Skip to main content
Log in

Aquinas on Biological Individuals: An Essay in Analytical Thomism

  • Published:
Philosophia Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper presents a version of analytical Thomism that brings the principles of Aquinas into systematic and sustained contact with the sciences as opposed to contemporary philosophy. The leading idea of this version of analytical Thomism is to test the viability of scholastic principles by seeing if they provide the resources to cope with problems emerging from the natural and social sciences. If they do, then Thomism vindicates itself in the marketplace of ideas. If not, then the analytical Thomist knows where the perennial philosophy needs further development and perhaps revision. The first part of the paper sets out the rationale for this project. The remainder of the paper illustrates this approach by examining a problem emerging from evolutionary biology, namely, the provision of a theory of individuation for living entities.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Examples of neo-Thomists producing excellent work in this vein include Joseph Owens (1951), John Wippel (2000), Cornelio Fabro (1939) and Louis Geiger (1942).

  2. It goes without saying, of course, that the analytical Thomist benefits enormously from sound historical work on Aquinas and his contemporaries. Analytical Thomism is therefore in no way hostile to the historico-expository approach to Aquinas. But history is not philosophy.

  3. For an extended discussion of this version of analytical Thomism see Haldane (1997) and Paterson and Pugh (2006).

  4. For detracting voices see the contributions of Brian Shanley, Stephen Theron, and John Knasas in Paterson and Pugh (2006).

  5. This is no small achievement. Following Leo XIII’s encyclical Aeterni Patris, numerous philosophically unsophisticated manuals summarising the work of Aquinas were produced for use in seminars. These works did much to re-enforce the widespread prejudice that there is little of philosophical value to be found in the Scholastics.

  6. For a particularly forthright rejection of the use of Fregean logical syntax in metaphysics see E.J. Lowe’s (2012). Fred Sommer’s (1982) revitalisation of traditional logic and accompanying critique of Frege has done much to remove the shine from the Fregean revolution. For extended discussion of Sommer’s counter-revolution see Oderberg (2005).

  7. Consider the projects of Dummett, Kripke, Rawls, Armstrong, Derrida, Levinas and Habermas, leading figures of the second half of the 20th century.

  8. For extended discussion see Stephen Boulter’s (2013) “The Aporetic Method and the Defence of Immodest Metaphysics”.

  9. See Jack Wilson’s (1999) for a recent book length treatment of biological individuality that begins by recognising the practical difficulty. For early discussions of the concept of the biological individual see T.H Huxley’s (1852), J. Huxley’s (1912), and E. Haechel’s (1979). For recent work suggesting that a grasp of the notion of the biological individual is absolutely essential to the viability of evolutionary theory, and that such a grasp is currently lacking, see Pepper and Heron (2008) and Ruiz-Mirazo et al. (2000).

  10. As Hull says, “If selection is a process of differential perpetuation of the units of selection, and if organisms are the primary focus of selection, then we’d better know which entities we are to count” (2001, 17). Of course there are those who champion the gene as the basic unit of selection, and others who, while recognising the individual organism as one unit of selection, wish to add others such as the group or species. But both accept that the organism plays a key role in any account of selection. Groups are obviously made up of individual organisms, and genes are subject to selection indirectly through direct pressures brought to bear upon their interactors, i.e., the organism they use to replicate themselves.

  11. “What the ecologist, as population biologist, studies is the density of a population (number of individuals per unit area), the rate of increase (or decrease) of such a population under varying conditions, and, when dealing with the populations of a single species, all those parameters that control the size of the population such as birth rate, life expectancy, mortality, and so on” (Ernst Mayr, 1997, 210–11).

  12. We are standardly told that “…the fitness of a trait depends on the proportion of the individuals in a population that have that trait” (Sterelny and Griffiths 1999, 8). Similarly, “… difference in survival is expressed … by a parameter, assigned to each genotype, called relative fitness, a number that represents the fraction of the individuals of a given genotype that survives to adulthood and reproduction” (Stearns and Hoekstra 2005, 76).

  13. “In contemporary evolutionary biology an ‘adaptation’ is a characteristic of an organism whose form is a result of selection in a particular functional context” (West-Eberhard 1998, 8).

  14. The need to sure that we are comparing ‘apples with apples’ when employing the comparative method is part of the case Pepper and Heron (2008) make for the indispensability of an account of biological individuality to evolutionary theory.

  15. This paragraph is heavily indebted to Wilson (1999, 6–7).

  16. Space considerations make an examination of the strengths and weaknesses of these criteria impossible. But for extended discussion of the attending difficulties see Ellen Clarke’s (2010) “The Problem of Biological Individuality”, in Biological Theory.

  17. A typical example of the principle at work can be found in Summa Theologiae (1988) I, q. 75, a 2. “Nihil autem potest per se operari, nisi quod per se subsistit. Non enim est operari nisi entis in actu: unde eo modo aliquid operator, quo est.” “Now only that which subsists in itself can have an operation in itself. For nothing can operate but what is actual, and so a thing operates according as it is.” English translation by Pegis (1997). This is reaffirmed in Quaestio Disputata de Anima: “everything that exists in its own right has its own activity” (in Aquinas 2008, p. 184).

  18. Another significant difference is that the Thomist account suggests that the term ‘individual’ is analogical. There is a focal sense of ‘individual’ which attaches to the individual per se, viz., the independent agent; and then there are various analogically related senses of ‘individual’ that apply to agents who do not have this sort of independent activity. Recognising analogical senses of key terms frees one from an error of the analytic tradition, namely, insisting that all non-defective concepts are univocal, and thus have a set of necessary and sufficient conditions that apply to all legitimate applications of the term.

  19. The plausibility of linking individuals to actions and operations can be re-enforced by other considerations as well. (1) The focus on action and operation is itself sensible because we do not live in a frozen world. Because change is a real feature of the world we inhabit, and change is primarily brought about by the actions of individuals, it is no surprise that our notion of the individual per se is closely connected to that of action. (2) Linking individuals to actions also delivers a common sense response to the discussion of mereological sums. There is good reason to consider an apple, say, to be a real entity above and beyond the atoms that make it up because there are actions associated with the apple that cannot be attributed to the atoms in and of themselves. Similarly, we do not usually consider an apple and a pear to constitute three objects (the apple, the pear and the apple/pear composite) but only two because there are no actions associated with the apple/pear composite. (3) Tying individuals to action also allows one to side-step Unger’s sorties paradox of composition as applied to biological entities. Unger (2009) argues that the following three propositions are inconsistent: (a) Organisms exists; (b) Organisms consist of a finite number of cells; (c) If organisms exists, then the net removal of one cell, or only a few, will not mean the difference as to whether the organism exists. Unger suggests that all three propositions are irresistible. But since they are incompatible at least one of them must be false. Unger suggests that the most vulnerable proposition is (a), and so he concludes that composite entities like organisms do not exist, even at the expense of saying that he must now deny his own existence. But surely it is more reasonable to deny (b) or (c) on the basis of the Thomist analysis of the biological individual as an independent agent.

  20. Mitochondia lost the capacity to photosynthesize, while chloroplasts lost respiration.

  21. See Stearns and Hoesktra, ch. 15, for extended discussion.

References

  • Aquinas, T. (1988). Summa Theologiae. Edizioni San Paolo.

  • Aquinas, T. (1997). In A. Pegis (Ed.), Basic Writings of Saint Thomas. Vol. One. (trans: Pegis, A.). Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

  • Aquinas, T. (2008). In McDermott (Ed.), Aquinas: Selected Writings. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boulter, S. (2013). The aporetic method and the defence of immodest metaphysics. In E. Feser (Ed.), Aristotle on Method and Metaphysics, Houndsmill: Palgrave Macmillan.

  • Clarke, E. (2010). The Problem of Biological Individuality. Biological Theory, 5(4), 312–325.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Wulf, M. (1903). Scholasticism Old and New: An Introduction to Scholastic Philosophy Medieval and Modern. Dublin: Gill & Son.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fabro, C. (1939). The metaphysical notion of participation according to St. Thomas Aquinas. Turin: Edizioni Scientifiche Italiane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geiger, L. (1942). In J. Vrin (Ed.), La participation dans la philosophie de St. Thomas d’Aquin.

  • Gilson, E. (1952). Being and Some Philosophers. Toronto: The Pontifical Institute for Medieval Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haechel, E. (1979). Das System der Medusen. Jena: Gustav Fischer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haldane, J. (1997). In J. Haldane (Ed.), Analytical Thomism, The Monist, Vol. 80, No. 4, October 1997.

  • Hull, D. (2001). Science and Selection: essays on biological evolution and the philosophy of science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huxley, T. H. (1852). Upon Animal Individuality. In Proceedings of the Royal Institute (April 30, 184–89).

  • Huxley, J. (1912). The Individual in the Animal Kingdom. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, J. (2012). Categorial predication. Ratio, 25(4), 369–386.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marechal, J. (1922–47). Le point de départ de la métaphysique. (5 Cahiers) Bruges-Louvain.

  • Maritain, J. (1959). Three Degrees of Knowledge. New York: Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. (1997). This is Biology. London: Belnap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oderberg, D. (2005). The Old New Logic. London: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Owens, J. (1951). The doctrine of being in the Aristotelian metaphysics: a study in the Greek background of medieval thought. Toronto: The Pontifical Institute for Medieval Studies.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paterson, C., & Pugh, M. (2006). Analytical Thomism: Traditions in Dialogue. Aldershot: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pepper, J., & Heron, M. (2008). Does biology need an organism concept? Biological Reviews, 83(4), 621–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rousselot, P. (1935). The Intellectualism of Saint Thomas. New York: Sheed and Ward.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruiz-Mirazo, K., et al. (2000). Organisms and their place in biology. Theory in Biosciences, 119(3), 209–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sommers, F. (1982). The Logic of Natural Language (p. 1982). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stearns, S., & Hoekstra, R. (2005). Evolution: An Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sterelny, K., & Griffiths, P. (1999). Sex and Death. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suarez, F. (1982). Metaphysical Disputation V: Individual Unity and its Principle. (trans: Gracia, J.). Milwaukee: Marquette University Press.

  • Unger, P. (2009). I do not exist. In M. Rea (Ed.), Arguing About Metaphysics (pp. 94–105). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard, M. J. (1998). Adaptation: Current Usages. In Hull & Ruse (Eds.), The Philosophy of Biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, J. (1999). Biological Individuality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wippel, J. (2000). The Metaphysical Thought of Thomas Aquinas. Washington D.C: The Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wojtyla, K. (1979). The Acting Person. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Stephen Boulter.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Boulter, S. Aquinas on Biological Individuals: An Essay in Analytical Thomism. Philosophia 41, 603–616 (2013). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-013-9482-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11406-013-9482-x

Keywords

Navigation