Skip to main content
Log in

Robust realism for the life sciences

  • Published:
Synthese Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Although scientific realism is the default position in the life sciences, philosophical accounts of realism are geared towards physics and run into trouble when applied to fields such as biology or neuroscience. In this paper, I formulate a new robustness-based version of entity realism, and show that it provides a plausible account of realism for the life sciences that is also continuous with scientific practice. It is based on the idea that if there are several independent ways of measuring, detecting or deriving something, then we are justified in believing that it is real. I also consider several possible objections to robustness-based entity realism, discuss its relationship to ontic structural realism, and show how it has the potential to provide a novel response to the pessimistic induction argument.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The exact structure of Cartwright’s original argument is not clear. For an overview of different interpretations and their problems, see Hitchcock (1992).

  2. Suárez (2008) and Egg (2012, 2016) defend entity realism by arguing that, when the right conditions are satisfied, causal explanation does give warrant for believing that the cause is real. This strategy is interesting, but I will not discuss it in detail here, as it leads to a form of entity realism that is not well suited for accounting for scientific realism in the life sciences—see Sect. 4 for more.

  3. This idea has also many other names, including triangulation, overdetermination, mutual grounding, diverse testing, argument from coincidence, and so on. Note also that this use of the term ’robustness’ should not be confused with the distantly related notion of ’robustness analysis’ that has been much discussed in the context of modeling (e.g., Weisberg 2006; Odenbaugh and Alexandrova 2011; Kuorikoski et al. 2012). See Calcott (2011) and Eronen (2015) for more on the differences between various notions of robustness.

  4. This can also be seen as a common cause argument: The independent pieces of evidence are explained by being due to a common cause, i.e., the robust entity or property (see, e.g., Salmon 1984). However, the account of robustness I offer below is more general and includes dimensions (e.g., derivability and explanatory role) that do not easily fit into the common cause framework.

  5. Strictly speaking, it would be more accurate to always write “robust evidence for X” instead of “X is robust”, but for the sake of readability, I also use the latter kinds of expressions here.

  6. For more discussion on robustness and independence, see Hudson (2014), Kuorikoski and Marchionni (2016), Schupbach (2016) and Stegenga (2009).

  7. However, many other aspects of the constructive empiricism of van Fraassen (1980) are in fact compatible with RER: For example, RER does not require accepting inference to the best explanation as valid for theories and explanations.

  8. The extent to which measuring a property (or believing in the reality of a property) requires belief in theories also depends on how broadly we understand ‘theory’. For more on the relationships between properties, theories and realism, see Chakravartty (2007, chap. 2–3).

  9. See Fahrbach (2011) for a different but complementary argument against pessimistic induction based on the exponential growth of science.

  10. Much of this section was written in response to insightful comments by two anonymous reviewers, for which I am very grateful.

  11. What this means for OSR is an open question that goes beyond the scope of this paper. It is possible, for example, that the ontological commitments that RER supports could somehow be translated to the objectless ontology of OSR (cf. Ladyman and Ross 2007), rendering the two compatible. On the other hand, it has also been argued that there is no need to expand OSR to the special sciences (Lyre 2013). Note also that even if it is true that there are no objects but only structure in the ontology of fundamental physics, this is not a threat to RER, as RER does not imply or require that only entities or properties exist, or that robustness is the only route to ontological commitments and justification (see Sect. 3).

References

  • Bornmann, L., & Rüdiger, M. (2015). Growth rates of modern science: A bibliometric analysis based on the number of publications and cited references. Journal of the Association for Information Science and Technology, 66, 2215–2222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briggman, K. L., & Bock, D. D. (2012). Volume electron microscopy for neuronal circuit reconstruction. Current Opinion in Neurobiology, 22, 154–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Calcott, B. (2011). Wimsatt and the robustness family: Review of Wimsatt’s re-engineering philosophy for limited beings. Biology & Philosophy, 26, 281–293.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1983). How the laws of physics lie. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. (2004). Inventing temperature: Measurement and scientific progress. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, S. (2001). Defensible territory for entity realism. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52, 701–722.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Devitt, M. (2005). Scientific realism. In F. Jackson & M. Smith (Eds.), The oxford handbook of contemporary philosophy (pp. 767–791). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Egg, M. (2012). Causal warrant for realism about particle physics. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 43, 259–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Egg, M. (2016). Expanding our grasp: Causal knowledge and the problem of unconceived alternatives. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 67, 115–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eronen, M. I. (2012). Pluralistic physicalism and the causal exclusion argument. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 2(2), 219–232.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eronen, M. I. (2015). Robustness and reality. Synthese, 192(12), 3961–3977.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fagan, M. B. (2013). The stem cell uncertainty principle. Philosophy of Science, 80, 945–957.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fahrbach, L. (2011). How the growth of science ends theory change. Synthese, 180, 139–155.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • French, S. (2011). Shifting to structures in physics and biology: A prophylactic for promiscuous realism. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 42, 164–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R., & Votsis, I. (2011). Everything you always wanted to know about structural realism but were afraid to ask. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 1, 227–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guillery, R. W. (2005). Observations of synaptic structures: Origins of the neuron doctrine and its current status. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 360, 1281–1307.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1981). Do we see through a microscope? Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 62, 305–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1982). Experimentation and scientific realism. Philosophical Topics, 13, 154–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1983). Representing and intervening. Introductory topics in the philosophy of natural science. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, C. (1992). Causal explanation and scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 37, 151–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hudson, R. (2014). Seeing things: The philosophy of reliable observation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolb, H. (2003). How the retina works. American Scientist, 91, 28–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolb, H. (2015). Roles of amacrine cells. Webvision. Moran Eye Center. http://webvision.med.utah.edu/book/part-iii-retinal-circuits/roles-of-amacrine-cells/. Accessed 20 Feb 2017.

  • Kuorikoski, J., & Marchionni, C. (2016). Evidential diversity and the triangulation of phenomena. Philosophy of Science, 83, 227–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuorikoski, J., Lehtinen, A., & Marchionni, C. (2012). Robustness analysis disclaimer: Please read the manual before use!. Biology & Philosophy, 27, 891–902.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J., & Ross, D. (2007). Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalised. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ladyman, J. (2014). Structural realism. In The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), ed. E. N. Zalta, http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/structural-realism/.

  • Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 19–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lichtman, J. W., Sanes, J. R., & Livet, J. (2008). A technicolour approach to the connectome. Nature Reviews Neuroscience, 9, 417.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyre, H. (2013). Must structural realism cover the special sciences? In V. Karakostas & D. Dieks (Eds.), EPSA11: Perspectives and foundational problems in philosophy of science (pp. 383–390). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Masland, R. H. (2012). The tasks of amacrine cells. Visual Neuroscience, 29, 3–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (1990). Theory, intervention and realism. Synthese, 82, 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Conaill, D. (2014). Ontic structural realism and concrete objects. Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 284–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Odenbaugh, J., & Alexandrova, A. (2011). Buyer beware: Robustness analyses in economics and biology. Biology & Philosophy, 26, 757–771.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Radder, H. (2012). The material realization of science. From habermas to experimentation and referential realism (revised edition, with a new postscript). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

  • Schupbach, J. (2016). Robustness analysis as explanatory reasoning. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science. doi:10.1093/bjps/axw008.

  • Soler, L., Trizio, E., Nickles, T., & Wimsatt, W. C. (Eds.). (2012). Characterizing the robustness of science: After the practice turn in the philosophy of science. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stegenga, J. (2009). Robustness, discordance, and relevance. Philosophy of Science, 76, 650–661.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2008). Experimental realism reconsidered: How inference to the most likely cause might be sound. In S. Hartmann, C. Hoefer, & L. Bovens (Eds.), Nancy Cartwright’s philosophy of science (pp. 137–163). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • van Fraassen, B. (1985). Empiricism in the philosophy of science. In Paul Churchland & Clifford Hooker (Eds.), Images of Science (pp. 245–308). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M. (2006). Robustness analysis. Philosophy of Science, 73, 730–742.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1981). Robustness, reliability, and overdetermination. In M. Brewer & B. Collins (Eds.), Scientific inquiry and the social sciences (pp. 124–163). San Fransisco: Jossey-Bass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (1994). The ontology of complex systems: Levels of organization, perspectives, and causal thickets. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, S20, 207–274.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wimsatt, W. C. (2007). Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings. Piecewise approximations to reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeilinger, A. (2005). The message of the quantum. Nature, 438, 743.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I thank Laura Bringmann, Daniel Brooks and Leah Henderson for very helpful critical comments on earlier drafts of the paper. I am also grateful to two anonymous referees, and the audiences at Philosophy of Science in a Forest 2016 (Utrecht), PSA 2016 (Atlanta) and OZSW 2016 (Groningen), for their constructive feedback. The research that led to this paper was generously funded by Fonds Wetenschappelijk Onderzoek (Grant No. 102627).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Markus I. Eronen.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Eronen, M.I. Robust realism for the life sciences. Synthese 196, 2341–2354 (2019). https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1542-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-017-1542-5

Keywords

Navigation