‘irreligious’ interpretation of Hume was anticipated by Mossner: ‘Hume’s aversion […] to Christianity was deep-rooted and informed his entire career as philosopher, from Treatise to Dialogue’ (1977, 16); and A. J. Ayer: ‘the discrediting […] of any form of religious belief was one of the principal aims Hume’s philosophy’; 1980, 23.

  43. Philip Schaff (ed.) 1877, 606.

  44. See, e.g., Hume 1748, 23–25. For more on Hume’s empiricist view of word meaning, see Yandell 2005, 62–69.

  45. Aquinas 1948, 160. (ST I, q13, a5.)

  46. See Russell 2008, 282–283.

  47. Kemp Smith 1935, 8.

  48. See Russell 2002, 164–165; and 2008, 282–286.

  49. Schaff (ed.) 1877, 608 (my emphasis).

  50. It may be noted that Calvinism’s doctrine that all events are ordained by God is inconsistent with a libertarian view of free will, for on such a view there are events that must be beyond what God can ordain, namely the volitional actions of free agents. Hume concurred with Calvinism in rejecting libertarianism, although, of course, for different reasons; see Hume 1748, 129–163.

  51. Schaff (ed.) 1877, 615.

References

  • Adams, M. M., & Adams, R. M. (1990). Introduction. In M. M. Adams & R. M. Adams (Eds.), The Problem of Evil (pp. 1–24). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aiken, H. D. (1958). God and Evil. Ethics, 68(2), 77–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andre, S. (1993). Was Hume an Atheist? Hume Studies, 19(1), 141–166.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aquinas, T. (1948) [1265-73]. Summa Theologica, trans. the English Dominican Province. London: Sheed and Ward.

  • Ayer, A. J. (1980). Hume. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayle, P. (1734) [1697]. The dictionary historical and critical. 2nd ed., vol. 4. London.

  • Capaldi, N. (1970). Hume’s Philosophy of Religion: God without Ethics. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion, 1(4), 233–240.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capitan, W. (1966). Part X of Hume’s Dialogues. American Philosophical Quarterly, 3(1), 82–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, D. (1989). Interpreting Hume’s ‘Dialogues’. Religious Studies, 25(2), 179–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cudworth, R. (1743) [1671]. The true Intellectual System of the Universe, 2nd ed., vol. 1. London.

  • Davies, B. (2006). The Reality of God and the Problem of Evil. London: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Echelbarger, C. (1975). Hume’s Tacit Atheism. Religious Studies, 11(1), 19–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gaskin, J. C. A. (1978). Hume’s Philosophy of Religion. London: The MacMillian Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gaskin, J. C. A. (1993). Hume on Religion. In D. F. Norton & J. Taylor (Eds.), The Cambridge Companion to Hume (2nd ed., pp. 480–513). New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendel, C. (1963). Studies in the Philosophy of David Hume. New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holden, T. (2010). The Spectres of False Divinity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1748). Philosophical Essays concerning Human Understanding [Enquiry concerning Human Understanding]. London.

  • Hume, D. (1779). Dialogues concerning Natural Religion. London.

  • Hurlbutt, R. H., III. (1956). David Hume and Scientific Theism. Journal of the History of Ideas, 17(4), 486–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffner, A. (1966). Butler and Hume on Religion. Stockholm: Diakonistyrelsens bokförlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kemp Smith, N. (1935). Hume’s Dialogues concerning Natural Religion. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • King, W. (1732) [1703]. An Essay on the Origin of Evil. London.

  • Kraay, K. (2003). Philo’s Argument for Divine Amorality Reconsidered. Hume Studies, 29(2), 283–304.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lactantius (1974). A Treatise on the Anger of God. (trans. William Fletcher). In Alexander Roberts and James Donaldson (Eds.), The Ante-Nicene Fathers. (pp. 259–280). Grand Rapids, MI: Eerdmans.

  • Laing, B. M. (1937). Hume’s Dialogues concerning Natural Religion. Philosophy, 12(46), 175–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Logan, B. (1996). Why Hume Wasn’t an Atheist: A Reply to Andre. Hume Studies, 22(1), 193–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mossner, E. C. (1948). Hume’s Early Memoranda, 1729-1740: The Complete Text. Journal of the History of Ideas, 9(4), 492–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mossner, E. C. (1977). Hume and the Legacy of the Dialogues. In G. P. Morice (Ed.), David Hume: Bicentenary Papers (pp. 1–22). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noxon, J. (1964). Hume’s Agnosticism. Philosophical Review, 73(2), 248–261.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, D. Z. (2004). The Problem of Evil and the Problem of God. London: SCM Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pike, N. (1963). Hume on Evil. Philosophical Review, 72(2), 180–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pitson, T. (2008). The Miseries of Life: Hume and the Problem of Evil. Hume Studies, 34(1), 89–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, P. (2002). Freedom and Moral Sentiment: Hume’s Way of Naturalizing Responsibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Russell, P. (2008). The Riddle of Hume’s Treatise: Scepticism, Naturalism and Irreligion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Schaff, P. (Ed.). (1877). The Creeds of Christendom, vol. 3. New York: Harper & Brothers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sessions, W. L. (2002). Reading Hume’s Dialogues: A Veneration for True Religion. Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tweyman, S. (1991). Dialogues concerning Natural Religion in Focus. London and New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yandell, K. (2005). ‘David Hume on Meaning, Verification and Natural Theology,’ in In Defense of Natural Theology: A Post-Humean Assessment, eds. James Sennett and Douglas Groothius. Drowners Grove, Ill: InterVarsity Press, 58–81.

Download references

Acknowledgements

Many thanks to Professor Paul Russell, of the University of British Columbia, Canada, and to Professor Anders Jeffner, of Uppsala University and the Royal Academy of Letters, History and Antiquities, Sweden, for helpful feedback on earlier versions of this paper. Work on this paper was made possible by a generous grant from the Swedish Research Council.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Anders Kraal.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Kraal, A. Philo’s Argument from Evil in Hume’s Dialogues X: A Semantic Interpretation. SOPHIA 52, 573–592 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-013-0372-2

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11841-013-0372-2

Keywords

Navigation