Skip to main content
Log in

A Difference of Some Consequence Between Conventions and Rules

  • Published:
Topoi Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Lewis’s view of the way conventions are passed on may have some especially interesting consequences for the study of language. I’ll start by briefly discussing agreements and disagreements that I have with Lewis’s general views on conventions and then turn to how linguistic conventions spread. I’ll compare views of main stream generative linguistics, in particular, Chomsky’s views on how syntactic forms are passed on, with the sort of view of language acquisition and language change advocated by usage-based or construction grammars, which seem to fit better with Lewis’s ideas. Then I will illustrate the interest of Lewis’s perspective on the dissemination of conventions with a variety of linguistic examples.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This essay was written from the perspective of the American northeast where only the tradition of generative grammar is clearly visible. I am grateful to William Croft, one of the referees, for pointing me to a number of references from outside that contain data and arguments supporting various of my points. I have now cited several of the most pertinent readings that Croft suggested, but I have retained my primary emphasis on very recent writings by Jackendoff, Culicover and Pinker as major spokesmen for a departure from the central generative tradition. It should be evident that these people, at least, could not possibly have simply failed to understand the force of the generative tradition. My bibliography contains a number of references supplied by Croft that I do not cite but that may be of use to others who would like to explore the territory into which I am venturing here.

  2. I will not be trying to prove, of course, that various phenomena I describe cannot possibly be accounted for within a generative grammar perspective. My purpose is only to illustrate the interest of Lewis's idea that conventions are essentially subject to indeterminacy in interpretation.

  3. Including, for example, Searle 1969; Schiffer 1972; Bach and Harnish 1979; Gilbert 1983, 1989/1992; Recanati 1987.

  4. Clark (1996), Croft (2000).

  5. Millikan (1984, Chap. 3, 2004 chaps. 9–12, 2005, Chaps. 8–10).

  6. This is the major premise of those who advocate “usage-based” grammars, for example, Tomasello (2003), Croft and Cruse (2004).

  7. For example, Fillmore (1988), Heine et al. (1991), Fillmore and Kay (1993), Zwicky (1994), Goldberg (1995), Dubrowska (1997), Hopper and Traugott (2003), Tomasello (2003), Croft and Cruze (2004), Culicover and Jackendoff (2003).

  8. These examples are adapted from Jackendoff (2002, Chap. 6).

  9. Compare Croft (2000, p. 26).

  10. From a public lecture Hoffstader gave at Stanford University in 1991.

  11. See, for example, Morgan (1978).

  12. From Snyder (2000), Hiramatsu (2000). See also Debrowska (1997).

  13. For more discussion here, see Millikan (1984, Chap. 4).

  14. “‘When I use a word,’ Humpty Dumpty said, in rather a scornful tone, ‘it means just what I choose it to mean—neither more nor less.”’ Lewis Carroll, Through the Looking Glass

  15. As for what the person calling me “Hillary Clinton” means (rather than says), that is indeterminate too; having crossed some wires, she means two persons at once (Millikan 2000).

  16. This equivocation occurs, I believe, in the Korta and Perry quotation with which I began this section and, indeed, permeates much of the literature in pragmatics.

  17. See Millikan (1984, Chap. 4; 2005, Chaps. 2–3).

  18. He keyed the car has recently come to mean that he took his key and maliciously scratched the finish of the car.

  19. Clark and Clark (1979) compiled a list of denominal verbs that included more than 400 documented examples which they considered to be “innovations,” including He enfant terrible'd gracefully, to stif-upper—lip it through, to bargain—counter the Bible, She Houdinied her way out of the closet, and so forth. They propose that the use of these innovative denominals “is regulated by a convention: in using such a verb, the speaker means to denote the kind of state, event, or process that, he has good reason to believe, the listener can readily and uniquely compute on this occasion, on the basis of their mutual knowledge, …” and so forth. Rules, rules, even here there are supposed to be rules! In exactly what medium are they written?

  20. For example, in Recanati (2007a, b).

References

  • Bach K, Harnish RM (1979) Linguistic communication and speech acts. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloom P (2000) How children learn the meanings of words. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (1965) Aspects of the theory of syntax. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (1980) Rules and representations. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky N (1986) Knowledge of language, its nature origin and use. Praeger, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark HH (1996) Using language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark EV, Clark HH (1979) When nouns surface as verbs. Language 55:767–811

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Croft W (2000) Explaining language change: an evolutionary approach. Longman, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Croft W, Cruse DA (2004) Cognitive linguistics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Culicover PW (1999) The view from the periphery: the English comparative correlative. Linguist Inq 30:543–571

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Culicover PW, Jackendoff R (2003) Simpler syntax. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Culicover PW, Nowak A (2003) Dynamical grammar. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Davis S (1991) Pragmatics; a reader. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins R (1976) The selfish gene. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Debrowska E (1997) The lad goes to school: a cautionary tale for nativists. Linguistics 35:735–766

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fillmore CJ (1988) The mechanisms of construction grammar. Berkley Linguist Soc 14:35–55

    Google Scholar 

  • Fillmore CJ, Kay P (1993) Construction grammar coursebook. Copy Central, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Fillmore CJ, Kay P, O’Connor MC (1988) Regularity and idiomaticity in grammatical constructions: the case of let alone. Language 64:501–538

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert M (1983) Agreements, conventions, and language. Synthese 54:375–407

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert M (1989/1992) On social facts. Princeton University Press, Princeton. Reprinted from Routledge 1989 edn

  • Goldberg AE (1995) Constructions: a construction grammar approach to argument structure. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Heine B, Claudi U, Hünnemeyer F (1991) Grammaticalization: a conceptual framework. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Hiramatsu K (2000) Competence vs. performance: evidence from children’s and adults’ grammaticality judgments, unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, University of Connecticut, Storrs

  • Hopper P, Traugott E (2003) Grammaticalization, 2nd edn. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

  • Jackendoff R (2002) Foundations of language; brain, meaning, grammar, evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff R, Pinker S (2005) The nature of the language faculty and its implications for evolution of language. Cognition 97(2):211–225

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • James W (1968) Pragmatism. Selection reprinted In: McDermott JJ (ed) The writings of William James. Random House, New York, pp 376–377

  • Kaplan D (1989) Demonstratives. In: Almog J, Perry J, Wettstein H (eds) Themes from Kaplan. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 481–564

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1969) Convention: a philosophical study. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis D (1975) Languages and language. In: Gunderson K (eds) Language, mind and knowledge. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp 3–35. Reprinted in Martinich AP (ed) (2001) The philosophy of language. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 562–580

  • Millikan R (1984) Language, thought, and other biological categories. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (1998) In defense of public language. In: Antony L, Hornstein N (eds) Chomsky and his critics. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 215–237. Also in Millikan 2005

  • Millikan R (2003) Language conventions made simple. J Philos XCV(4):161–180. Also in Millikan 2005

  • Millikan R (2004) Varieties of meaning; the Jean Nicod Lectures 2002. The MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan R (2005) Language: a biological model. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgan JL (1978) Two types of convention in indirect speech acts. In: Cole P (ed) Syntax and semantics, vol 9: Pragmatics. Academic Press, pp 261–280. Reprinted in Davis 1991, pp 242–253

  • Perry J (1986) Thought without representation. In: Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, suppl vol 60, pp 137–151. Reprinted in Perry 1993, pp 219–225

  • Perry J (1993) The problem of the essential indexical and other essays. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker S (2000) Words and rules; the ingredients of language. Perennial, imprint of Harper Collins Publishers

  • Recanati F (1987) Meaning and force; the pragmatics of performative utterances. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Recanati F (2007a) Millikan’s theory of signs. Philos Phenomenol Res 75(3):674–681

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Recanati F (2007b) Perspectival thought: a plea for moderate relativism. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts I (1985) Agreement parameters in the development of English modal auxiliaries. Nat Lang Linguist Theory 3:21–58

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts I, Roussou A (2003) A minimalist approach to grammaticalization. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Schiffer S (1972) Meaning. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1969) Speech acts; an essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle J (1983) Intentionality: an essay in the philosophy of mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Snyder W (2000) An experimental investigation of syntactic satiation effects. Linguist Inq 31:575–582

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (2000) Do young children have adult syntactic competence? Cognition 74:209–253

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello M (2003) Constructing a language: a usage-based theory of language acquisition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwicky A (1994) Dealing out meaning: fundamentals of syntatic construction. Berkeley Linguist Soc 20:611–625

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ruth Garrett Millikan.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Millikan, R.G. A Difference of Some Consequence Between Conventions and Rules. Topoi 27, 87–99 (2008). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-008-9026-3

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11245-008-9026-3

Keywords

Navigation