Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Justifying the Distinction Between Justifications and Power (Justifications vs. Power)

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Criminal Law and Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The paper suggests that there are two different ways in which a legal system restricts an individual’s rights. It can either grant a power that revokes the legal protection of the right or it can acknowledge the infringement of a legal right and yet justify such an infringement by means of a criminal law justification. The distinction proposed by the paper has both expressive and practical implications and is useful in solving dilemmas arising in emergencies when constitutional constraints make it impossible to grant the power to revoke legal protection of a basic right. In some of these situations a criminal law justification might support infringement of such a right. This claim is demonstrated by analyzing the ruling of the German Constitutional Court concerning the shooting down of a hijacked airplane in circumstances similar to those of September 11.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. But see Berman 2003, p. 9.

  2. See discussion infra “The Importance of Distinguishing between Legal Power and Criminal Law Justifications”.

  3. Robinson's approach was explicitly criticized by George Fletcher (1975). See also Husak (1989, pp. 504–517); Thorburn (2008, pp. 1086–1089); Gardner (2007, pp. 92–120); Duff (2007, pp. 277–284).

  4. A different approach will be discussed infra Justifying the Wrongdoing.

  5. For the distinction between the offense definition and justifications see Fletcher (1975, pp. 308–310); Gardner (2007, pp. 216–228); Campbell (1987, pp. 73–86).

  6. See the discussion at “The Importance of Distinguishing between Legal Power and Criminal Law Justifications” infra.

  7. For the power of police officer to arrest a suspect without a judicial warrant, see 18 United States Code Annotated § 3052 (2006) (regarding FBI agents); Model Penal Code § 120.1; United States v. Watson (1976); Atwater v. City of Lago Vista (2001).

  8. Locke (1967, § 181), Uniacke (1994, pp. 196–208), Leverick (2006, pp. 61–63) claim that aggressors forfeit their right to life. This approach is rejected by Fletcher (1980, pp. 135–155), Kadish (1976, pp. 883–886), Kaufman (2004, pp. 23–24), Segev (2005, p. 407). This paper adopts the last approach and assumes that aggressors do not lose their right of life by virtue of their unlawful aggression.

  9. In various states, the offense itself is labeled as "unlawful imprisonment" (New York Penal Law §§135.05-10; Revised Code of Washington, § 9A.40.040).

  10. However, 18 United States Code Annotated § 1111 (2006), defines murder as "the unlawful killing of a human being with malice aforethought".

  11. The example is analyzed by Campbell (1987, p. 83), and cited by Gardner (2007, p. 145).

  12. See supra note 8.

  13. See Ibid.

  14. See supra note 8.

  15. Model Penal code § 3.03 grants the justification in executing official tasks to both the officials and private individuals who assist them.

  16. Fletcher (1978 pp. 698–707), on the other hand, argues that the woman's lack of consent should not be classified as an element of rape, but rather as a justification.

  17. Baker (2009) explains the rationale of limiting the scope of consent as a criminal law justification.

  18. See supra Criminal Law Justifications.

  19. See supra text accompanying note 4.

  20. See supra Justifying the Wrongdoing.

  21. Model Penal Code § 3.01(2) provides: “The fact that a conduct is justifiable under this Article does not abolish or impair any remedy for such conduct which is available in any civil action”.

  22. Alternatively, compensation could be based on restitution (Virgo 1999, p. 312; Rogers 2006, p. 1096).

  23. Supra note 8.

  24. Supra Self-Defense and the Right to Life.

  25. See supra note 8.

  26. Under 28 U.S.C.A. § 2680(a) (2006) the United States is not liable for “Any claim based upon an act or omission of an employee of the Government, exercising due care, in the execution of a statute or regulation …”.

  27. Several states in the United States enacted statutes granting limited compensation for wrongly convicted prisoners who were released. In 2007, though, most of those wrongfully incarcerated received no compensation (Bernhard 2009; Entin 2005, p. 161).

  28. Note that we are discussing compensation for the reasonable exercises of power, parallel to the compensations for justified infringement of rights. Some legal systems go further and deny compensation even for the negligent exercise of the power (Dobbs 2000, pp. 702–704; Booth and Squires 2006, pp. 589–590).

  29. Robinson (1996) presents an opposite view.

  30. Even with regard to official power, the official may sometimes decide to exercise the power to change individual's rights and carry out the decision herself, for example a police officer arresting a suspect on reasonable grounds.

  31. The sentencing guidelines in the UK are determined by The Sentencing Guidelines Council, see http://www.sentencing-guidelines.gov.uk.

  32. The German Court based its ruling on constitutional considerations under the German Basic Law; the Court did not discuss the law of war.

  33. For the opposite view, according to which “the passengers’ lives are not being targeted as a means of thwarting the hijackers”, see: Kleinig and Kasachkoff 2010; Hörnle (2007, pp. 606–607); Zamir and Medina (2008, pp. 375–376).

  34. I elaborated on that distinction in a different article (Gur-Arye 1986).

  35. See supra Justifying the Wrongdoing.

  36. Hörnle (2007, pp. 600–604) analyzes such a scenario to find that a private pilot who has shot down the airplane will be granted an excuse; the shooting down of the airplane by a state official is justified.

References

  • Ashworth, A. (2006). Principles of criminal law (5th ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atwater v. City of Lago Vista, 532 U.S. 318 (2001)

  • Baker, D. J. (2009). The moral limits of consent as a defense in the criminal law. New Criminal Law Review, 12(1), 93–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baron, M. W. (2005). Justifications and excuses. Ohio State Journal of Criminal Law, 2, 387–406.

    Google Scholar 

  • Berman, M. (2003). Justification and excuse, law and morality. Duke Law Journal, 53(1), 1–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernhard, A. (2009). Symposium: A short overview of the statutory remedies for the wrongly convicted: What works, what doesn’t and why. Public Interest Law Journal, 18, 403–425.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackstone, W. (1765). Commentaries on the laws of England. London: Dawson of Pall Mall 1966.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohlander, M. (2006). In Extremis—Hijacked Airplanes, ‘Collateral Damage’ and the limits of criminal law. Criminal Law Review, 2006, 579–592.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohlander, M. (2009). Principles of German criminal law. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Booth, C. Q. C., & Squires, D. (2006). The negligence liability of public authorities. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bronitt, S., & Stephens, D. (2007). “Flying under the Radar”—The use of lethal force against Hijacked Aircraft: Recent australian developments. Oxford University Commonwealth Law Journal, 7(2), 265–278.

    Google Scholar 

  • BVerfGE 2006 115, 118. http://www.bundesverfassungsgericht.de/entscheidungen/rs20060215_1bvr035705en.html. Accessed 5 November 2010.

  • Campbell, K. (1987). Offence and defence. In I. H. Dennis (Ed.), Criminal law and justice: Essays from the W. G. Hart Workshop, 1986 (pp. 73). London: Sweet & Maxwell.

  • Coady, C. A. J. (2009). The problem of dirty hands. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/dirty-hands/. Accessed 5 November 2010.

  • Cohan, J. A. (2007). Private and public necessity and the violation of property rights. North Dakota Law Review, 83, 651–734.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coke, E. (1644). The Institute of the Laws of England. Garland Publishing Inc. 1979

  • Dan-Cohen, M. (2002). Harmful thoughts: Essays on law, self, and morality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobbs, D. B. (2000). The law of torts. St. Paul, MN: West.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dressler, J. (1984). New thoughts about the concept of justification in the criminal law: A critique of Fletcher’s thinking and rethinking. UCLA Law Review, 32, 61–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dressler, J. (1987). Justifications and excuse: A brief review of the concepts and literature. Wayne Law Review, 33(4), 1155–1176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dressler, J. (1988). Reflections on excusing wrongdoers: Moral theory, new excuses and the model penal code. Rutgers Law Journal, 19, 671–716.

    Google Scholar 

  • Duff, A. R. (2007). Answering for crime: Responsibility and liability in the criminal law. Oxford: Hart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Entin, J. L. (2005). Being the government means (almost) never having to say you’re sorry: The Sam Sheppard case and the meaning of wrongful imprisonment. Akron Law Review, 38, 139–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eser, A. (1987). Justification and excuse: A key issue in the concept of crime. In A. Eser & G. Fletcher (Eds.), Justification and excuse: Comparative perspectives (pp. 17–65). Freiburg: Max-Planc Institute Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, G. P. (1975). The right deed for the wrong reason: A reply to Mr. Robinson. UCLA Law Review, 23, 293–321.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, G. P. (1978). Rethinking criminal law. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, G. P. (1979). Should intolerable prison conditions generate a justification or an excuse for escape? UCLA Law Review, 26, 1355–1369.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, G. P. (1980). The right to life. The Monist, 63, 135–158.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, G. P. (1985). The right and the reasonable. Harvard Law Review, 98, 949–982.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, G. P. (1998). Basic concepts of criminal law. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fletcher, G. P. (2007). The grammar of criminal law: American, comparative, and international. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, J. B. (2007). Offences and defences: Selected essays in the philosophy of criminal law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Geiss, R. (2005). Civil aircraft as weapons of large-scale destruction: Countermeasures, article 3bis of the Chicago convention, and the newly adopted German “Luftsicherheitsgesetz”. Michigan Journal of International Law, 27, 227–256.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenawalt, K. (1984). The perplexing borders of justification and excuse. Columbia Law Review, 84(8), 1897–1927.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gur-Arye, M. (1986). Should a criminal law distinguish between necessity as a justification and necessity as an excuse? Law Quarterly Review, 102, 71–89.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gur-Arye, M. (2004). Can the war against terror justify the use of force in interrogations? Reflections in light of the Israeli experience. In S. Levinson (Ed.), Torture: A collection (pp. 183–198). Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harel, A., & Sharon, A. (2008). What is really wrong with Torture. Journal of International Criminal Justice, 6(2), 242–259.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • HCJ 5100/94 Public Committee against Torture in Israel v. The State of Israel [1999] IsrSC 53(4) 817. elyon1.court.gov.il/files_eng/02/690/007/a34/02007690.a34.pdf. Accessed 5 November 2010.

  • Hohfeld, W. (1919). Fundamental legal conception: As applied in judicial reasoning. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hörnle, T. (2007). Hijacked airplanes: May they be shot down? New Criminal Law Review, 10(4), 582–612.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hufnagel, S. M. (2008). German perspectives on the right to life and human dignity in the “War on Terror”. Criminal Law Journal, 32, 100–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hurd, H. M. (1999). Justification and excuse, wrongdoing and culpability. Notre Dame Law Review, 74, 1551–1574.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husak, D. N. (1989). Criminal law: Justifications and the criminal liability of accessories. Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 80(2), 491–520.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Husak, D. N. (1998). Partial defenses. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence, 11(1), 167–192.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kadish, S. (1976). Respect for life and regards for rights in the criminal law. California Law Review, 64(4), 871–901.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, D., & Nussbaum, M. C. (1996). Two conceptions of emotion in criminal law. Columbia Law Review, 96(2), 269–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaufman, W. (2004). Is there a ‘right’ to self-defence? Criminal Justice Ethics, 23, 20–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kleinig, J. & Kasachkoff, Z. (2010) Civil emergencies and the claims of innocence. In S. Bronitt et al. (Eds.), Shooting to kill: The law governing the use of lethal force in context. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

  • Ladiges, M. (2007). Comment—Oliver Lepsius’s human dignity and the downing of aircraft: The German federal constitutional court strikes down a prominent anti-terrorism provision in the new air-transport security act. German Law Journal, 8(3), 307–310.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lepsius, O. (2006). Human dignity and the downing of an aircraft: The German federal constitutional court strikes down a prominent anti-terrorism provision in the new air-transport security act. German Law Journal, 7(9), 761–776.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leverick, F. (2006). Killing in self-defence. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Locke, J. (1967). Two treatises of government, second treatise (reprinted). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Möller, K. (2006). On treating persons as ends: The German aviation security act, human dignity, and the german federal constitutional court. Public Law, 51, 457–466.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, M. S. (1989). Torture and the balance of evils. Israel Law Review, 23, 280–344.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, I. H. (1990). Structuring sentencing discretion: The new federal sentencing guidelines. Journal of Criminal Law and Criminology, 80(4), 883–943.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2001). The fragility of goodness: Luck and ethics in Greek tragedy and philosophy. [Revised edition]. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, J. (1999). Practical reason and norms (2nd ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Regoli, R. M., & Hewitt, J. D. (2007). Exploring criminal justice: The essentials. Canada: Jones & Bartlett Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Riverside County, California v. McLaughlin, 500 U.S. 44 (1991)

  • Robinson, P. H. (1975). A theory of justification: Societal harm as a prerequisite for criminal liability. UCLA Law Review, 23, 266–292.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, P. H. (1984). Criminal law defenses. St. Paul, MN: West.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, P. H. (1996). Competing theories of justifications: Deeds vs. reasons. In A. P. Simester & A. T. G. Smith (Eds.), Harm and culpability (pp. 45). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, W. V. H. (2006). Winifield and Jolowicz on Tort (17th ed.). London: Sweet & Maxwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopp, R. F. (1998). Justification defenses and just convictions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Seavey, W. A. (1942). Principles of Torts. Harvard Law Review, 56, 72–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Segev, R. (2005). Fairness, responsibility, and self-defence. Santa Clara Law Review, 45, 383–460.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, J. C. (1989). Justifications and excuse in the criminal law. London: Stevens.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, J. J. (1986). Self-defense and rights. In W. Parent (Ed.), Rights, restitution and risk: Essays in moral theory (pp. 33). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thorburn, M. (2008). Justifications, powers, and authority. Yale Law Journal, 117, 1070–1130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Travis, S. A. (1996). Guiding the sentencing court’s discretion: A proposed definition of the phrase “non-violent offense” under United States sentencing guideline section 5K2.13. Journal of Criminal Law and criminology, 86(2), 530–558.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Uniacke, S. (1994). Permissible killing: The self-defence justification of homicide. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • United States Sentencing Commission. (2009). Guidelines Manual. http://www.ussc.gov/2009guid/TABCON09.htm

  • United States v. Watson, 423 U.S. 411 (1976)

  • Virgo, G. (1999). The principles of the law of restitution. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walzer, M. (1973). Political action: The problem of dirty hands. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 2(2), 160–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Youngs, R. (2008). Germany: Shooting down aircraft and analyzing computer data. International Journal of Constitutional Law, 6(2), 331–348.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zamir, E., & Medina, B. (2008). Law, morality, and economics: Integrating moral constraints with economic analysis of law. California Law Review, 96, 325–397.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Miriam Gur-Arye.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Gur-Arye, M. Justifying the Distinction Between Justifications and Power (Justifications vs. Power). Criminal Law, Philosophy 5, 293–313 (2011). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-010-9110-9

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11572-010-9110-9

Keywords

Navigation